"Aut prodesse volunt aut delectare poetæ."[80]
"Aut prodesse volunt aut delectare poetæ."[80]
This line suggests that the function of poetry may be to please, or to instruct, or both to please and instruct; and every one of the writers of the Renaissance takes one or other of these three positions. Aristotle, as we know, regarded poetry as an imitation of human life, for the purpose of giving a certain refined pleasure to the reader or hearer. "The end of the fine arts is to give pleasure (πρὸς ἡδονήν), or rational enjoyment (πρὸς διαγωγήν)."[81]It has already been said that poetry, in so far as it is an imitation of human life, andattempts to be true to human life in its ideal aspects, must fundamentally be moral; but to give moral or scientific instruction is in no way the end or function of poetry. It will be seen that the Renaissance was in closer accord with Horace than with Aristotle, in requiring for the most part theutileas well as thedulcein poetry.
For Daniello, one of the earliest critical writers of the century, the function of the poet is to teach and delight. As the aim of the orator is to persuade, and the aim of the physician to cure, so the aim of the poet is equally to teach and delight; and unless he teaches and delights he cannot be called a poet, even as one who does not persuade cannot be called an orator, or one who does not cure, a physician.[82]But beyond profitableness and beauty, the poet must carry with him a certain persuasion, which is one of the highest functions of poetry, and which consists in moving and affecting the reader or hearer with the very passions depicted; but the poet must be moved first, before he can move others.[83]Here Daniello is renewing Horace's
"Si vis me flere, dolendum estPrimum ipsi tibi,"—
"Si vis me flere, dolendum estPrimum ipsi tibi,"—
a sentiment echoed by poets as different as Vauquelin, Boileau, and Lamartine.
Fracastoro, however, attempts a deeper analysis of the proper function of the poetic art. What is the aim of the poet? Not merely to give delight, for the fields, the stars, men and women,the objects of poetic imitation themselves do that; and poetry, if it did no more, could not be said to have any reason for existing. Nor is it merely to teach and delight, as Horace says; for the descriptions of countries, peoples, and armies, the scientific digressions and the historical events, which constitute the instructive side of poetry, are derived from cosmographers, scientists, and historians, who teach and delight as much as poets do. What, then, is the function of the poet? It is, as has already been pointed out, to describe the essential beauty of things, to aim at the universal and ideal, and to perform this function with every possible accompaniment of beautiful speech, thus affecting the minds of men in the direction of excellence and beauty. Portions of Fracastoro's argument have been alluded to before, and it will suffice here to state his own summing up of the aim of the poet, which is this,"Delectare et prodesse imitando in unoquoque maxima et pulcherrima per genus dicendi simpliciter pulchrum ex convenientibus."[84]This is a mingling of the Horatian and Platonic conceptions of poetic art.
By other critics a more practical function was given to poetry. Giraldi Cintio asserts that it is the poet's aim to condemn vice and to praise virtue, and Maggi says that poets aim almost exclusively at benefiting the mind. Poets who, on the contrary, treat of obscene matters for the corruption of youth, may be compared with infamous physicians who give their patients deadly poisonin the guise of wholesome medicine. Horace and Aristotle, according to Maggi, are at one on this point, for in the definition of tragedy Aristotle ascribes to it a distinctly useful purpose, and whatever delight is obtainable is to be regarded as a result of this moral function; for Maggi and the Renaissance critics in general would follow the Elizabethan poet who speaks of "delight, the fruit of virtue dearly loved." Muzio, in his versifiedArte Poetica(1555), regards the end of poetry as pleasure and profit, and the pleasurable aim of poetry as attained by variety, for the greatest poems contain every phase of life and art.
It has been seen that Varchi classed poetry with rational philosophy. The end of all arts and sciences is to make human life perfect and happy; but they differ in their modes of producing this result. Philosophy attains its end by teaching; rhetoric, by persuasion; history, by narration; poetry, by imitation or representation. The aim of the poet, therefore, is to make the human soul perfect and happy, and it is his office to imitate, that is, to invent and represent, things which render men virtuous, and consequently happy. Poetry attains this end more perfectly than any of the other arts or sciences, because it does so, not by means of precept, but by means of example. There are various ways of making men virtuous,—by teaching them what vice is and what virtue is, which is the province of ethics; by actually chastising vices and rewarding virtues, which is the province of law; or by example, that is, by therepresentation of virtuous men receiving suitable rewards for their virtue, and of vicious men receiving suitable punishments, which is the province of poetry. This last method is the most efficacious, because it is accompanied by delight. For men either can not or will not take the trouble to study sciences and virtues—nay, do not even like to be told what they should or should not do; but in hearing or reading poetic examples, not only is there no trouble, but there is the greatest delight, and no one can help being moved by the representation of characters who are rewarded or punished according to an ideal justice.
