SIXTH PAPERDEDUCTION, INDUCTION, AND HYPOTHESIS[51]

ABCDE AbCDE aBCDE abCDEABCDe AbCDe aBCDe abCDeABCdE AbCdE aBCdE abCdEABCde AbCde aBCde abCdeABcDE AbcDE aBcDE abcDEABcDe AbcDe aBcDe abcDeABcdE AbcdE aBcdE abcdEABcde Abcde aBcde abcde

ABCDE AbCDE aBCDE abCDEABCDe AbCDe aBCDe abCDeABCdE AbCdE aBCdE abCdEABCde AbCde aBCde abCdeABcDE AbcDE aBcDE abcDEABcDe AbcDe aBcDe abcDeABcdE AbcdE aBcdE abcdEABcde Abcde aBcde abcde

ABCDE AbCDE aBCDE abCDEABCDe AbCDe aBCDe abCDeABCdE AbCdE aBCdE abCdEABCde AbCde aBCde abCdeABcDE AbcDE aBcDE abcDEABcDe AbcDe aBcDe abcDeABcdE AbcdE aBcdE abcdEABcde Abcde aBcde abcde

ABCDE AbCDE aBCDE abCDE

ABCDe AbCDe aBCDe abCDe

ABCdE AbCdE aBCdE abCdE

ABCde AbCde aBCde abCde

ABcDE AbcDE aBcDE abcDE

ABcDe AbcDe aBcDe abcDe

ABcdE AbcdE aBcdE abcdE

ABcde Abcde aBcde abcde

For example, if the five primary characters werehard,sweet,fragrant,green,bright, there would be one object which reunited all these qualities, one which was hard, sweet, fragrant, and green, but not bright; one which was hard, sweet, fragrant, and bright, but not green; one which was hard, sweet, and fragrant, but neither green nor bright; and so on through all the combinations.

This is what a thoroughly chance-world would be like, and certainly nothing could be imagined more systematic. When a quantity of letters are poured out of a bag, the appearance of disorder is due to the circumstance that the phenomena are only partly fortuitous. The laws of space are supposed, in that case, to be rigidly preserved, and there is also a certain amount of regularity in the formation of the letters. The result is that some elements areorderly and some are disorderly, which is precisely what we observe in the actual world. Tillotson, in the passage of which a part has been quoted, goes on to ask, “How long might 20,000 blind men which should be sent out from the several remote parts of England, wander up and down before they would all meet upon Salisbury Plains, and fall into rank and file in the exact order of an army? And yet this is much more easy to be imagined than how the innumerable blind parts of matter should rendezvous themselves into a world.” This is very true, but in the actual world theblind menare, as far as we can see,notdrawn up in any particular order at all. And, in short, while a certain amount of order exists in the world, it would seem that the world is not so orderly as it might be, and, for instance, not so much so as a world of pure chance would be.

But we can never get to the bottom of this question until we take account of a highly-important logical principle[48]which I now proceed to enounce. This principle is that any plurality or lot of objects whatever have some character in common (no matter how insignificant) which is peculiar to them and not shared by anything else. The word “character” here is taken in such a sense as to include negative characters, such as incivility, inequality, etc., as well as their positives, civility, equality, etc. To prove the theorem, I will show what character any two things, A and B, have in common, not shared by anything else. The things, A and B, are each distinguished from all other things by the possession of certain characters which may be named A-ness and B-ness. Corresponding to these positivecharacters, are the negative characters un-A-ness, which is possessed by everything except A, and un-B-ness, which is possessed by everything except B. These two characters are united in everything except A and B; and this union of the characters un-A-ness and un-B-ness makes a compound character which may be termed A-B-lessness. This is not possessed by either A or B, but it is possessed by everything else. This character, like every other, has its corresponding negative un-A-B-lessness, and this last is the character possessed by both A and B, and by nothing else. It is obvious that what has thus been shown true of two things ismutatis mutandis, true of any number of things. Q. E. D.

In any world whatever, then, there must be a character peculiar to each possible group of objects. If, as a matter of nomenclature, characters peculiar to the same group be regarded as only different aspects of the same character, then we may say that there will be precisely one character for each possible group of objects. Thus, suppose a world to contain five things, α, β, γ, δ, ε. Then it will have a separate character for each of the 31 groups (withnon-existencemaking up 32 or 25) shown in the following table:

Table II.

