Fig. 36.
We shall now use these simple cases for illustrating the principle by which capacity and potential are determined. First, it is clear that we can use the jar composed of concentric spheres with its known capacity as our unit jar and by means of this ascertain, in the manner above laid down, the capacity of any given jarF. We find, for example, that 37 discharges of this unit jar of the capacity 100, just charges the jar investigated at the same striking distance, that is, at the same potential. Hence, the capacity of the jar investigated is 3700 centimetres. The large battery of the Prague physical laboratory, which consists of sixteen such jars, all of nearly equal size, has a capacity, therefore, of something like 50,000 centimetres, or the capacity of a sphere, a kilometre in diameter, freely suspended in atmospheric space. This remark distinctly shows us the great superiority which Leyden jars possess for the storage of electricity as compared with common conductors. In fact, as Faraday pointed out, jars differ from simple conductors mainly by their great capacity.
Fig. 37.
For determining potential, imagine the inner coating of a jarF, the outer coating of which communicates with the ground, connected by a long, thin wire with a conductive sphereKplaced free in a large atmospheric space, compared with whose dimensions the radius of the sphere vanishes. (Fig. 37.) The jar and the sphere assume at once the same potential. But on the surface of the sphere, if that be sufficiently far removed from all other conductors, a uniform layer of electricity will be found. If the sphere, having the radiusr, contains the chargeq, its potential isV=q/r. If the upper half of the sphere be severed from the lower half and equilibrated on a balance with one of whose beams it is connected by silk threads, the upper half will be repelled from the lower half with the forceP=q2/8r2= 1/8V2. This repulsionPmay be counter-balanced by additional weights placed on the beam-end, and so ascertained. The potential is thenV= √(8P).[35]
That the potential is proportional to the square root of the force is not difficult to see. A doubling or trebling of the potential means that the charge of all the parts is doubled or trebled; hence their combined power of repulsion quadrupled or nonupled.
Let us consider a special case. I wish to produce the potential 40 on the sphere. What additional weight must I give to the half sphere in grammes that the force of repulsion shall maintain the balance in exact equilibrium? As a gramme weight is approximately equivalent to 1000 units of force, we have only the following simple example to work out: 40×40 = 8× 1000.x, wherexstands for the number of grammes. In round numbers we getx= 0.2 gramme. I charge the jar. The balance is deflected; I have reached, or rather passed, the potential 40, and you see when I discharge the jar the associated spark.[36]
The striking distance between the knobs of a machine increases with the difference of the potential, although not proportionately to that difference. The striking distance increases faster than the potential difference. For a distance between the knobs of one centimetre on this machine the difference of potential is 110. It can easily be increased tenfold. Of the tremendous differences of potential which occur in nature some idea may be obtained from the fact that the striking distances of lightning in thunder-storms is counted by miles. The differences of potential in galvanic batteries are considerably smaller than those of our machine, for it takes fully one hundred elements to give a spark of microscopic striking distance.
We shall now employ the ideas reached to shed some light upon another important relation between electrical and mechanical phenomena. We shall investigate what is the potentialenergy, or thestore of work, contained in a charged conductor, for example, in a jar.
If we bring a quantity of electricity up to a conductor, or, to speak less pictorially, if we generate by work electrical force in a conductor, this force is able to produce anew the work by which it was generated. How great, now, is the energy or capacity for work of a conductor of known chargeQand known potentialV?
Imagine the given chargeQdivided into very small partsq,q1,q2..., and these little parts successively carried up to the conductor. The first very small quantityqis brought up without any appreciable work and produces by its presence a small potentialV'. To bring up the second quantity, accordingly, we must do the workq'V', and similarly for the quantities which follow the workq''V'',q'''V''', and so forth. Now, as the potential rises proportionately to the quantities added until the valueVis reached, we have, agreeably to the graphical representation of Fig. 38, for the total work performed,
W= 1/2QV,
which corresponds to the total energy of the charged conductor. Using the equationQ=CV, whereCstands for capacity, we also have,
W= 1/2CV2, orW=Q2/2C.
It will be helpful, perhaps, to elucidate this idea by an analogy from the province of mechanics. If we pump a quantity of liquid,Q, gradually into a cylindrical vessel (Fig. 39), the level of the liquid in the vessel will gradually rise. The more we have pumped in, the greater the pressure we must overcome, or the higher the level to which we must lift the liquid. The stored-up work is rendered again available when the heavy liquidQ, which reaches up to the levelh, flows out. This workWcorresponds to the fall of the whole liquid weightQ, through the distanceh/2 or through the altitude of its centre of gravity. We have
W= 1/2Qh.
Further, sinceQ=Kh, or since the weight of the liquid and the heighthare proportional, we get also
W= 1/2Kh2andW=Q2/2K.
Fig. 38.
Fig. 39.
As a special case let us consider our jar. Its capacity isC= 3700, its potentialV= 110; accordingly, its quantityQ=CV= 407,000 electrostatic units and its energyW= 1/2QV= 22,385,000 C. G. S. units of work.
The unit of work of the C. G. S. system is not readily appreciable by the senses, nor does it well admit of representation, as we are accustomed to work with weights. Let us adopt, therefore, as our unit of work the gramme-centimetre, or the gravitational pressure of a gramme-weight through the distance of a centimetre, which in round numbers is 1000 times greater than the unit assumed above; in this case, our numerical result will be approximately 1000 times smaller. Again, if we pass, as more familiar in practice, to the kilogramme-metre as our unit of work, our unit, the distance being increased a hundred fold, and the weight a thousand fold, will be 100,000 times larger. The numerical result expressing the work done is in this case 100,000 times less, being in round numbers 0.22 kilogramme-metre. We can obtain a clear idea of the work done here by letting a kilogramme-weight fall 22 centimetres.
This amount of work, accordingly, is performed on the charging of the jar, and on its discharge appears again, according to the circumstances, partly as sound, partly as a mechanical disruption of insulators, partly as light and heat, and so forth.
The large battery of the Prague physical laboratory, with its sixteen jars charged to equal potentials, furnishes, although the effect of the discharge is imposing, a total amount of work of only three kilogramme-metres.
In the development of the ideas above laid down we are not restricted to the method there pursued; in fact, that method was selected only as one especially fitted to familiarise us with the phenomena. On the contrary, the connexion of the physical processes is so multifarious that we can come at the same event from very different directions. Particularly are electrical phenomena connected with all other physical events; and so intimate is this connexion that we might justly call the study of electricity the theory of the general connexion of physical processes.
With respect to the principle of the conservation of energy which unites electrical with mechanical phenomena, I should like to point out briefly two ways of following up the study of this connexion.