For Varchi, then, as for Sir Philip Sidney later, the high importance of poetry is to be found in the fact that it teaches morality better than any other art, and the reason is that its instrument is not precept but example, which is the most delightful and hence the most efficacious of all means. The function of poetry is, therefore, a moral one, and it consists in removing the vices of men and inciting them to virtue. This twofold moral object of poetry—the removal of vices, which is passive, and the incitement to virtue, which is active—is admirably attained, for example, by Dante in hisDivina Commedia; for in theInfernoevil men are so fearfully punished that we resolve to flee from every form of vice, and in theParadisovirtuous men are so gloriously rewarded that we resolve to imitate every one of their perfections. This is the expression of the extreme view of poetic justice; and while it is in keeping with the common sentimentof the Renaissance, it is of course entirely un-Aristotelian.
Scaliger's point of view is in accord with the common Renaissance tradition. Poetry is imitation, but imitation is not the end of poetry. Imitation for its own sake—that is, art for art's sake—receives no encouragement from Scaliger. The purpose of poetry is to teach delightfully (docere cum delectatione); and, therefore, not imitation, as Aristotle says, but delightful instruction, is the test of poetry.[85]Minturno (1559) adds a third element to that of instruction and of delight.[86]The function of poetry is not only to teach and delight, but also to move, that is, beyond instruction and delight the poet must impel certain passions in the reader or hearer, and incite the mind to admiration of what is described.[87]An ideal hero may be represented in a poem, but the poem is futile unless it excites the reader to admiration of the hero depicted. Accordingly, it is the peculiar office of the poet to move admiration for great men; for the orator, the philosopher, and the historian need not necessarily do so, but no one who does not incite this admiration can really be called a poet.
This new element of admiration is the logical consequence of the Renaissance position that philosophy teaches by precept, but poetry by example, and that in this consists its superior ethical efficacy. In Seneca's phrase,"longum iter per præcepta,breve per exempla." If poetry, therefore, attains its end by means of example, it follows that to arrive at this end the poet must incite in the reader an admiration of the example, or the ethical aim of poetry will not be accomplished. Poetry is more than a mere passive expression of truth in the most pleasurable manner; it becomes like oratory an active exhortation to virtue, by attempting to create in the reader's mind a strong desire to be like the heroes he is reading about. The poet does not tell what vices are to be avoided and what virtues are to be imitated, but sets before the reader or hearer the most perfect types of the various virtues and vices. It is, in Sidney's phrase (a phrase apparently borrowed from Minturno), "that feigning notable images of virtues, vices, or what else, with that delightful instruction, which must be the right describing note to know a poet by." Dryden, a century later, seems to be insisting upon this same principle of admiration when he says that it is the work of the poet "to affect the soul, and excite the passions, and above all to move admiration, which is the delight of serious plays."[88]
But Minturno goes even further than this. If the poet is fundamentally a teacher of virtue, it follows that he must be a virtuous man himself; and in pointing this out, Minturno has given the first complete expression in modern times of the consecrated conception of the poet's office. As no form of knowledge and no moral excellence is foreign to the poet, so at bottom he is the truly wiseand good man. The poet may, in fact, be defined as a good man skilled in language and imitation; not only ought he to be a good man, but no one will be a good poet unless he is so.[89]This conception of the moral nature of the poet may be traced henceforth throughout modern times. It is to be found in Ronsard[90]and other French and Italian writers; it is especially noticeable in English literature, and is insisted on by Ben Jonson,[91]Milton,[92]Shaftesbury,[93]Coleridge,[94]and Shelley.[95]In this idea Plato's praise of the philosopher, as well as Cicero's and Quintilian's praise of the orator, was by the Renaissance transferred to the poet;[96]but the conception itself goes back to a passage in Strabo'sGeography, a work well known to sixteenth-century scholars. This passage is as follows:—
"Can we possibly imagine that the genius, power, and excellence of a real poet consist in aught else than the just imitation of life in formed discourse and numbers? But how should he be that just imitator of life, whilst he himself knows not its measures, nor how to guide himself by judgment and understanding? For we have not surely the same notion of the poet's excellence as of the ordinary craftsman's, the subject of whose art is senseless stone or timber,without life, dignity, or beauty; whilst the poet's art turning principally on men and manners, he has his virtues and excellence as poet naturally annexed to human excellence, and to the worth and dignity of man, insomuch that it is impossible he should be a great and worthy poet who is not first a worthy and good man."[97]