αβ αβγ αβγδ αβγδεα αγ αβδ αβγεβ αδ αβε αβδεγ αε αγδ αγδεδ βγ αγε βγδεε βδ αδεβε βγδγδ βγεγε βδεδε γδε

αβ αβγ αβγδ αβγδεα αγ αβδ αβγεβ αδ αβε αβδεγ αε αγδ αγδεδ βγ αγε βγδεε βδ αδεβε βγδγδ βγεγε βδεδε γδε

αβ αβγ αβγδ αβγδεα αγ αβδ αβγεβ αδ αβε αβδεγ αε αγδ αγδεδ βγ αγε βγδεε βδ αδεβε βγδγδ βγεγε βδεδε γδε

αβ αβγ αβγδ αβγδε

α αγ αβδ αβγε

β αδ αβε αβδε

γ αε αγδ αγδε

δ βγ αγε βγδε

ε βδ αδε

βε βγδ

γδ βγε

γε βδε

δε γδε

This shows that a contradiction is involved in the very idea[49]of a chance-world, for in a world of 32 things, instead of there being only 35or 243 characters, as we have seen that the notion of a chance-world requires, there would, in fact, be no less than 232, or 4,294,967,296 characters, which would not be all independent, but would have all possible relations with one another.

We further see that so long as we regard characters abstractly, without regard to their relative importance, etc., there is no possibility of a more or less degree of orderliness in the world, the whole system of relationship between the different characters being given by mere logic; that is, being implied in those facts which are tacitly admitted as soon as we admit that there is any such thing as reasoning.

In order to descend from this abstract point of view, it is requisite to consider the characters of things as relative to the perceptions and active powers of living beings. Instead, then, of attempting to imagine a world in which there should be no uniformities, let us suppose one in which none of the uniformities should have reference to characters interesting or important to us. In the first place, there would be nothing to puzzle us in such a world. The small number of qualities which would directly meet the senses would be the ones which would afford the key to everything which could possibly interest us. The whole universe would have such an air of system and perfect regularity that there would be nothing to ask. In the next place, no action of ours, and no event of Nature, would have important consequences in such a world. We should beperfectly free from all responsibility, and there would be nothing to do but to enjoy or suffer whatever happened to come along. Thus there would be nothing to stimulate or develop either the mind or the will, and we consequently should neither act nor think. We should have no memory, because that depends on a law of our organization. Even if we had any senses, we should be situated toward such a world precisely as inanimate objects are toward the present one, provided we suppose that these objects have an absolutely transitory and instantaneous consciousness without memory—a supposition which is a mere mode of speech, for that would be no consciousness at all. We may, therefore, say that a world of chance is simply our actual world viewed from the standpoint of an animal at the very vanishing-point of intelligence. The actual world is almost a chance-medley to the mind of a polyp. The interest which the uniformities of Nature have for an animal measures his place in the scale of intelligence.

Thus, nothing can be made out from the orderliness of Nature in regard to the existence of a God, unless it be maintained that the existence of a finite mind proves the existence of an infinite one.

In the last of these papers we examined the nature of inductive or synthetic reasoning. We found it to be a process of sampling. A number of specimens of a class are taken, not by selection within that class, but at random. These specimens will agree in a great number of respects. If, now, it were likely that a second lot would agree withthe first in the majority of these respects, we might base on this consideration an inference in regard to any one of these characters. But such an inference would neither be of the nature of induction, nor would it (except in special cases) be valid, because the vast majority of points of agreement in the first sample drawn would generally be entirely accidental, as well as insignificant. To illustrate this, I take the ages at death of the first five poets given in Wheeler’sBiographical Dictionary. They are:

Aagard, 48.Abeille, 70.Abulola, 84.Abunowas, 48.Accords, 45.

Aagard, 48.Abeille, 70.Abulola, 84.Abunowas, 48.Accords, 45.

Aagard, 48.Abeille, 70.Abulola, 84.Abunowas, 48.Accords, 45.

Aagard, 48.

Abeille, 70.

Abulola, 84.

Abunowas, 48.

Accords, 45.

These five ages have the following characters in common:

1. The difference of the two digits composing the number, divided by three, leaves a remainder ofone.

2. The first digit raised to the power indicated by the second, and divided by three, leaves a remainder ofone.

3. The sum of the prime factors of each age, including one, is divisible by three.

It is easy to see that the number of accidental agreements of this sort would be quite endless. But suppose that, instead of considering a character because of its prevalence in the sample, we designate a character before taking the sample, selecting it for its importance, obviousness, or other point of interest. Then two considerable samples drawn at random are extremely likely to agreeapproximately in regard to the proportion of occurrences of a character so chosen.The inference that a previously designated character has nearly the same frequency of occurrence in the whole of a class that it has in a sample drawn at random out of that class is induction.If the character be not previously designated, then a sample in which it is found to be prevalent can only serve to suggest that itmay beprevalent in the whole class. We may consider this surmise as an inference if we please—an inference of possibility; but a second sample must be drawn to test the question of whether the character actually is prevalent. Instead of designating beforehand a single character in reference to which we will examine a sample, we may designate two, and use the same sample to determine the relative frequencies of both. This will be making two inductive inferences at once; and, of course, we are less certain that both will yield correct conclusions than we should be that either separately would do so. What is true of two characters is true of any limited number. Now, the number of characters which have any considerable interest for us in reference to any class of objects is more moderate than might be supposed. As we shall be sure to examine any sample with reference to these characters, they may be regarded not exactly as predesignated, but as predetermined (which amounts to the same thing); and we may infer that the sample represents the class in all these respects if we please, remembering only that this is not so secure an inference as if the particular quality to be looked for had been fixed upon beforehand.