A few years ago Professor Rosetti, taking an influence-machine, which he set in motion by means of weights alternately in the electrical and non-electrical condition with the same velocities, determined the mechanical work expended in the two cases and was thus enabled, after deducting the work of friction, to ascertain the mechanical work consumed in the development of the electricity.
I myself have made this experiment in a modified, and, as I think, more advantageous form. Instead of determining the work of friction by special trial, I arranged my apparatus so that it was eliminated of itself in the measurement and could consequently be neglected. The so-called fixed disk of the machine, the axis of which is placed vertically, is suspended somewhat like a chandelier by three vertical threads of equal lengthslat a distancerfrom the axis. Only when the machine is excited does this fixed disk, which represents a Prony's brake, receive, through its reciprocal action with the rotating disk, a deflexionαand a moment of torsion which is expressed byD=(Pr2/l)α, wherePis the weight of the disk.[37]The angleαis determined by a mirror set in the disk. The work expended innrotations is given by2nπD.
If we close the machine, as Rosetti did, we obtain a continuous current which has all the properties of a very weak galvanic current; for example, it produces a deflexion in a multiplier which we interpose, and so forth. We can directly ascertain, now, the mechanical work expended in the maintenance of this current.
If we charge a jar by means of a machine, the energy of the jar employed in the production of sparks, in the disruption of the insulators, etc., corresponds to a part only of the mechanical work expended, a second part of it being consumed in the arc which forms the circuit.[38]This machine, with the interposed jar, affords in miniature a picture of the transference of force, or more properly of work. And in fact nearly the same laws hold here for the economical coefficient as obtain for large dynamo-machines.
Another means of investigating electrical energy is by its transformation into heat. A long time ago (1838), before the mechanical theory of heat had attained its present popularity, Riess performed experiments in this field with the help of his electrical air-thermometer or thermo-electrometer.
Fig. 40.
If the discharge be conducted through a fine wire passing through the globe of the air-thermometer, a development of heat is observed proportional to the expression above-discussedW= 1/2QV. Although the total energy has not yet been transformed into measurable heat by this means, in as much as a portion is left behind in the spark in the air outside the thermometer, still everything tends to show that the total heat developed in all parts of the conductor and along all the paths of discharge is the equivalent of the work 1/2QV.
It is not important here whether the electrical energy is transformed all at once or partly, by degrees. For example, if of two equal jars one is charged with the quantityQat the potentialVthe energy present is 1/2QV. If the first jar be discharged into the second,V, since the capacity is now doubled, falls toV/2. Accordingly, the energy 1/4QVremains, while 1/4QVis transformed in the spark of discharge into heat. The remainder, however, is equally distributed between the two jars so that each on discharge is still able to transform 1/8QVinto heat.
We have here discussed electricity in the limited phenomenal form in which it was known to the inquirers before Volta, and which has been called, perhaps not very felicitously, "statical electricity." It is evident, however, that the nature of electricity is everywhere one and the same; that a substantial difference between statical and galvanic electricity does not exist. Only the quantitative circumstances in the two provinces are so widely different that totally new aspects of phenomena may appear in the second, for example, magnetic effects, which in the first remained unnoticed, whilst,vice versa, in the second field statical attractions and repulsions are scarcely appreciable. As a fact, we can easily show the magnetic effect of the current of discharge of an influence-machine on the galvanoscope although we could hardly have made the original discovery of the magnetic effects with this current. The statical distant action of the wire poles of a galvanic element also would hardly have been noticed had not the phenomenon been known from a different quarter in a striking form.
If we wished to characterise the two fields in their chief and most general features, we should say that in the first, high potentials and small quantities come into play, in the second small potentials and large quantities. A jar which is discharging and a galvanic element deport themselves somewhat like an air-gun and the bellows of an organ. The first gives forth suddenly under a very high pressure a small quantity of air; the latter liberates gradually under a very slight pressure a large quantity of air.
In point of principle, too, nothing prevents our retaining the electrostatical units in the domain of galvanic electricity and in measuring, for example, the strength of a current by the number of electrostatic units which flow per second through its cross-section. But this would be in a double aspect impractical. In the first place, we should totally neglect the magnetic facilities for measurement so conveniently offered by the current, and substitute for this easy means a method which can be applied only with difficulty and is not capable of great exactness. In the second place our units would be much too small, and we should find ourselves in the predicament of the astronomer who attempted to measure celestial distances in metres instead of in radii of the earth and the earth's orbit; for the current which by the magnetic C. G. S. standard represents the unit, would require a flow of some 30,000,000,000 electrostatic units per second through its cross-section. Accordingly, different units must be adopted here. The development of this point, however, lies beyond my present task.
In a popular lecture, distinguished for its charming simplicity and clearness, which Joule delivered in the year 1847,[40]that famous physicist declares that the living force which a heavy body has acquired by its descent through a certain height and which it carries with it in the form of the velocity with which it is impressed, is theequivalentof the attraction of gravity through the space fallen through, and that it would be "absurd" to assume that this living force could be destroyed without some restitution of that equivalent. He then adds: "You will therefore be surprised to hear that until veryrecentlythe universal opinion has been that living force could be absolutely and irrevocably destroyed at any one's option." Let us add that to-day, after forty-seven years, thelaw of the conservation of energy, wherever civilisation exists, is accepted as a fully established truth and receives the widest applications in all domains of natural science.
The fate of all momentous discoveries is similar. On their first appearance they are regarded by the majority of men as errors. J. R. Mayer's work on the principle of energy (1842) was rejected by the first physical journal of Germany; Helmholtz's treatise (1847) met with no better success; and even Joule, to judge from an intimation of Playfair, seems to have encountered difficulties with his first publication (1843). Gradually, however, people are led to see that the new view was long prepared for and ready for enunciation, only that a few favored minds had perceived it much earlier than the rest, and in this way the opposition of the majority is overcome. With proofs of the fruitfulness of the new view, with its success, confidence in it increases. The majority of the men who employ it cannot enter into a deep-going analysis of it; for them, its success is its proof. It can thus happen that a view which has led to the greatest discoveries, like Black's theory of caloric, in a subsequent period in a province where it does not apply may actually become an obstacle to progress by its blinding our eyes to facts which do not fit in with our favorite conceptions. If a theory is to be protected from this dubious rôle, the grounds and motives of its evolution and existence must be examined from time to time with the utmost care.
The most multifarious physical changes, thermal,electrical, chemical, and so forth, can be brought about by mechanical work. When such alterations are reversed they yield anew the mechanical work in exactly the quantity which was required for the production of the part reversed. This is theprinciple of the conservation of energy; "energy" being the term which has gradually come into use for that "indestructible something" of which the measure is mechanicalwork.