"Can we possibly imagine that the genius, power, and excellence of a real poet consist in aught else than the just imitation of life in formed discourse and numbers? But how should he be that just imitator of life, whilst he himself knows not its measures, nor how to guide himself by judgment and understanding? For we have not surely the same notion of the poet's excellence as of the ordinary craftsman's, the subject of whose art is senseless stone or timber,without life, dignity, or beauty; whilst the poet's art turning principally on men and manners, he has his virtues and excellence as poet naturally annexed to human excellence, and to the worth and dignity of man, insomuch that it is impossible he should be a great and worthy poet who is not first a worthy and good man."[97]
Another writer of the sixteenth century, Bernardo Tasso, tells us that in his poem of theAmadigihe has aimed at delight rather than profitable instruction.[98]"I have spent most of my efforts," he says, "in attempting to please, as it seems to me that this is more necessary, and also more difficult to attain; for we find by experience that many poets may instruct and benefit us very much, but certainly give us very little delight." This agrees with what one of the sanest of English critics, John Dryden (1668), has said of verse, "I am satisfied if it caused delight, for delight is the chief if not the only end of poesie; instruction can be admitted but in the second place, for poesie only instructs as it delights."[99]
It is this same end which Castelvetro (1570) ascribes to poetic art. For Castelvetro, as in a lesser degree for Robortelli also, the end of poetry is delight, and delight alone.[100]This, he asserts, is the position of Aristotle, and if utility is to be conceded to poetry at all, it is merely as an accident, as in the tragic purgation of terror and compassion.[101]But he goes further than Aristotle would have been willing to go; for poetry, according to Castelvetro, is intended not merely to please, but to please the populace, in fact everybody, even the vulgar mob.[102]On this he insists throughout his commentary; indeed, as will be seen later, it is on this conception that his theory of the drama is primarily based. But it may be confidently asserted that Aristotle would have willingly echoed the conclusion of Shakespeare, as expressed inHamlet, that the censure of one of the judicious must o'erweigh a whole theatre of others. At the same time, Castelvetro's conception is in keeping with a certain modern feeling in regard to the meaning of poetic art. Thus a recent writer regards literature as aiming "at the pleasure of the greatest possible number of the nation rather than instruction and practical effects," and as applying "to general rather than specialized knowledge."[103]There is, then, in Castelvetro's argument this modicum of truth, that poetry appeals to no specialized knowledge, but that its function is, as Coleridge says, to give a definite and immediate pleasure.
Torquato Tasso, as might be expected, regards poetry in a more highly ideal sense. His conception of the function of poets and of the poetic art may be explained as follows: The universe is beautiful in itself, because beauty is a ray from the Divine splendor; and hence art should seek to approach as closely as possible to nature, and to catch andexpress this natural beauty of the world.[104]Real beauty, however, is not so called because of any usefulness it may possess, but is primarily beautiful in itself; for the beautiful is what pleases every one, just as the good is what every one desires.[105]Beauty is therefore the flower of the good (quasi un fiore del buono); it is the circumference of the circle of which the good is the centre, and accordingly, poetry, as an expression of this beauty, imitates the outward show of life in its general aspects. Poetry is therefore an imitation of human actions, made for the guidance of life; and its end is delight,ordinato al giovamento.[106]It must essentially delight, either because delight is its aim, or because delight is the necessary means of effecting the ethical end of art.[107]Thus, for example, heroic poetry consists of imitation and allegory, the function of the former being to cause delight, and that of the latter to give instruction and guidance in life. But since difficult or obscure conceits rarely delight, and since the poet does not appeal to the learned only, but to the people, just as the orator does, the poet's idea must be, if not popular in the ordinary sense of the word, at least intelligible to the people. Now the people will not study difficult problems; but poetry, by appealing to them on the side of pleasure, teaches them whether they will or no; and this constitutes the true effectiveness of poetry, for it is the most delightful, and hence the most valuable, of teachers.[108]
Such, then, are the various conceptions of the function of poetry, as held by the critics of the Renaissance. On the whole, it may be said that at bottom the conception was an ethical one, for, with the exception of such a revolutionary spirit as Castelvetro, by most theorists it was as an effective guide to life that poetry was chiefly valued. Even when delight was admitted as an end, it was simply because of its usefulness in effecting the ethical aim.