The demonstration of this theory of induction rests uponprinciples and follows methods which are accepted by all those who display in other matters the particular knowledge and force of mind which qualify them to judge of this. The theory itself, however, quite unaccountably seems never to have occurred to any of the writers who have undertaken to explain synthetic reasoning. The most widely-spread opinion in the matter is one which was much promoted by Mr. John Stuart Mill—namely, that induction depends for its validity upon the uniformity of Nature—that is, on the principle that what happens once will, under a sufficient degree of similarity of circumstances, happen again as often as the same circumstances recur. The application is this: The fact that different things belong to the same class constitutes the similarity of circumstances, and the induction is good, provided this similarity is “sufficient.” What happens once is, that a number of these things are found to have a certain character; what may be expected, then, to happen again as often as the circumstances recur consists in this, that all things belonging to the same class should have the same character.

This analysis of induction has, I venture to think, various imperfections, to some of which it may be useful to call attention. In the first place, when I put my hand in a bag and draw out a handful of beans, and, finding three-quarters of them black, infer that about three-quarters of all in the bag are black, my inference is obviously of the same kind as if I had found any larger proportion, or the whole, of the sample black, and had assumed that it represented in that respect the rest of the contents of the bag. But the analysis in question hardly seems adapted to theexplanation of thisproportionateinduction, where the conclusion, instead of being that a certain event uniformly happens under certain circumstances, is precisely that it does not uniformly occur, but only happens in a certain proportion of cases. It is true that the whole sample may be regarded as a single object, and the inference may be brought under the formula proposed by considering the conclusion to be that any similar sample will show a similar proportion among its constituents. But this is to treat the induction as if it rested on a single instance, which gives a very false idea of its probability.

In the second place, if the uniformity of Nature were the sole warrant of induction, we should have no right to draw one in regard to a character whose constancy we knew nothing about. Accordingly, Mr. Mill says that, though none but white swans were known to Europeans for thousands of years, yet the inference that all swans were white was “not a good induction,” because it was not known that color was a usual generic character (it, in fact, not being so by any means). But it is mathematically demonstrable that an inductive inference may have as high a degree of probability as you please independent of any antecedent knowledge of the constancy of the character inferred. Before it was known that color is not usually a character ofgenera, there was certainly a considerable probability that all swans were white. But the further study of thegeneraof animals led to the induction of their non-uniformity in regard to color. A deductive application of this general proposition would have gone far to overcome the probability of the universal whiteness of swans beforethe black species was discovered. When we do know anything in regard to the general constancy or inconstancy of a character, the application of that general knowledge to the particular class to which any induction relates, though it serves to increase or diminish the force of the induction, is, like every application of general knowledge to particular cases, deductive in its nature and not inductive.

In the third place, to say that inductions are true because similar events happen in similar circumstances—or, what is the same thing, because objects similar in some respects are likely to be similar in others—is to overlook those conditions which really are essential to the validity of inductions. When we take all the characters into account, any pair of objects resemble one another in just as many particulars as any other pair. If we limit ourselves to such characters as have for us any importance, interest, or obviousness, then a synthetic conclusion may be drawn, but only on condition that the specimens by which we judge have been taken at random from the class in regard to which we are to form a judgment, and not selected as belonging to any sub-class. The induction only has its full force when the character concerned has been designated before examining the sample. These are the essentials of induction, and they are not recognized in attributing the validity of induction to the uniformity of Nature. The explanation of induction by the doctrine of probabilities, given in the last of these papers, is not a mere metaphysical formula, but is one from which all the rules of synthetic reasoning can be deduced systematically and with mathematical cogency. But the account of the matter by a principleof Nature, even if it were in other respects satisfactory, presents the fatal disadvantage of leaving us quite as much afloat as before in regard to the proper method of induction. It does not surprise me, therefore, that those who adopt this theory have given erroneous rules for the conduct of reasoning, nor that the greater number of examples put forward by Mr. Mill in his first edition, as models of what inductions should be, proved in the light of further scientific progress so particularly unfortunate that they had to be replaced by others in later editions. One would have supposed that Mr. Mill might have based an induction onthiscircumstance, especially as it is his avowed principle that, if the conclusion of an induction turns out false, it cannot have been a good induction. Nevertheless, neither he nor any of his scholars seem to have been led to suspect, in the least, the perfect solidity of the framework which he devised for securely supporting the mind in its passage from the known to the unknown, although at its first trial it did not answer quite so well as had been expected.