How did we acquire this idea? What are the sources from which we have drawn it? This question is not only of interest in itself, but also for the important reason above touched upon. The opinions which are held concerning the foundations of the law of energy still diverge very widely from one another. Many trace the principle to the impossibility of a perpetual motion, which they regard either as sufficiently proved by experience, or as self-evident. In the province of pure mechanics the impossibility of a perpetual motion, or the continuous production ofworkwithout somepermanentalteration, is easily demonstrated. Accordingly, if we start from the theory that all physical processes are purelymechanicalprocesses, motions of molecules and atoms, we embrace also, by thismechanicalconception of physics, the impossibility of a perpetual motion in thewholephysical domain. At present this view probably counts the most adherents. Other inquirers, however, are for accepting only a purelyexperimentalestablishment of the law of energy.
It will appear, from the discussion to follow, thatallthe factors mentioned have co-operated in the development of the view in question; but that in addition to them a logical and purely formal factor, hitherto little considered, has also played a very important part.
The law of energy in its modern form is not identical with the principle of the excluded perpetual motion, but it is very closely related to it. The latter principle, however, is by no means new, for in the province of mechanics it has controlled for centuries the thoughts and investigations of the greatest thinkers. Let us convince ourselves of this by the study of a few historical examples.
Fig. 41.
S. Stevinus, in his famous workHypomnemata mathematica, Tom. IV,De statica, (Leyden, 1605, p. 34), treats of the equilibrium of bodies on inclined planes.
Over a triangular prismABC, one side of which,AC, is horizontal, an endless cord or chain is slung, to which at equal distances apart fourteen balls of equal weight are attached, as represented in cross-section in Figure 41. Since we can imagine the lowersymmetrical part of the cordABCtaken away, Stevinus concludes that the four balls onABhold in equilibrium the two balls onBC. For if the equilibrium were for a moment disturbed, it could never subsist: the cord would keep moving round forever in the same direction,—we should have a perpetual motion. He says:
"But if this took place, our row or ring of balls would come once more into their original position, and from the same cause the eight globes to the left would again be heavier than the six to the right, and therefore those eight would sink a second time and these six rise, and all the globes would keep up, of themselves,a continuous and unending motion, which is false."[41]
"But if this took place, our row or ring of balls would come once more into their original position, and from the same cause the eight globes to the left would again be heavier than the six to the right, and therefore those eight would sink a second time and these six rise, and all the globes would keep up, of themselves,a continuous and unending motion, which is false."[41]
Stevinus, now, easily derives from this principle the laws of equilibrium on the inclined plane and numerous other fruitful consequences.
In the chapter "Hydrostatics" of the same work, page 114, Stevinus sets up the following principle: "Aquam datam, datum sibi intra aquam locum servare,"—a given mass of water preserves within water its given place.
Fig. 42.
This principle is demonstrated as follows (see Fig. 42):
"For, assuming it to be possible by natural means, let us suppose that A does not preserve the place assigned to it, but sinks down to D. This being posited, the water which succeeds A will, for the same reason, also flow down toD;Awill be forced out of its place inD; and thus this body of water, for the conditions in it are everywhere the same,will set up a perpetual motion, which is absurd."[42]
"For, assuming it to be possible by natural means, let us suppose that A does not preserve the place assigned to it, but sinks down to D. This being posited, the water which succeeds A will, for the same reason, also flow down toD;Awill be forced out of its place inD; and thus this body of water, for the conditions in it are everywhere the same,will set up a perpetual motion, which is absurd."[42]
From this all the principles of hydrostatics are deduced. On this occasion Stevinus also first develops the thought so fruitful for modern analytical mechanics that the equilibrium of a system is not destroyed by the addition of rigid connexions. As we know, the principle of the conservation of the centre of gravity is now sometimes deduced from D'Alembert's principle with the help of that remark. If we were to reproduce Stevinus's demonstration to-day, we should have to change it slightly. We find no difficulty in imagining the cord on the prism possessed of unending uniform motion if all hindrances are thought away, but we should protest against the assumption of an accelerated motion or even against that of a uniform motion, if the resistances were not removed. Moreover, for greater precision of proof, the string of balls might be replaced by a heavy homogeneous cord of infinite flexibility. But all this does not affect in the least the historical value of Stevinus's thoughts. It is a fact, Stevinus deduces apparently much simpler truths from the principle of an impossible perpetual motion.
In the process of thought which conducted Galileo to his discoveries at the end of the sixteenth century, the following principle plays an important part, that a body in virtue of the velocity acquired in its descent can rise exactly as high as it fell. This principle, which appears frequently and with much clearness in Galileo's thought, is simply another form of the principle of excluded perpetual motion, as we shall see it is also in Huygens.
Galileo, as we know, arrived at the law of uniformly accelerated motion bya prioriconsiderations, as that law which was the "simplest and most natural," after having first assumed a different law which he was compelled to reject. To verify his law he executed experiments with falling bodies on inclined planes, measuring the times of descent by the weights of the water which flowed out of a small orifice in a large vessel. In this experiment he assumes as a fundamental principle, that the velocity acquired in descent down an inclined plane always corresponds to the vertical height descended through, a conclusion which for him is the immediate outcome of the fact that a body which has fallen down one inclined plane can, with the velocity it has acquired, rise on another plane of any inclination only to the same vertical height. This principle of the height of ascent also led him, as it seems, to the law of inertia. Let us hear his own masterful words in theDialogo terzo(Opere, Padova, 1744, Tom. III). On page 96 we read:
"I take it for granted that the velocities acquired by a body in descent down planes of different inclinations are equal if the heights of those planes are equal."[43]
"I take it for granted that the velocities acquired by a body in descent down planes of different inclinations are equal if the heights of those planes are equal."[43]
Then he makes Salviati say in the dialogue:[44]
"What you say seems very probable, but I wish to go further and by an experiment so to increase the probability of it that it shall amount almost to absolute demonstration. Suppose this sheet of paper to be a vertical wall, and from a nail driven in it a ball of lead weighing two or three ounces to hang by a very fine threadABfour or five feet long. (Fig. 43.) On the wall mark a horizontal lineDCperpendicular to the verticalAB, which latter ought to hang about two inches from the wall. If now the threadABwith the ball attached take the positionACand the ball be let go, you will see the ball first descend through the arcCBand passing beyondBrise through the arcBDalmost to the level of the lineCD, being prevented from reaching it exactly by the resistance of the air and of the thread. From this we may truly conclude that its impetus at the pointB, acquired by its descent through the arcCB, is sufficient to urge it through a similar arcBDto the same height. Having performed this experiment and repeated it several times, let us drive in the wall, in the projection of the verticalAB, as atEor atF, a nail five or six inches long, so that the threadAC, carrying as before the ball through the arcCB, at the moment it reaches the positionAB, shall strike the nailE, and the ball be thus compelled to move up the arcBGdescribed aboutEas centre. Then we shall see what the same impetus will here accomplish, acquired now as before at the same pointB, which then drove the same moving body through the arcBDto the height of the horizontalCD. Now gentlemen, you will be pleased to see the ball rise to the horizontal line at the pointG, and the same thing also happen if the nail be placed lower as atF, in which case the ball would describe the arcBJ, always terminating its ascent precisely at the lineCD. If the nail be placed so low that the length of thread below it does not reach to the height ofCD(which would happen ifFwere nearerBthan to the intersection ofABwith the horizontalCD), then the thread will wind itself about the nail. This experiment leaves no room for doubt as to the truth of the supposition. For as the two arcsCB,DBare equal and similarly situated, the momentum acquired in the descent of the arcCBis the same as that acquired in the descent of the arcDB; but the momentum acquired atBby the descent through the arcCBis capable of driving up the same moving body through the arcBD; hence also the momentum acquired in the descentDBis equal to that which drives the same moving body through the same arc fromBtoD, so that in general every momentum acquired in the descent of an arc is equal to that which causes the same moving body to ascend through the same arc; but all the momenta which cause the ascent of all the arcsBD,BG,BJ, are equal since they are made by the same momentum acquired in the descentCB, as the experiment shows: therefore all the momenta acquired in the descent of the arcsDB,GB,JBare equal."