In concluding this chapter, it may be well to say a few words, and only a few, upon the classification of poetic forms. There were during the Renaissance numerous attempts at distinguishing these forms, but on the whole all of them are fundamentally equivalent to that of Minturno, who recognizes threegenres,—the lyric or melic, the dramatic or scenic, and the epic or narrative. This classification is essentially that of the Greeks, and it has lasted down to this very day. With lyric poetry this essay is scarcely concerned, for during the Renaissance there was no systematic lyric theory. Those who discussed it at all gave most of their attention to its formal structure, its style, and especially the conceit it contained. The model of all lyrical poetry was Petrarch, and it was in accordance with the lyrical poet's agreement or disagreement with the Petrarchan method that he was regarded as a success or a failure. Muzio's critical poem (1551) deals almost entirely with lyrical verse, and there are discussions on this subject in the works of Trissino, Equicola, Ruscelli,Scaliger, and Minturno. But the real question at issue in all these discussions is merely that of external form, and it is with the question of principles, in so far as they regard literary criticism, that this essay is primarily concerned. The theory of dramatic and epic poetry, being fundamental, will therefore receive almost exclusive attention.
top
FOOT-NOTES:[40]Robortelli, p. 1sq.[41]This analysis of Zabarella,Opera Logica, De Natura Logicæ, ii. 13-23, I owe to the kindness of Professor Butcher of Edinburgh. Zabarella probably derived his knowledge of Aristotle'sPoeticsfrom Robortelli, under whom he studied Greek.Cf.Bayle,Dict.s. v. Zabarella.[42]Maggi, p. 28sq.Cf.B. Tasso,Lettere, ii. 514; Scaliger,Poet.i. 2; Castelvetro,Poetica, p. 7; Salviati, Cod. Magliabech. ii. ii. 11, fol. 384 v.; B. Jonson,Timber, p. 74.[43]Daniello, p. 41sq.[44]Robortelli, p. 86sq.[45]Robortelli, p. 90sq.[46]Fracastoro, i. 340.[47]Fracastoro, i. 357sq.[48]Poet.vi. 2.[49]Varchi, p. 578.[50]E.g.Piccolomini, p. 27sq.[51]Tiraboschi, vii. 1331.[52]Summo, pp. 61-69.[53]Poet.iii. 95.[54]Poet.i. 1.[55]Another critic of the time, Vettori, 1560, pp. 14, 93, attacks poetic prose on the ground that in Aristotle's definition of the various poetic forms, verse is always spoken of as an essential part. It is interesting to note that the phrase "poetic prose" is used, perhaps for the first time, in Minturno,Arte Poetica, 1564, p. 3, etc.[56]Opere, x. 254.Cf.Minturno,Arte Poetica, p. 33.[57]Poet.iii. 96.[58]Muzio, p. 69.[59]Giraldi Cintio, i. 61.[60]Art Poét.iii. 50.Cf.Horace,Ars Poet.188.[61]Zodiac. Vitæ, i. 143.[62]Butcher, pp. 117, 118.[63]Poet.i. 8.[64]Fracastoro, i. 335sq.[65]Cf.Castelvetro,Poetica, p. 27sq.[66]Rhet.i. 11.[67]Cf.A. Segni, 1581, cap. i.[68]Varchi, p. 227sq.[69]Capriano, cap. ii.[70]Lionardi, p. 43sq.[71]Lettere, ii. 525.[72]Scaliger,Poet.i. 2.[73]Defense, pp. 10, 11.[74]De Poeta, p. 53sq.[75]Castelvetro,Poetica, p. 23sq.[76]Ibid.p. 190.[77]Cf.T. Tasso, xi. 51.[78]Poetica, p. 158.[79]Poetica, p. 191.[80]Ars Poet.333.[81]Butcher, p. 185.[82]Daniello, p. 25.[83]Ibid.p. 40.[84]Fracastoro, i. 363.[85]Scaliger,Poet.vi. ii. 2.[86]De Poeta, p. 102.Cf.Scaliger,Poet.iii. 96.[87]De Poeta, p. 11.[88]Essay of Dramatic Poesy, p. 104.[89]De Poeta, p. 79.[90]Œuvres, vii. 318.[91]Works, i. 333.[92]Prose Works, iii. 118.[93]Characteristicks, 1711, i. 207.[94]H. C. Robinson,Diary, May 29, 1812, "Coleridge talked of the impossibility of being a good poet without being a good man."[95]Defence of Poetry, p. 42.[96]Minturno plainly says as much,De Poeta, p. 105.[97]Geog.i. ii. 5, as cited by Shaftesbury.[98]Lettere, ii. 195.[99]Essay of Dramatic Poesy, p. 104.[100]Cf.Piccolomini, p. 369.[101]Castelvetro,Poetica, p. 505.Cf.Twining, ii. 449, 450.[102]Poetica, p. 29.[103]Posnett, cited by Cook, p. 247.[104]Opere, viii. 26sq.[105]Ibid.ix. 123.[106]Ibid.xii. 13.[107]Ibid.xi. 50.[108]Ibid.xii. 212.