When we have drawn any statistical induction—such, for instance, as that one-half of all births are of male children—it is always possible to discover, by investigation sufficiently prolonged, a class of which the same predicate may be affirmed universally; to find out, for instance,what sort ofbirths are of male children. The truth of this principle follows immediately from the theorem that there is a character peculiar to every possible group of objects. Theform in which the principle is usually stated is, thatevery event must have a cause.

But, though there exists a cause for every event, and that of a kind which is capable of being discovered, yet if there be nothing to guide us to the discovery; if we have to hunt among all the events in the world without any scent; if, for instance, the sex of a child might equally be supposed to depend on the configuration of the planets, on what was going on at the antipodes, or on anything else—then the discovery would have no chance of ever getting made.

That we ever do discover the precise causes of things, that any induction whatever is absolutely without exception, is what we have no right to assume. On the contrary, it is an easy corollary, from the theorem just referred to, that every empirical rule has an exception.[50]But there are certain of our inductions which present an approach to universality so extraordinary that, even if we are to suppose that they are not strictly universal truths, we cannot possibly think that they have been reached merely by accident. The most remarkable laws of this kind are those oftimeandspace. With reference to space, Bishop Berkeley first showed, in a very conclusive manner, that it was not a thingseen, but a thinginferred. Berkeley chiefly insists on the impossibility of directly seeing the third dimension of space, since the retina of the eye is a surface. But, in point of fact, the retina is not even a surface; it is a conglomeration of nerve-needles directedtoward the light and having only their extreme points sensitive, these points lying at considerable distances from one another compared with their areas. Now, of these points, certainly the excitation of no one singly can produce the perception of a surface, and consequently not the aggregate of all the sensations can amount to this. But certain relations subsist between the excitations of different nerve-points, and these constitute the premises upon which the hypothesis of space is founded, and from which it is inferred. That space is not immediately perceived is now universally admitted; and a mediate cognition is what is called an inference, and is subject to the criticism of logic. But what are we to say to the fact of every chicken as soon as it is hatched solving a problem whose data are of a complexity sufficient to try the greatest mathematical powers? It would be insane to deny that the tendency to light upon the conception of space is inborn in the mind of the chicken and of every animal. The same thing is equally true of time. That time is not directly perceived is evident, since no lapse of time is present, and we only perceive what is present. That, not having the idea of time, we should never be able to perceive the flow in our sensations without some particular aptitude for it, will probably also be admitted. The idea of force—at least, in its rudiments—is another conception so early arrived at, and found in animals so low in the scale of intelligence, that it must be supposed innate. But the innateness of an idea admits of degree, for it consists in the tendency of that idea to present itself to the mind. Some ideas, like that of space, do so present themselves irresistibly at the very dawn ofintelligence, and take possession of the mind on small provocation, while of other conceptions we are prepossessed, indeed, but not so strongly, down a scale which is greatly extended. The tendency to personify every thing, and to attribute human characters to it, may be said to be innate; but it is a tendency which is very soon overcome by civilized man in regard to the greater part of the objects about him. Take such a conception as that of gravitation varying inversely as the square of the distance. It is a very simple law. But to say that it is simple is merely to say that it is one which the mind is particularly adapted to apprehend with facility. Suppose the idea of a quantity multiplied into another had been no more easy to the mind than that of a quantity raised to the power indicated by itself—should we ever have discovered the law of the solar system?

It seems incontestable, therefore, that the mind of man is strongly adapted to the comprehension of the world; at least, so far as this goes, that certain conceptions, highly important for such a comprehension, naturally arise in his mind; and, without such a tendency, the mind could never have had any development at all.

How are we to explain this adaptation? The great utility and indispensableness of the conceptions of time, space, and force, even to the lowest intelligence, are such as to suggest that they are the results of natural selection. Without something like geometrical, kinetical, and mechanical conceptions, no animal could seize his food or do anything which might be necessary for the preservation of the species. He might, it is true, be provided with an instinct which would generally have the same effect; that is to say,he might have conceptions different from those of time, space, and force, but which coincided with them in regard to the ordinary cases of the animal’s experience. But, as that animal would have an immense advantage in the struggle for life whose mechanical conceptions did not break down in a novel situation (such as development must bring about), there would be a constant selection in favor of more and more correct ideas of these matters. Thus would be attained the knowledge of that fundamental law upon which all science rolls; namely, that forces depend upon relations of time, space, and mass. When this idea was once sufficiently clear, it would require no more than a comprehensible degree of genius to discover the exact nature of these relations. Such an hypothesis naturally suggests itself, but it must be admitted that it does not seem sufficient to account for the extraordinary accuracy with which these conceptions apply to the phenomena of Nature, and it is probable that there is some secret here which remains to be discovered.