"What you say seems very probable, but I wish to go further and by an experiment so to increase the probability of it that it shall amount almost to absolute demonstration. Suppose this sheet of paper to be a vertical wall, and from a nail driven in it a ball of lead weighing two or three ounces to hang by a very fine threadABfour or five feet long. (Fig. 43.) On the wall mark a horizontal lineDCperpendicular to the verticalAB, which latter ought to hang about two inches from the wall. If now the threadABwith the ball attached take the positionACand the ball be let go, you will see the ball first descend through the arcCBand passing beyondBrise through the arcBDalmost to the level of the lineCD, being prevented from reaching it exactly by the resistance of the air and of the thread. From this we may truly conclude that its impetus at the pointB, acquired by its descent through the arcCB, is sufficient to urge it through a similar arcBDto the same height. Having performed this experiment and repeated it several times, let us drive in the wall, in the projection of the verticalAB, as atEor atF, a nail five or six inches long, so that the threadAC, carrying as before the ball through the arcCB, at the moment it reaches the positionAB, shall strike the nailE, and the ball be thus compelled to move up the arcBGdescribed aboutEas centre. Then we shall see what the same impetus will here accomplish, acquired now as before at the same pointB, which then drove the same moving body through the arcBDto the height of the horizontalCD. Now gentlemen, you will be pleased to see the ball rise to the horizontal line at the pointG, and the same thing also happen if the nail be placed lower as atF, in which case the ball would describe the arcBJ, always terminating its ascent precisely at the lineCD. If the nail be placed so low that the length of thread below it does not reach to the height ofCD(which would happen ifFwere nearerBthan to the intersection ofABwith the horizontalCD), then the thread will wind itself about the nail. This experiment leaves no room for doubt as to the truth of the supposition. For as the two arcsCB,DBare equal and similarly situated, the momentum acquired in the descent of the arcCBis the same as that acquired in the descent of the arcDB; but the momentum acquired atBby the descent through the arcCBis capable of driving up the same moving body through the arcBD; hence also the momentum acquired in the descentDBis equal to that which drives the same moving body through the same arc fromBtoD, so that in general every momentum acquired in the descent of an arc is equal to that which causes the same moving body to ascend through the same arc; but all the momenta which cause the ascent of all the arcsBD,BG,BJ, are equal since they are made by the same momentum acquired in the descentCB, as the experiment shows: therefore all the momenta acquired in the descent of the arcsDB,GB,JBare equal."
Fig. 43.
The remark relative to the pendulum may be applied to the inclined plane and leads to the law of inertia. We read on page 124:[45]
"It is plain now that a movable body, starting from rest atAand descending down the inclined planeAB, acquires a velocity proportional to the increment of its time: the velocity possessed atBis the greatest of the velocities acquired, and by its nature immutably impressed, provided all causes of new acceleration or retardation are taken away: I say acceleration, having in view its possible further progress along the plane extended; retardation, in view of the possibility of its being reversed and made to mount the ascending planeBC. But in the horizontal planeGHits equable motion, according to its velocity as acquired in the descent fromAtoB, will be continuedad infinitum." (Fig. 44.)
"It is plain now that a movable body, starting from rest atAand descending down the inclined planeAB, acquires a velocity proportional to the increment of its time: the velocity possessed atBis the greatest of the velocities acquired, and by its nature immutably impressed, provided all causes of new acceleration or retardation are taken away: I say acceleration, having in view its possible further progress along the plane extended; retardation, in view of the possibility of its being reversed and made to mount the ascending planeBC. But in the horizontal planeGHits equable motion, according to its velocity as acquired in the descent fromAtoB, will be continuedad infinitum." (Fig. 44.)
Fig. 44.
Huygens, upon whose shoulders the mantel of Galileo fell, forms a sharper conception of the law of inertia and generalises the principle respecting the heights of ascent which was so fruitful in Galileo's hands. He employs the latter principle in the solution of the problem of the centre of oscillation and is perfectly clear in the statement that the principle respecting the heights of ascent is identical with the principle of the excluded perpetual motion.
The following important passages then occur (Hugenii,Horologium oscillatorium, pars secunda).Hypotheses:
"If gravity did not exist, nor the atmosphere obstruct the motions of bodies, a body would keep up forever the motion once impressed upon it, with equable velocity, in a straight line."[46]
"If gravity did not exist, nor the atmosphere obstruct the motions of bodies, a body would keep up forever the motion once impressed upon it, with equable velocity, in a straight line."[46]
In part four of theHorologium de centro oscillationiswe read:
"If any number of weights be set in motion by the force of gravity, the common centre of gravity of the weights as a whole cannot possibly rise higher than the place which it occupied when the motion began."That this hypothesis of ours may arouse no scruples, we will state that it simply imports, what no one has ever denied, that heavy bodies do not moveupwards.—And truly if the devisers of the new machines who make such futile attempts to construct a perpetual motion would acquaint themselves with this principle, they could easily be brought to see their errors and to understand that the thing is utterly impossible by mechanical means."[47]
"If any number of weights be set in motion by the force of gravity, the common centre of gravity of the weights as a whole cannot possibly rise higher than the place which it occupied when the motion began.
"That this hypothesis of ours may arouse no scruples, we will state that it simply imports, what no one has ever denied, that heavy bodies do not moveupwards.—And truly if the devisers of the new machines who make such futile attempts to construct a perpetual motion would acquaint themselves with this principle, they could easily be brought to see their errors and to understand that the thing is utterly impossible by mechanical means."[47]
There is possibly a Jesuitical mental reservation contained in the words "mechanical means." One might be led to believe from them that Huygens held a non-mechanical perpetual motion for possible.