[40]Robortelli, p. 1sq.
[40]Robortelli, p. 1sq.
[41]This analysis of Zabarella,Opera Logica, De Natura Logicæ, ii. 13-23, I owe to the kindness of Professor Butcher of Edinburgh. Zabarella probably derived his knowledge of Aristotle'sPoeticsfrom Robortelli, under whom he studied Greek.Cf.Bayle,Dict.s. v. Zabarella.
[41]This analysis of Zabarella,Opera Logica, De Natura Logicæ, ii. 13-23, I owe to the kindness of Professor Butcher of Edinburgh. Zabarella probably derived his knowledge of Aristotle'sPoeticsfrom Robortelli, under whom he studied Greek.Cf.Bayle,Dict.s. v. Zabarella.
[42]Maggi, p. 28sq.Cf.B. Tasso,Lettere, ii. 514; Scaliger,Poet.i. 2; Castelvetro,Poetica, p. 7; Salviati, Cod. Magliabech. ii. ii. 11, fol. 384 v.; B. Jonson,Timber, p. 74.
[42]Maggi, p. 28sq.Cf.B. Tasso,Lettere, ii. 514; Scaliger,Poet.i. 2; Castelvetro,Poetica, p. 7; Salviati, Cod. Magliabech. ii. ii. 11, fol. 384 v.; B. Jonson,Timber, p. 74.
[43]Daniello, p. 41sq.
[43]Daniello, p. 41sq.
[44]Robortelli, p. 86sq.
[44]Robortelli, p. 86sq.
[45]Robortelli, p. 90sq.
[45]Robortelli, p. 90sq.
[46]Fracastoro, i. 340.
[46]Fracastoro, i. 340.
[47]Fracastoro, i. 357sq.
[47]Fracastoro, i. 357sq.
[48]Poet.vi. 2.
[48]Poet.vi. 2.
[49]Varchi, p. 578.
[49]Varchi, p. 578.
[50]E.g.Piccolomini, p. 27sq.
[50]E.g.Piccolomini, p. 27sq.
[51]Tiraboschi, vii. 1331.
[51]Tiraboschi, vii. 1331.
[52]Summo, pp. 61-69.
[52]Summo, pp. 61-69.
[53]Poet.iii. 95.
[53]Poet.iii. 95.
[54]Poet.i. 1.
[54]Poet.i. 1.
[55]Another critic of the time, Vettori, 1560, pp. 14, 93, attacks poetic prose on the ground that in Aristotle's definition of the various poetic forms, verse is always spoken of as an essential part. It is interesting to note that the phrase "poetic prose" is used, perhaps for the first time, in Minturno,Arte Poetica, 1564, p. 3, etc.
[55]Another critic of the time, Vettori, 1560, pp. 14, 93, attacks poetic prose on the ground that in Aristotle's definition of the various poetic forms, verse is always spoken of as an essential part. It is interesting to note that the phrase "poetic prose" is used, perhaps for the first time, in Minturno,Arte Poetica, 1564, p. 3, etc.
[56]Opere, x. 254.Cf.Minturno,Arte Poetica, p. 33.
[56]Opere, x. 254.Cf.Minturno,Arte Poetica, p. 33.
[57]Poet.iii. 96.
[57]Poet.iii. 96.
[58]Muzio, p. 69.
[58]Muzio, p. 69.
[59]Giraldi Cintio, i. 61.
[59]Giraldi Cintio, i. 61.
[60]Art Poét.iii. 50.Cf.Horace,Ars Poet.188.
[60]Art Poét.iii. 50.Cf.Horace,Ars Poet.188.
[61]Zodiac. Vitæ, i. 143.
[61]Zodiac. Vitæ, i. 143.
[62]Butcher, pp. 117, 118.
[62]Butcher, pp. 117, 118.
[63]Poet.i. 8.
[63]Poet.i. 8.
[64]Fracastoro, i. 335sq.
[64]Fracastoro, i. 335sq.
[65]Cf.Castelvetro,Poetica, p. 27sq.