Some important questions of logic depend upon whether we are to consider the material universe as of limited extent and finite age, or quite boundless in space and in time. In the former case, it is conceivable that a general plan or design embracing the whole universe should be discovered, and it would be proper to be on the alert for some traces of such a unity. In the latter case, since the proportion of the world of which we can have any experience is less than the smallest assignable fraction, it follows thatwe never could discover anypatternin the universe except a repeating one; any design embracing the whole would be beyond our powers to discern, and beyond the united powers of all intellects during all time. Now, what is absolutely incapable of being known is, as we have seen in a former paper, not real at all. An absolutely incognizable existence is a nonsensical phrase. If, therefore, the universe is infinite, the attempt to find in it any design embracing it as a whole is futile, and involves a false way of looking at the subject. If the universe never had any beginning, and if in space world stretches beyond world without limit, there is nowholeof material things, and consequently no general character to the universe, and no need or possibility of any governor for it. But if there was a time before which absolutely no matter existed, if there are certain absolute bounds to the region of things outside of which there is a mere void, then we naturally seek for an explanation of it, and, since we cannot look for it among material things, the hypothesis of a great disembodied animal, the creator and governor of the world, is natural enough.

The actual state of the evidence as to the limitation of the universe is as follows: As to time, we find on our earth a constant progress of development since the planet was a red-hot ball; the solar system seems to have resulted from the condensation of a nebula, and the process appears to be still going on. We sometimes see stars (presumably with systems of worlds) destroyed and apparently resolved back into the nebulous condition, but we have no evidence of any existence of the world previous to the nebulous stage from which it seems to have been evolved. All this ratherfavors the idea of a beginning than otherwise. As for limits in space, we cannot be sure that we see anything outside of the system of the Milky Way. Minds of theological predilections have therefore no need of distorting the facts to reconcile them with their views.

But the only scientific presumption is, that the unknown parts of space and time are like the known parts, occupied; that, as we see cycles of life and death in all development which we can trace out to the end, the same holds good in regard to solar systems; that as enormous distances lie between the different planets of our solar system, relatively to their diameters, and as still more enormous distances lie between our system relatively to its diameter and other systems, so it may be supposed that other galactic clusters exist so remote from ours as not to be recognized as such with certainty. I do not say that these are strong inductions; I only say that they are the presumptions which, in our ignorance of the facts, should be preferred to hypotheses which involve conceptions of things and occurrences totally different in their character from any of which we have had any experience, such as disembodied spirits, the creation of matter, infringements of the laws of mechanics, etc.

The universe ought to be presumed too vast to have any character. When it is claimed that the arrangements of Nature are benevolent, or just, or wise, or of any other peculiar kind, we ought to be prejudiced against such opinions, as being the offspring of an ill-founded notion of the finitude of the world. And examination has hitherto shown that such beneficences, justice, etc., are of a most limited kind—limited in degree and limited in range.

In like manner, if any one claims to have discovered a plan in the structure of organized beings, or a scheme in their classification, or a regular arrangement among natural objects, or a system of proportionality in the human form, or an order of development, or a correspondence between conjunctions of the planets and human events, or a significance in numbers, or a key to dreams, the first thing we have to ask is whether such relations are susceptible of explanation on mechanical principles, and if not they should be looked upon with disfavor as having already a strong presumption against them; and examination has generally exploded all such theories.

There are minds to whom every prejudice, every presumption, seems unfair. It is easy to say what minds these are. They are those who never have known what it is to draw a well-grounded induction, and who imagine that other people’s knowledge is as nebulous as their own. That all science rolls upon presumption (not of a formal but of a real kind) is no argument with them, because they cannot imagine that there is anything solid in human knowledge. These are the people who waste their time and money upon perpetual motions and other such rubbish.

But there are better minds who take up mystical theories (by which I mean all those which have no possibility of being mechanically explained). These are persons who are strongly prejudiced in favor of such theories. We all have natural tendencies to believe in such things; our education often strengthens this tendency; and the result is, that to many minds nothing seems so antecedently probable as a theory of this kind. Such persons find evidence enoughin favor of their views, and in the absence of any recognized logic of induction they cannot be driven from their belief.