The generalisation of Galileo's principle is still more clearly put in Prop. IV of the same chapter:
"If a pendulum, composed of several weights, set in motion from rest, complete any part of its full oscillation, and from that point onwards, the individual weights, with their common connexions dissolved, change their acquired velocities upwards and ascend as far as they can, the common centre of gravity of all will be carried up to the same altitude with that which it occupied before the beginning of the oscillation."[48]
"If a pendulum, composed of several weights, set in motion from rest, complete any part of its full oscillation, and from that point onwards, the individual weights, with their common connexions dissolved, change their acquired velocities upwards and ascend as far as they can, the common centre of gravity of all will be carried up to the same altitude with that which it occupied before the beginning of the oscillation."[48]
On this last principle now, which is a generalisation, applied to a system of masses, of one of Galileo's ideas respecting a single mass and which from Huygens's explanation we recognise as the principle of excluded perpetual motion, Huygens grounds his theory of the centre of oscillation. Lagrange characterises this principle as precarious and is rejoiced at James Bernoulli's successful attempt, in 1681, to reduce the theory of the centre of oscillation to the laws of the lever, which appeared to him clearer. All the great inquirers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries broke a lance on this problem, and it led ultimately, in conjunction with the principle of virtual velocities, to the principle enunciated by D'Alembert in 1743 in hisTraité de dynamique, though previously employed in a somewhat different form by Euler and Hermann.
Furthermore, the Huygenian principle respecting the heights of ascent became the foundation of the "law of the conservation of living force," as that was enunciated by John and Daniel Bernoulli and employedwith such signal success by the latter in hisHydrodynamics. The theorems of the Bernoullis differ in form only from Lagrange's expression in theAnalytical Mechanics.
The manner in which Torricelli reached his famous law of efflux for liquids leads again to our principle. Torricelli assumed that the liquid which flows out of the basal orifice of a vessel cannot by its velocity of efflux ascend to a greater height than its level in the vessel.
Let us next consider a point which belongs to pure mechanics, the history of the principle ofvirtual motionsorvirtual velocities. This principle was not first enunciated, as is usually stated, and as Lagrange also asserts, by Galileo, but earlier, by Stevinus. In hisTrochleostaticaof the above-cited work, page 72, he says:
"Observe that this axiom of statics holds good here:"As the space of the body acting is to the space of the body acted upon, so is the power of the body acted upon to the power of the body acting."[49]
"Observe that this axiom of statics holds good here:
"As the space of the body acting is to the space of the body acted upon, so is the power of the body acted upon to the power of the body acting."[49]
Galileo, as we know, recognised the truth of the principle in the consideration of the simple machines, and also deduced the laws of the equilibrium of liquids from it.
Torricelli carries the principle back to the properties of the centre of gravity. The condition controllingequilibrium in a simple machine, in which power and load are represented by weights, is that the common centre of gravity of the weights shall not sink. Conversely, if the centre of gravity cannot sink equilibrium obtains, because heavy bodies of themselves do not move upwards. In this form the principle of virtual velocities is identical with Huygens's principle of the impossibility of a perpetual motion.
John Bernoulli, in 1717, first perceived the universal import of the principle of virtual movements for all systems; a discovery stated in a letter to Varignon. Finally, Lagrange gives a general demonstration of the principle and founds upon it his wholeAnalytical Mechanics. But this general demonstration is based after all upon Huygens and Torricelli's remarks. Lagrange, as is known, conceives simple pulleys arranged in the directions of the forces of the system, passes a cord through these pulleys, and appends to its free extremity a weight which is a common measure of all the forces of the system. With no difficulty, now, the number of elements of each pulley may be so chosen that the forces in question shall be replaced by them. It is then clear that if the weight at the extremity cannot sink, equilibrium subsists, because heavy bodies cannot of themselves move upwards. If we do not go so far, but wish to abide by Torricelli's idea, we may conceive every individual force of the system replaced by a special weight suspended from a cord passing over a pulley in the direction of the force and attachedat its point of application. Equilibrium subsists then when the common centre of gravity of all the weights together cannot sink. The fundamental supposition of this demonstration is plainly the impossibility of a perpetual motion.
Lagrange tried in every way to supply a proof free from extraneous elements and fully satisfactory, but without complete success. Nor were his successors more fortunate.
The whole of mechanics, thus, is based upon an idea, which, though unequivocal, is yet unwonted and not coequal with the other principles and axioms of mechanics. Every student of mechanics, at some stage of his progress, feels the uncomfortableness of this state of affairs; every one wishes it removed; but seldom is the difficulty stated in words. Accordingly, the zealous pupil of the science is highly rejoiced when he reads in a master like Poinsot (Théorie générale de l'équilibre et du mouvement des systèmes) the following passage, in which that author is giving his opinion of theAnalytical Mechanics:
"In the meantime, because our attention in that work was first wholly engrossed with the consideration of its beautiful development of mechanics, which seemed to spring complete from a single formula, we naturally believed that the science was completed or that it only remained to seek the demonstration of the principle of virtual velocities. But that quest brought back all the difficulties that we had overcome by the principle itself. That law so general, wherein are mingled the vague and unfamiliar ideas of infinitely small movements and of perturbations of equilibrium, only grewobscure upon examination; and the work of Lagrange supplying nothing clearer than the march of analysis, we saw plainly that the clouds had only appeared lifted from the course of mechanics because they had, so to speak, been gathered at the very origin of that science."At bottom, a general demonstration of the principle of virtual velocities would be equivalent to the establishment of the whole of mechanics upon a different basis: for the demonstration of a law which embraces a whole science is neither more nor less than the reduction of that science to another law just as general, but evident, or at least more simple than the first, and which, consequently, would render that useless."[50]
"In the meantime, because our attention in that work was first wholly engrossed with the consideration of its beautiful development of mechanics, which seemed to spring complete from a single formula, we naturally believed that the science was completed or that it only remained to seek the demonstration of the principle of virtual velocities. But that quest brought back all the difficulties that we had overcome by the principle itself. That law so general, wherein are mingled the vague and unfamiliar ideas of infinitely small movements and of perturbations of equilibrium, only grewobscure upon examination; and the work of Lagrange supplying nothing clearer than the march of analysis, we saw plainly that the clouds had only appeared lifted from the course of mechanics because they had, so to speak, been gathered at the very origin of that science.