[65]Cf.Castelvetro,Poetica, p. 27sq.
[66]Rhet.i. 11.
[66]Rhet.i. 11.
[67]Cf.A. Segni, 1581, cap. i.
[67]Cf.A. Segni, 1581, cap. i.
[68]Varchi, p. 227sq.
[68]Varchi, p. 227sq.
[69]Capriano, cap. ii.
[69]Capriano, cap. ii.
[70]Lionardi, p. 43sq.
[70]Lionardi, p. 43sq.
[71]Lettere, ii. 525.
[71]Lettere, ii. 525.
[72]Scaliger,Poet.i. 2.
[72]Scaliger,Poet.i. 2.
[73]Defense, pp. 10, 11.
[73]Defense, pp. 10, 11.
[74]De Poeta, p. 53sq.
[74]De Poeta, p. 53sq.
[75]Castelvetro,Poetica, p. 23sq.
[75]Castelvetro,Poetica, p. 23sq.
[76]Ibid.p. 190.
[76]Ibid.p. 190.
[77]Cf.T. Tasso, xi. 51.
[77]Cf.T. Tasso, xi. 51.
[78]Poetica, p. 158.
[78]Poetica, p. 158.
[79]Poetica, p. 191.
[79]Poetica, p. 191.
[80]Ars Poet.333.
[80]Ars Poet.333.
[81]Butcher, p. 185.
[81]Butcher, p. 185.
[82]Daniello, p. 25.
[82]Daniello, p. 25.
[83]Ibid.p. 40.
[83]Ibid.p. 40.
[84]Fracastoro, i. 363.
[84]Fracastoro, i. 363.
[85]Scaliger,Poet.vi. ii. 2.
[85]Scaliger,Poet.vi. ii. 2.
[86]De Poeta, p. 102.Cf.Scaliger,Poet.iii. 96.
[86]De Poeta, p. 102.Cf.Scaliger,Poet.iii. 96.
[87]De Poeta, p. 11.
[87]De Poeta, p. 11.
[88]Essay of Dramatic Poesy, p. 104.
[88]Essay of Dramatic Poesy, p. 104.
[89]De Poeta, p. 79.
[89]De Poeta, p. 79.
[90]Œuvres, vii. 318.
[90]Œuvres, vii. 318.
[91]Works, i. 333.
[91]Works, i. 333.
[92]Prose Works, iii. 118.
[92]Prose Works, iii. 118.
[93]Characteristicks, 1711, i. 207.
[93]Characteristicks, 1711, i. 207.
[94]H. C. Robinson,Diary, May 29, 1812, "Coleridge talked of the impossibility of being a good poet without being a good man."
[94]H. C. Robinson,Diary, May 29, 1812, "Coleridge talked of the impossibility of being a good poet without being a good man."
[95]Defence of Poetry, p. 42.
[95]Defence of Poetry, p. 42.
[96]Minturno plainly says as much,De Poeta, p. 105.
[96]Minturno plainly says as much,De Poeta, p. 105.
[97]Geog.i. ii. 5, as cited by Shaftesbury.
[97]Geog.i. ii. 5, as cited by Shaftesbury.
[98]Lettere, ii. 195.
[98]Lettere, ii. 195.
[99]Essay of Dramatic Poesy, p. 104.
[99]Essay of Dramatic Poesy, p. 104.
[100]Cf.Piccolomini, p. 369.
[100]Cf.Piccolomini, p. 369.
[101]Castelvetro,Poetica, p. 505.Cf.Twining, ii. 449, 450.
[101]Castelvetro,Poetica, p. 505.Cf.Twining, ii. 449, 450.
[102]Poetica, p. 29.
[102]Poetica, p. 29.
[103]Posnett, cited by Cook, p. 247.
[103]Posnett, cited by Cook, p. 247.
[104]Opere, viii. 26sq.
[104]Opere, viii. 26sq.
[105]Ibid.ix. 123.
[105]Ibid.ix. 123.
[106]Ibid.xii. 13.
[106]Ibid.xii. 13.
[107]Ibid.xi. 50.
[107]Ibid.xi. 50.
[108]Ibid.xii. 212.
[108]Ibid.xii. 212.