But to the mind of a physicist there ought to be a strong presumption against every mystical theory; and, therefore, it seems to me that those scientific men who have sought to make out that science was not hostile to theology have not been so clear-sighted as their opponents.

It would be extravagant to say that science can at present disprove religion; but it does seem to me that the spirit of science is hostile to any religion except such a one as that of M. Vacherot. Our appointed teachers inform us that Buddhism is a miserable and atheistical faith, shorn of the most glorious and needful attributes of a religion; that its priests can be of no use to agriculture by praying for rain, nor to war by commanding the sun to stand still. We also hear the remonstrances of those who warn us that to shake the general belief in the living God would be to shake the general morals, public and private. This, too, must be admitted; such a revolution of thought could no more be accomplished without waste and desolation than a plantation of trees could be transferred to new ground, however wholesome in itself, without all of them languishing for a time, and many of them dying. Nor is it, by-the-way, a thing to be presumed that a man would have taken part in a movement having a possible atheistical issue without having taken serious and adequate counsel in regard to that responsibility. But, let the consequences of such a belief be as dire as they may, one thing is certain: that the state of the facts, whatever it may be, will surely get found out, and no human prudence can long arrest the triumphal carof truth—no, not if the discovery were such as to drive every individual of our race to suicide!

But it would be folly to suppose that any metaphysical theory in regard to the mode of being of the perfect is to destroy that aspiration toward the perfect which constitutes the essence of religion. It is true that, if the priests of any particular form of religion succeed in making it generally believed that religion cannot exist without the acceptance of certain formulas, or if they succeed in so interweaving certain dogmas with the popular religion that the people can see no essential analogy between a religion which accepts these points of faith and one which rejects them, the result may very well be to render those who cannot believe these things irreligious. Nor can we ever hope that any body of priests should consider themselves more teachers of religion in general than of the particular system of theology advocated by their own party. But no man need be excluded from participation in the common feelings, nor from so much of the public expression of them as is open to all the laity, by the unphilosophical narrowness of those who guard the mysteries of worship. Am I to be prevented from joining in that common joy at the revelation of enlightened principles of religion, which we celebrate at Easter and Christmas, because I think that certain scientific, logical, and metaphysical ideas which have been mixed up with these principles are untenable? No; to do so would be to estimate those errors as of more consequence than the truth—an opinion which few would admit. People who do not believe what are really the fundamental principles of Christianity are rare to find, and all but these few ought to feel at home in the churches.

SIXTH PAPERDEDUCTION, INDUCTION, AND HYPOTHESIS[51]

The chief business of the logician is to classify arguments; for all testing clearly depends on classification. The classes of the logicians are defined by certain typical forms called syllogisms. For example, the syllogism calledBarbarais as follows:

S is M; M is P:Hence, S is P.

S is M; M is P:Hence, S is P.

S is M; M is P:Hence, S is P.

S is M; M is P:

Hence, S is P.

Or, to put words for letters—

Enoch and Elijah were men; all men die:Hence, Enoch and Elijah must have died.

Enoch and Elijah were men; all men die:Hence, Enoch and Elijah must have died.

Enoch and Elijah were men; all men die:Hence, Enoch and Elijah must have died.

Enoch and Elijah were men; all men die:

Hence, Enoch and Elijah must have died.

The “is P” of the logicians stands for any verb, active or neuter. It is capable of strict proof (with which, however, I will not trouble the reader) that all arguments whatever can be put into this form; but only under the condition that theisshall mean “isfor the purposes of the argument” or “is represented by.” Thus, an induction will appear in this form something like this:

These beans are two-thirds white;

But, the beans in this bag are (represented by) these beans;

∴ The beans in the bag are two-thirds white.

But, because all inference may be reduced in some way toBarbara, it does not follow that this is the most appropriate form in which to represent every kind of inference. On the contrary, to show the distinctive characters of different sorts of inference, they must clearly be exhibited in different forms peculiar to each.Barbaraparticularly typifies deductive reasoning; and so long as theisis taken literally, no inductive reasoning can be put into this form.Barbarais, in fact, nothing but the application of a rule. The so-called major premise lays down this rule; as, for example,All men are mortal.The other or minor premise states a case under the rule; as,Enoch was a man.The conclusion applies the rule to the case and states the result:Enoch is mortal.All deduction is of this character; it is merely the application of general rules to particular cases. Sometimes this is not very evident, as in the following:

All quadrangles are figures,But no triangle is a quadrangle;Therefore, some figures are not triangles.

All quadrangles are figures,But no triangle is a quadrangle;Therefore, some figures are not triangles.

All quadrangles are figures,But no triangle is a quadrangle;Therefore, some figures are not triangles.