"At bottom, a general demonstration of the principle of virtual velocities would be equivalent to the establishment of the whole of mechanics upon a different basis: for the demonstration of a law which embraces a whole science is neither more nor less than the reduction of that science to another law just as general, but evident, or at least more simple than the first, and which, consequently, would render that useless."[50]
According to Poinsot, therefore, a proof of the principle of virtual movements is tantamount to a total rehabilitation of mechanics.
Another circumstance of discomfort to the mathematician is, that in the historical form in which mechanics at present exists, dynamics is founded on statics, whereas it is desirable that in a science which pretends to deductive completeness the more special statical theorems should be deducible from the more general dynamical principles.
In fact, a great master, Gauss, gave expression to this desire in his presentment of the principle of least constraint (Crelle'sJournal für reine und angewandte Mathematik, Vol. IV, p. 233) in the following words: "Proper as it is that in the gradual development of a science, and in the instruction of individuals, the easy should precede the difficult, the simple the complex, the special the general, yet the mind, when once it has reached a higher point of view, demands the contrary course, in which all statics shall appear simply as a special case of mechanics." Gauss's own principle, now, possesses all the requisites of universality, but its difficulty is that it is not immediately intelligible and that Gauss deduced it with the help of D'Alembert's principle, a procedure which left matters where they were before.
Whence, now, is derived this strange part which the principle of virtual motion plays in mechanics? For the present I shall only make this reply. It would be difficult for me to tell the difference of impression which Lagrange's proof of the principle made on me when I first took it up as a student and when I subsequently resumed it after having made historical researches. It first appeared to me insipid, chiefly on account of the pulleys and the cords which did not fit in with the mathematical view, and whose action I would much rather have discovered from the principleitself than have taken for granted. But now that I have studied the history of the science I cannot imagine a more beautiful demonstration.
In fact, through all mechanics it is this self-same principle of excluded perpetual motion which accomplishes almost all, which displeased Lagrange, but which he still had to employ, at least tacitly, in his own demonstration. If we give this principle its proper place and setting, the paradox is explained.
The principle of excluded perpetual motion is thus no new discovery; it has been the guiding idea, for three hundred years, of all the great inquirers. But the principle cannot properly bebasedupon mechanical perceptions. For long before the development of mechanics the conviction of its truth existed and even contributed to that development. Its power of conviction, therefore, must have more universal and deeper roots. We shall revert to this point.
It cannot be denied that an unmistakable tendency has prevailed, from Democritus to the present day, to explainallphysical eventsmechanically. Not to mention earlier obscure expressions of that tendency we read in Huygens the following:[51]
"There can be no doubt that light consists of themotionof a certain substance. For if we examine its production, we find that here on earth it is principally fire and flame which engender it, both of which contain beyond doubt bodies which are in rapid movement, since they dissolve and destroy many other bodies more solid than they: while if we regard its effects, we see that when light is accumulated, say by concave mirrors, it has the property of combustion just as fire has, that is to say, it disunites the parts of bodies, which is assuredly a proof ofmotion, at least in thetrue philosophy, in which the causes of all natural effects are conceived asmechanicalcauses. Which in my judgment must be accomplished or all hope of ever understanding physics renounced."[52]
"There can be no doubt that light consists of themotionof a certain substance. For if we examine its production, we find that here on earth it is principally fire and flame which engender it, both of which contain beyond doubt bodies which are in rapid movement, since they dissolve and destroy many other bodies more solid than they: while if we regard its effects, we see that when light is accumulated, say by concave mirrors, it has the property of combustion just as fire has, that is to say, it disunites the parts of bodies, which is assuredly a proof ofmotion, at least in thetrue philosophy, in which the causes of all natural effects are conceived asmechanicalcauses. Which in my judgment must be accomplished or all hope of ever understanding physics renounced."[52]
S. Carnot,[53]in introducing the principle of excluded perpetual motion into the theory of heat, makes the following apology:
"It will be objected here, perhaps, that a perpetual motion proved impossible forpurely mechanical actions, is perhaps not so when the influence ofheator of electricity is employed. But can phenomena of heat or electricity be thought of as due to anything else than tocertain motions of bodies, and as such must they not be subject to the general laws of mechanics?"[54]
"It will be objected here, perhaps, that a perpetual motion proved impossible forpurely mechanical actions, is perhaps not so when the influence ofheator of electricity is employed. But can phenomena of heat or electricity be thought of as due to anything else than tocertain motions of bodies, and as such must they not be subject to the general laws of mechanics?"[54]
These examples, which might be multiplied by quotations from recent literature indefinitely, show that a tendency to explain all things mechanically actually exists. This tendency is also intelligible. Mechanical events as simple motions in space and time best admit of observation and pursuit by the help of our highly organised senses. We reproduce mechanical processes almost without effort in our imagination. Pressure as a circumstance that produces motion is very familiar to us from daily experience. All changes which the individual personally produces in his environment, or humanity brings about by means of the arts in the world, are effected through the instrumentality ofmotions. Almost of necessity, therefore, motion appears to us as the most important physical factor. Moreover, mechanical properties may be discovered in all physical events. The sounding bell trembles, the heated body expands, the electrified body attracts other bodies. Why, therefore, should we not attempt to grasp all events under their mechanical aspect, since that is so easily apprehended and most accessible to observation and measurement? In fact, no objectionisto be made to the attempt to elucidate the properties of physical events by mechanicalanalogies.
But modern physics has proceededvery farin this direction. The point of view which Wundt represents in his excellent treatiseOn the Physical Axiomsis probablyshared by the majority of physicists. The axioms of physics which Wundt sets up are as follows:
1. All natural causes are motional causes.
2. Every motional cause lies outside the object moved.
3. All motional causes act in the direction of the straight line of junction, and so forth.
4. The effect of every cause persists.
5. Every effect involves an equal countereffect.
6. Every effect is equivalent to its cause.
These principles might be studied properly enough as fundamental principles of mechanics. But when they are set up as axioms of physics, their enunciation is simply tantamount to a negation of all events except motion.
According to Wundt, all changes of nature are mere changes of place. All causes are motional causes (page 26). Any discussion of the philosophical grounds on which Wundt supports his theory would lead us deep into the speculations of the Eleatics and the Herbartians. Change of place, Wundt holds, is theonlychange of a thing in which a thing remains identical with itself. If a thing changedqualitatively, we should be obliged to imagine that something was annihilated and something else created in its place, which is not to be reconciled with our idea of the identity of the object observed and of the indestructibility of matter. But we have only to remember that the Eleatics encountered difficulties of exactly the same sortin motion. Can we not also imagine that a thing is destroyed inoneplace and inanotheran exactly similar thing created? After all, do we really knowmorewhy a body leaves one place and appears in another, than why acoldbody growswarm? Granted that we had a perfect knowledge of the mechanical processes of nature, could we and should we, for that reason,put out of the worldall other processes that we do not understand? On this principle it would really be the simplest course to deny the existence of the whole world. This is the point at which the Eleatics ultimately arrived, and the school of Herbart stopped little short of the same goal.