Aristotle'sdefinition of tragedy is the basis of the Renaissance theory of tragedy. That definition is as follows: "Tragedy is an imitation of an action that is serious, complete, and of a certain magnitude; in language embellished with each kind of artistic ornament, the several kinds being found in separate parts of the play; in the form of action, not of narration; through pity and fear effecting the properkatharsisor purgation of these emotions."[109]
To expand this definition, tragedy, in common with all other forms of poetry, is the imitation of an action; but the action of tragedy is distinguished from that of comedy in being grave and serious. The action is complete, in so far as it possesses perfect unity; and in length it must be of the proper magnitude. By embellished language, Aristotle means language into which rhythm, harmony, and song enter; and by the remark that the several kinds are to be found in separate parts of the play, he means that some parts of tragedy are rendered through the medium of verse alone, while others receive the aid of song. Moreover, tragedy is distinguishedfrom epic poetry by being in the form of action instead of that of narration. The last portion of Aristotle's definition describes the peculiar function of tragic performance.
Tragedy is the imitation of aseriousaction, that is, an action both grave and great, or, as the sixteenth century translated the word, illustrious. Now, what constitutes a serious action, and what actions are not suited to the dignified character of tragedy? Daniello (1536) distinguishes tragedy from comedy in that the comic poets "deal with the most familiar and domestic, not to say base and vile operations; the tragic poets, with the deaths of high kings and the ruins of great empires."[110]Whichever of these matters the poet selects should be treated without admixture of any other form; if he resolves to treat of grave matters, mere loveliness should be excluded; if of themes of loveliness, he should exclude all grave themes. Here, at the very beginning of dramatic discussion, the strict separation of themes orgenresis advocated in as formal a manner as ever during the period of classicism; and this was never deviated from, at least in theory, by any of the writers of the sixteenth century. Moreover, according to Daniello, the dignified character of tragedy demands that all unseemly, cruel, impossible, or ignoble incidents should be excluded from the stage; while even comedyshould not attempt to represent any lascivious act.[111]This was merely a deduction from Senecan tragedy and the general practice of the classics.
There is, in Daniello's theory of tragedy, no single Aristotelian element, and it was not until about a decade later that Aristotle's theory of tragedy played any considerable part in the literary criticism of the sixteenth century. In 1543, however, thePoeticshad already become a part of university study, for Giraldi Cintio, in hisDiscorso sulle Comedie e sulle Tragedie, written in that year, says that it was a regular academic exercise to compare some Greek tragedy, such as theŒdipusof Sophocles, with a tragedy of Seneca on the same subject, using thePoeticsof Aristotle as a dramatic text-book.[112]Giraldi distinguishes tragedy from comedy on somewhat the same grounds as Daniello. "Tragedy and comedy," he says, "agree in that they are both imitations of an action, but they differ in that the former imitates the illustrious and royal, the latter the popular and civil. Hence Aristotle says that comedy imitates the worse sort of actions, not that they are vicious and criminal, but that, as regards nobility, they are worse when compared with royal actions." Giraldi's position is made clear by his further statement that the actions of tragedy are called illustrious, not because they are virtuous or vicious, but merely because they are the actions of people of the highest rank.[113]
This conception of the serious action of tragedy,which makes its dignity the result of the rank of those who are its actors, and thus regards rank as the real distinguishing mark between comedy and tragedy, was not only common throughout the Renaissance, but even throughout the whole period of classicism, and had an extraordinary effect on the modern drama, especially in France. Thus Dacier (1692) says that it is not necessary that the action be illustrious and important in itself: "On the contrary, it may be very ordinary or common; but it must be so by the quality of the persons who act.... The greatness of these eminent men renders the action great, and their reputation makes it credible and possible."[114]
Again, Robortelli (1548) maintains that tragedy deals only with the greater sort of men (præstantiores), because the fall of men of such rank into misery and disgrace produces greater commiseration (which is, as will be seen, one of the functions of tragedy) than the fall of men of merely ordinary rank. Another commentator on thePoetics, Maggi (1550), gives a slightly different explanation of Aristotle's meaning. Maggi asserts that Aristotle,[115]in saying that comedy deals with the worse and tragedy with the better sort of men, means to distinguish between those whose rank is lower or higher than that of ordinary men; comedy dealing with slaves, tradesmen, maidservants, buffoons, and other low people, tragedy with kings and heroes.[116]This explanation is defended on grounds similar tothose given by Robortelli, that is, the change from felicity to infelicity is greater and more noticeable in the greatest men.[117]
This conception of the rank of the characters as the distinguishing mark between tragedy and comedy is, it need not be said, entirely un-Aristotelian. "Aristotle does undoubtedly hold," says Professor Butcher, "that actors in tragedy ought to be illustrious by birth and position. The narrow and trivial life of obscure persons cannot give scope for a great and significant action, one of tragic consequence. But nowhere does he make outward rank the distinguishing feature of tragic as opposed to comic representation. Moral nobility is what he demands; and this—on the French stage, or at least with French critics—is transformed into an inflated dignity, a courtly etiquette and decorum, which seemed proper to high rank. The instance is one of many in which literary critics have wholly confounded the teaching of Aristotle."[118]This distinction, then, though common up to the end of the eighteenth century, is not to be found in Aristotle; but the fact is, that a similar distinction can be traced, throughout the Middle Ages, throughout classical antiquity, back almost to the time of Aristotle himself.