All quadrangles are figures,

But no triangle is a quadrangle;

Therefore, some figures are not triangles.

But here the reasoning is really this:

Rule.—Every quadrangle is other than a triangle.Case.—Some figures are quadrangles.Result.—Some figures are not triangles.

Rule.—Every quadrangle is other than a triangle.Case.—Some figures are quadrangles.Result.—Some figures are not triangles.

Rule.—Every quadrangle is other than a triangle.Case.—Some figures are quadrangles.Result.—Some figures are not triangles.

Rule.—Every quadrangle is other than a triangle.

Case.—Some figures are quadrangles.

Result.—Some figures are not triangles.

Inductive or synthetic reasoning, being something more than the mere application of a general rule to a particular case, can never be reduced to this form.

If, from a bag of beans of which we know that 2/3 are white, we take one at random, it is a deductive inferencethat this bean is probably white, the probability being 2/3. We have, in effect, the following syllogism:

Rule.—The beans in this bag are 2/3 white.

Case.—This bean has been drawn in such a way that in the long run the relative number of white beans so drawn would be equal to the relative number in the bag.

Result.—This bean has been drawn in such a way that in the long run it would turn out white 2/3 of the time.

If instead of drawing one bean we draw a handful at random and conclude that about 2/3 of the handful are probably white, the reasoning is of the same sort. If, however, not knowing what proportion of white beans there are in the bag, we draw a handful at random and, finding 2/3 of the beans in the handful white, conclude that about 2/3 of those in the bag are white, we are rowing up the current of deductive sequence, and are concluding a rule from the observation of a result in a certain case. This is particularly clear when all the handful turn out one color. The induction then is:

These beans were in this bag.———————-These beans are white.—————————All the beans in the bag were white. | || | |Which is but an inversion of the deductive | | |syllogism. | | || | |Rule.—All the beans in the bag were white.—+ | |Case.—These beans were in the bag.——————+-+Result.—These beans are white.————————+

These beans were in this bag.———————-These beans are white.—————————All the beans in the bag were white. | || | |Which is but an inversion of the deductive | | |syllogism. | | || | |Rule.—All the beans in the bag were white.—+ | |Case.—These beans were in the bag.——————+-+Result.—These beans are white.————————+

These beans were in this bag.———————-These beans are white.—————————All the beans in the bag were white. | || | |Which is but an inversion of the deductive | | |syllogism. | | || | |Rule.—All the beans in the bag were white.—+ | |Case.—These beans were in the bag.——————+-+Result.—These beans are white.————————+

These beans were in this bag.———————-

These beans are white.—————————

All the beans in the bag were white. | |

| | |

Which is but an inversion of the deductive | | |

syllogism. | | |

| | |

Rule.—All the beans in the bag were white.—+ | |

Case.—These beans were in the bag.——————+-+

Result.—These beans are white.————————+

So that induction is the inference of therulefrom thecaseandresult.

But this is not the only way of inverting a deductive syllogism so as to produce a synthetic inference. Suppose I enter a room and there find a number of bags, containing different kinds of beans. On the table there is a handful of white beans; and, after some searching, I find one of the bags contains white beans only. I at once infer as a probability, or as a fair guess, that this handful was taken out of that bag. This sort of inference is calledmaking an hypothesis.[52]It is the inference of acasefrom aruleandresult. We have, then—

Deduction.Rule.—All the beans from this bag are white.Case.—These beans are from this bag.∴Result.—These beans are white.

Deduction.Rule.—All the beans from this bag are white.Case.—These beans are from this bag.∴Result.—These beans are white.

Deduction.

Deduction.

Rule.—All the beans from this bag are white.

Rule.—All the beans from this bag are white.

Case.—These beans are from this bag.

Case.—These beans are from this bag.

∴Result.—These beans are white.

∴Result.—These beans are white.

Induction.Case.—These beans are from this bag.Result.—These beans are white.∴Rule.—All the beans from this bag are white.

Induction.Case.—These beans are from this bag.Result.—These beans are white.∴Rule.—All the beans from this bag are white.

Induction.

Induction.

Case.—These beans are from this bag.

Case.—These beans are from this bag.

Result.—These beans are white.

Result.—These beans are white.

∴Rule.—All the beans from this bag are white.

∴Rule.—All the beans from this bag are white.

Hypothesis.Rule.—All the beans from this bag are white.Result.—These beans are white.∴Case.—These beans are from this bag.

Hypothesis.Rule.—All the beans from this bag are white.Result.—These beans are white.∴Case.—These beans are from this bag.

Hypothesis.

Hypothesis.

Rule.—All the beans from this bag are white.

Rule.—All the beans from this bag are white.

Result.—These beans are white.