Physics treated in this sense supplies us simply with a diagram of the world, in which we do not know reality again. It happens, in fact, to men who give themselves up to this view for many years, that the world of sense from which they start as a province of the greatest familiarity, suddenly becomes, in their eyes, the supreme "world-riddle."
Intelligible as it is, therefore, that the efforts of thinkers have always been bent upon the "reduction of all physical processes to the motions of atoms," it must yet be affirmed that this is a chimerical ideal. This ideal has often played an effective part in popular lectures, but in the workshop of the serious inquirer it has discharged scarcely the least function. What has really been achieved in mechanical physics is either theelucidationof physical processes by morefamiliarmechanical analogies, (for example, the theories of light and of electricity,) or the exactquantitativeascertainment of the connexion of mechanical processes with other physical processes, for example, the results of thermodynamics.
We can know only fromexperiencethat mechanical processes produce other physical transformations, orvice versa. The attention was first directed to the connexion of mechanical processes, especially the performance of work, with changes of thermal conditions by the invention of the steam-engine, and by its great technical importance. Technical interests and the need of scientific lucidity meeting in the mind of S. Carnot led to the remarkable development from which thermodynamics flowed. It is simplyan accident of historythat the development in question was not connected with the practical applications ofelectricity.
In the determination of the maximum quantity ofworkthat, generally, a heat-machine, or, to take a special case, a steam-engine, can perform with the expenditure of agivenamount of heat of combustion, Carnot is guided by mechanical analogies. A body can do work on being heated, by expanding under pressure. But to do this the body must receive heat from ahotterbody. Heat, therefore, to do work, must pass from a hotter body to a colder body, just as water must fall from a higher level to a lower level to put a mill-wheelin motion. Differences of temperature, accordingly, represent forces able to do work exactly as do differences of height in heavy bodies. Carnot pictures to himself an ideal process in which no heat flows away unused, that is, without doing work. With a given expenditure of heat, accordingly, this process furnishes the maximum of work. An analogue of the process would be a mill-wheel which scooping its water out of a higher level would slowly carry it to a lower level without the loss of a drop. A peculiar property of the process is, that with the expenditure of the same work the water can be raised again exactly to its original level. This property ofreversibilityis also shared by the process of Carnot. His process also can be reversed by the expenditure of the same amount of work, and the heat again brought back to its original temperature level.
Suppose, now, we hadtwodifferent reversible processesA,B, such that inAa quantity of heat,Q, flowing off from the temperaturet1to the lower temperaturet2should perform the workW, but inBunder the same circumstances it should perform a greater quantity of workW+W'; then, we could joinBin the sense assigned andAin the reverse sense into asingleprocess. HereAwould reverse the transformation of heat produced byBand would leave a surplus of workW', produced, so to speak, from nothing. The combination would present a perpetual motion.
With the feeling, now, that it makes little differencewhether the mechanical laws are broken directly or indirectly (by processes of heat), and convinced of the existence of auniversallaw-ruled connexion of nature, Carnot here excludes for the first time from the province ofgeneralphysics the possibility of a perpetual motion.But it follows, then, that the quantity of work W, produced by the passage of a quantity of heat Q from a temperature t1to a temperature t2, is independent of the nature of the substances as also of the character of the process, so far as that is unaccompanied by loss, but is wholly dependent upon the temperature t1, t2.
This important principle has been fully confirmed by the special researches of Carnot himself (1824), of Clapeyron (1834), and of Sir William Thomson (1849), now Lord Kelvin. The principle was reachedwithout any assumption whateverconcerning the nature of heat, simply by the exclusion of a perpetual motion. Carnot, it is true, was an adherent of the theory of Black, according to which the sum-total of the quantity of heat in the world is constant, but so far as his investigations have been hitherto considered the decision on this point is of no consequence. Carnot's principle led to the most remarkable results. W. Thomson (1848) founded upon it the ingenious idea of an "absolute" scale of temperature. James Thomson (1849) conceived a Carnot process to take place with water freezing under pressure and, therefore, performing work. He discovered, thus, that the freezing point is lowered 0·0075° Celsius by every additional atmosphereof pressure. This is mentioned merely as an example.
About twenty years after the publication of Carnot's book a further advance was made by J. R. Mayer and J. P. Joule. Mayer, while engaged as a physician in the service of the Dutch, observed, during a process of bleeding in Java, an unusual redness of the venous blood. In agreement with Liebig's theory of animal heat he connected this fact with the diminished loss of heat in warmer climates, and with the diminished expenditure of organic combustibles. The total expenditure of heat of a man at rest must be equal to the total heat of combustion. But sinceallorganic actions, even the mechanical actions, must be set down to the credit of the heat of combustion, some connexion must exist between mechanical work and expenditure of heat.
Joule started from quite similar convictions concerning the galvanic battery. A heat of association equivalent to the consumption of the zinc can be made to appear in the galvanic cell. If a current is set up, a part of this heat appears in the conductor of the current. The interposition of an apparatus for the decomposition of water causes a part of this heat to disappear, which on the burning of the explosive gas formed, is reproduced. If the current runs an electromotor, a portion of the heat again disappears, which, on the consumption of the work by friction, again makes its appearance. Accordingly, both the heatproduced and the work produced, appeared to Joule also as connected with the consumption of material. The thought was therefore present, both to Mayer and to Joule, of regarding heat and work as equivalent quantities, so connected with each other that what is lost in one form universally appears in another. The result of this was asubstantialconception of heat and of work, andultimately a substantial conception of energy. Here every physical change of condition is regarded as energy, the destruction of which generates work or equivalent heat. An electric charge, for example, is energy.
In 1842 Mayer had calculated from the physical constants then universally accepted that by the disappearance of one kilogramme-calorie 365 kilogramme-metres of work could be performed, andvice versa. Joule, on the other hand, by a long series of delicate and varied experiments beginning in 1843 ultimately determined the mechanical equivalent of the kilogramme-calorie, more exactly, as 425 kilogramme-metres.
If we estimate every change of physical condition by themechanical workwhich can be performed upon thedisappearanceof that condition, and call this measureenergy, then we can measure all physical changes of condition, no matter how different they may be, with the same common measure, and say:the sum-total of all energy remains constant. This is the form that the principle of excluded perpetual motion received atthe hands of Mayer, Joule, Helmholtz, and W. Thomson in its extension to the whole domain of physics.