The grammarian, Diomedes, has preserved the definition of tragedy formulated by Theophrastus, Aristotle's successor as head of the Peripatetic school. According to this definition, tragedy is"a change in the fortune of a hero."[119]A Greek definition of comedy preserved by Diomedes, and ascribed to Theophrastus also,[120]speaks of comedy as dealing with private and civil fortunes, without the element of danger. This seems to have been the accepted Roman notion of comedy. In the treatise of Euanthius-Donatus, comedy is said to deal with the common fortunes of men, to begin turbulently, but to end tranquilly and happily; tragedy, on the other hand, has only mighty personages, and ends terribly; its subject is often historical, while that of comedy is always invented by the poet.[121]The third book of Diomedes'sArs Grammatica, based on Suetonius's tractateDe Poetis(written in the second centuryA.D.), distinguishes tragedy from comedy in that only heroes, great leaders, and kings are introduced in tragedy, while in comedy the characters are humble and private persons; in the former, lamentations, exiles, bloodshed predominate, in the latter, love affairs and seductions.[122]Isidore of Seville, in the seventh century, says very much the same thing: "Comic poets treat of the acts of private men, while tragic poets treat of public matters and the histories of kings; tragic themes are based on sorrowful affairs, comic themes on joyful ones."[123]In another place he speaks of tragedy as dealing with the ancient deeds and misdeedsof infamous kings, and of comedy as dealing with the actions of private men, and with the defilement of maidens and the love affairs of strumpets.[124]In theCatholiconof Johannes Januensis de Balbis (1286) tragedy and comedy are distinguished on similar grounds: tragedy deals only with kings and princes, comedy with private citizens; the style of the former is elevated, that of the latter humble; comedy begins sorrowfully and ends joyfully, tragedy begins joyfully and ends miserably and terribly.[125]For Dante, any poem written in an elevated and sublime style, beginning happily and ending in misery and terror, is a tragedy; his own great vision, written as it is in the vernacular, and beginning in hell and ending gloriously in paradise, he calls a comedy.[126]
It appears, therefore, that during the post-classic period and throughout the Middle Ages, comedy and tragedy were distinguished on any or all of the following grounds:—
i. The characters in tragedy are kings, princes, or great leaders; those in comedy, humble persons and private citizens.
ii. Tragedy deals with great and terrible actions; comedy with familiar and domestic actions.
iii. Tragedy begins happily and ends terribly; comedy begins rather turbulently and ends joyfully.
iv. The style and diction of tragedy are elevated and sublime; while those of comedy are humble and colloquial.
v. The subjects of tragedy are generally historical; those of comedy are always invented by the poet.
vi. Comedy deals largely with love and seduction; tragedy with exile and bloodshed.
This, then, was the tradition that shaped the un-Aristotelian conception of the distinctions between comedy and tragedy, which persisted throughout and even beyond the Renaissance. Giraldi Cintio has followed most of these traditional distinctions, but he is in closer accord with Aristotle[127]when he asserts that the tragic as well as the comic plot may be purely imaginary and invented by the poet.[128]He explains the traditional conception that the tragic fable should be historical, on the ground that as tragedy deals with the deeds of kings and illustrious men, it would not be probable that remarkable actions of such great personages should be left unrecorded in history, whereas the private events treated in comedy could hardly be known to all. Giraldi, however, asserts that it does not matter whether the tragic poet invents his story or not, so long as it follows the law of probability. The poet should choose an action that is probable and dignified, that does not need the intervention of a god in the unravelling of the plot, that does not occupy much more than the space of a day, and that can be represented on the stage in three orfour hours.[129]In respect to the dénouement of tragedy, it may be happy or unhappy, but in either case it must arouse pity and terror; and as for the classic notion that no deaths should be represented on the stage, Giraldi declares that those which are not excessively painful may be represented, for they are represented not for the sake of commiseration but of justice. The argument here centres about Aristotle's phraseἐν τῷ φανερῷ θάνατοι,[130]but the common practice of classicism was based on Horace's express prohibition:—