Result.—These beans are white.

∴Case.—These beans are from this bag.

∴Case.—These beans are from this bag.

We, accordingly, classify all inference as follows:

Inference./——————————————-|Deductive or Analytic. Synthetic./—————————|Induction. Hypothesis.

Inference./——————————————-|Deductive or Analytic. Synthetic./—————————|Induction. Hypothesis.

Inference./——————————————-|Deductive or Analytic. Synthetic./—————————|Induction. Hypothesis.

Inference.

/——————————————-|

Deductive or Analytic. Synthetic.

/—————————|

Induction. Hypothesis.

Induction is where we generalize from a number of cases of which something is true, and infer that the same thing is true of a whole class. Or, where we find a certain thing to be true of a certain proportion of cases and infer that it is true of the same proportion of the whole class. Hypothesis is where we find some very curious circumstance, which would be explained by the supposition that it was a case of a certain general rule, and thereupon adopt that supposition. Or, where we find that in certain respects two objects have a strong resemblance, and infer that they resemble one another strongly in other respects.

I once landed at a seaport in a Turkish province; and, as I was walking up to the house which I was to visit, I met a man upon horseback, surrounded by four horsemen holding a canopy over his head. As the governor of the province was the only personage I could think of who would be so greatly honored, I inferred that this was he. This was an hypothesis.

Fossils are found; say, remains like those of fishes, but far in the interior of the country. To explain the phenomenon, we suppose the sea once washed over this land. This is another hypothesis.

Numberless documents and monuments refer to a conqueror called Napoleon Bonaparte. Though we have not seen the man, yet we cannot explain what we have seen, namely, all these documents and monuments, without supposing that he really existed. Hypothesis again.

As a general rule, hypothesis is a weak kind of argument. It often inclines our judgment so slightly toward its conclusion that we cannot say that we believe the latter tobe true; we only surmise that it may be so. But there is no difference except one of degree between such an inference and that by which we are led to believe that we remember the occurrences of yesterday from our feeling as if we did so.

Besides the way just pointed out of inverting a deductive syllogism to produce an induction or hypothesis, there is another. If from the truth of a certain premise the truth of a certain conclusion would necessarily follow, then from the falsity of the conclusion the falsity of the premise would follow. Thus, take the following syllogism inBarbara:

Rule.—All men are mortal.Case.—Enoch and Elijah were men.∴Result.—Enoch and Elijah were mortal.

Rule.—All men are mortal.Case.—Enoch and Elijah were men.∴Result.—Enoch and Elijah were mortal.

Rule.—All men are mortal.

Rule.—All men are mortal.

Case.—Enoch and Elijah were men.

Case.—Enoch and Elijah were men.

∴Result.—Enoch and Elijah were mortal.

∴Result.—Enoch and Elijah were mortal.

Now, a person who denies this result may admit the rule, and, in that case, he must deny the case. Thus:

Denial of Result.—Enoch and Elijah were not mortal.Rule.—All men are mortal.∴Denial of Case.—Enoch and Elijah were not men.

Denial of Result.—Enoch and Elijah were not mortal.Rule.—All men are mortal.∴Denial of Case.—Enoch and Elijah were not men.

Denial of Result.—Enoch and Elijah were not mortal.

Denial of Result.—Enoch and Elijah were not mortal.

Rule.—All men are mortal.

Rule.—All men are mortal.

∴Denial of Case.—Enoch and Elijah were not men.

∴Denial of Case.—Enoch and Elijah were not men.

This kind of syllogism is calledBaroco, which is the typical mood of the second figure. On the other hand, the person who denies the result may admit the case, and in that case he must deny the rule. Thus:

Denial of the Result.—Enoch and Elijah were not mortal.Case.—Enoch and Elijah were men.∴Denial of the Rule.—Some men are not mortal.

Denial of the Result.—Enoch and Elijah were not mortal.Case.—Enoch and Elijah were men.∴Denial of the Rule.—Some men are not mortal.

Denial of the Result.—Enoch and Elijah were not mortal.

Denial of the Result.—Enoch and Elijah were not mortal.

Case.—Enoch and Elijah were men.

Case.—Enoch and Elijah were men.

∴Denial of the Rule.—Some men are not mortal.

∴Denial of the Rule.—Some men are not mortal.

This kind of syllogism is calledBocardo, which is the typical mood of the third figure.

BarocoandBocardoare, of course, deductive syllogisms; but of a very peculiar kind. They are called by logicians indirect moods, because they need some transformation to appear as the application of a rule to a particular case. But if, instead of setting out as we have here done with a necessary deduction inBarbara, we take a probable deduction of similar form, the indirect moods which we shall obtain will be—


Back to IndexNext