After it had been proved that heat mustdisappearif mechanical work was to be done at its expense, Carnot's principle could no longer be regarded as a complete expression of the facts. Its improved form was first given, in 1850, by Clausius, whom Thomson followed in 1851. It runs thus: "If a quantity of heatQ'is transformed into work in a reversible process,anotherquantity of heatQof the absolute[55]temperatureT1is lowered to the absolute temperatureT2." HereQ'is dependent only onQ,T1,T2, but is independent of the substances used and of the character of the process, so far as that is unaccompanied by loss. Owing to this last fact, it is sufficient to find the relation which obtains for some one well-known physical substance, say a gas, and some definite simple process. The relation found will be the one that holds generally. We get, thus,
Q'/(Q' + Q)=(T1-T2)/T1(1)
that is, the quotient of the available heatQ'transformed into work divided by the sum of the transformed and transferred heats (the total sum used), the so-calledeconomical coefficientof the process, is,
(T1-T2)/T1.
When a cold body is put in contact with a warm body it is observed that the first body is warmed and that the second body is cooled. We may say that the first body is warmedat the expense ofthe second body. This suggests the notion of a thing, or heat-substance, which passes from the one body to the other. If two masses of waterm,m', of unequal temperatures, be put together, it will be found, upon the rapid equalisation of the temperatures, that the respective changes of temperaturesuandu'are inversely proportional to the masses and of opposite signs, so that the algebraical sum of the products is,
mu+m'u'= 0.
Black called the productsmu,m'u', which are decisive for our knowledge of the process,quantities of heat. We may form a very clearpictureof these products by conceiving them with Black as measures of the quantities of some substance. But the essential thing is not this picture but theconstancyof the sum of these products in simple processes of conduction. If a quantity of heat disappears at one point, an equally large quantity will make its appearance at some other point. The retention of this idea leads to the discovery of specific heat. Black, finally, perceives that also something else may appear for a vanished quantity of heat, namely: the fusion or vaporisation of a definite quantityof matter. He adheres here still to this favorite view, though with some freedom, and considers the vanished quantity of heat as still present, but aslatent.
The generally accepted notion of a caloric, or heat-stuff, was strongly shaken by the work of Mayer and Joule. If the quantity of heat can be increased and diminished, people said, heat cannot be a substance, but must be amotion. The subordinate part of this statement has become much more popular than all the rest of the doctrine of energy. But we may convince ourselves that the motional conception of heat is now as unessential as was formerly its conception as a substance. Both ideas were favored or impeded solely by accidental historical circumstances. It does not follow that heat is not a substance from the fact that a mechanical equivalent exists for quantity of heat. We will make this clear by the following question which bright students have sometimes put to me. Is there a mechanical equivalent of electricity as there is a mechanical equivalent of heat? Yes, and no. There is no mechanical equivalent ofquantityof electricity as there is an equivalent ofquantityof heat, because the same quantity of electricity has a very different capacity for work, according to the circumstances in which it is placed; but thereisa mechanical equivalent of electrical energy.
Let us ask another question. Is there a mechanical equivalent of water? No, there is no mechanical equivalent of quantity of water, but there is a mechanicalequivalent of weight of water multiplied by its distance of descent.
When a Leyden jar is discharged and work thereby performed, we do not picture to ourselves that the quantity of electricity disappears as work is done, but we simply assume that the electricities come into different positions, equal quantities of positive and negative electricity being united with one another.
What, now, is the reason of this difference of view in our treatment of heat and of electricity? The reason is purely historical, wholly conventional, and, what is still more important, is wholly indifferent. I may be allowed to establish this assertion.
In 1785 Coulomb constructed his torsion balance, by which he was enabled to measure the repulsion of electrified bodies. Suppose we have two small balls,A,B, which over their whole extent are similarly electrified. These two balls will exert on one another, at a certain distancerof their centres, a certain repulsionp. We bring into contact withBnow a ballC, suffer both to be equally electrified, and then measure the repulsion ofBfromAand ofCfromAat the same distancer. The sum of these repulsions is againp. Accordingly something has remained constant. If we ascribe this effect to a substance, then we infer naturally its constancy. But the essential point of the exposition is the divisibility of the electric forcepand not the simile of substance.
In 1838 Riess constructed his electrical air-thermometer(the thermoelectrometer). This gives a measure of the quantity of heat produced by the discharge of jars. This quantity of heat is not proportional to the quantity of electricity contained in the jar by Coulomb's measure, but ifQbe this quantity andCbe the capacity, is proportional toQ2/2C, or, more simply still, to the energy of the charged jar. If, now, we discharge the jar completely through the thermometer, we obtain a certain quantity of heat,W. But if we make the discharge through the thermometer into a second jar, we obtain a quantity less thanW. But we may obtain the remainder by completely discharging both jars through the air-thermometer, when it will again be proportional to the energy of the two jars. On the first, incomplete discharge, accordingly, a part of the electricity's capacity for work was lost.
When the charge of a jar produces heat its energy is changed and its value by Riess's thermometer is decreased. But by Coulomb's measure the quantity remains unaltered.
Now let us imagine that Riess's thermometer had been invented before Coulomb's torsion balance, which is not a difficult feat, since both inventions are independent of each other; what would be more natural than that the "quantity" of electricity contained in a jar should be measured by the heat produced in the thermometer? But then, this so-called quantity of electricity would decrease on the production of heat or on the performance of work, whereas it now remains unchanged;in that case, therefore, electricity would not be asubstancebut amotion, whereas now it is still a substance. The reason, therefore, why we have other notions of electricity than we have of heat, is purely historical, accidental, and conventional.
This is also the case with other physical things. Water does not disappear when work is done. Why? Because we measure quantity of water with scales, just as we do electricity. But suppose the capacity of water for work were called quantity, and had to be measured, therefore, by a mill instead of by scales; then this quantity also would disappear as it performed the work. It may, now, be easily conceived that many substances are not so easily got at as water. In that case we should be unable to carry out the one kind of measurement with the scales whilst many other modes of measurement would still be left us.
In the case of heat, now, the historically established measure of "quantity" is accidentally the work-value of the heat. Accordingly, its quantity disappears when work is done. But that heat is not a substance follows from this as little as does the opposite conclusion that it is a substance. In Black's case the quantity of heat remains constant because the heat passes into nootherform of energy.
If any one to-day should still wish to think of heat as a substance, we might allow that person this liberty with little ado. He would only have to assume that that which we call quantity of heat was the energy ofa substance whose quantity remained unaltered, but whose energy changed. In point of fact we might much better say, in analogy with the other terms of physics, energy of heat, instead of quantity of heat.
When we wonder, therefore, at the discovery that heat is motion, we wonder at something that was never discovered. It is perfectly indifferent and possesses not the slightest scientific value, whether we think of heat as a substance or not. The fact is, heat behaves in some connexions like a substance, in others not. Heat is latent in steam as oxygen is latent in water.