'How small of all that human hearts endureThat part which kings and laws can cause or cure!'
'How small of all that human hearts endureThat part which kings and laws can cause or cure!'
He was, they held, telling the tyrants that it was not their fault if the poor were miserable. The essay was thus an apology for the heartlessness of the rich. This view was set forth by Hazlitt in an attack upon Malthus in 1807.[431]It appears again in theEnquiryby G. Ensor (1769-1843)—a vivacious though rather long-winded Irishman, who was known both to O'Connell and to Bentham.[432]Godwin himself was roused by the appearance of the fifth edition of Malthus'sEssayto write a reply, which appeared in 1820. He was helped by David Booth (1766-1846),[433]a man of some mathematical and statistical knowledge. Hazlitt's performance is sufficiently significant of the general tendency. Hazlitt had been an enthusiastic admirer of Godwin, and retained as much of the enthusiasm as his wayward prejudices would allow. He was through life what may be called a sentimental Radical, so far as Radicalism was compatible with an ardent worship of Napoleon. To him Napoleon meant the enemy of Pitt and Liverpool and Castlereagh and the Holy Alliance. Hazlitt could forgive any policy which meant the humiliation of the men whom he most heartily hated. His attack upon Malthus was such asmight satisfy even Cobbett, whose capacity for hatred, and especially for this particular object of hatred, was equal to Hazlitt's. The personal rancour of which Hazlitt was unfortunately capable leads to monstrous imputations. Not only does Malthus's essay show the 'little low rankling malice of a parish beadle ... disguised in the garb of philosophy,' and bury 'false logic' under 'a heap of garbled calculations,'[434]and so forth; but he founds insinuations upon Malthus's argument as to the constancy of the sexual passion. Malthus, he fully believes, has none of the ordinary passions, anger, pride, avarice, or the like, but declares that he must be a slave to an 'amorous complexion,' and believe all other men to be made 'of the same combustible materials.'[435]This foul blow is too characteristic of Hazlitt's usual method; but indicates also the tone which could be taken by contemporary journalism.
The more serious argument is really that the second version of Malthus is an answer to his first. Briefly, the 'moral check' which came in only as a kind of afterthought is a normal part of the process by which population is kept within limits, and prevents the monstrous results of the 'geometrical ratio.' Hazlitt, after insisting upon this, admits that there is nothing in 'the general principles here stated that Mr. Malthus is at present disposed to deny, or that he has not himself expressly insisted upon in some part or other of his various works.'[436]He only argues that Malthus's concessions are made at the cost of self-contradiction. Why then, it may be asked, should not Hazlitt take the position of an improver and harmoniser of the doctrinerather than of a fierce opponent? The answer has been already implied. He regards Malthus as an apologist for an unjust inequality. Malthus, he says, in classifying the evils of life, has 'allotted to the poor all the misery, and to the rich as much vice as they please.'[437]The check of starvation will keep down the numbers of the poor; and the check of luxury and profligacy will restrain the multiplication of the rich. 'The poor are to make a formal surrender of their right to provoke charity or parish assistance that the rich may be able to lay out all their money on their vices.'[438]The misery of the lower orders is the result of the power of the upper. A man born into a world where he is not wanted has no right, said Malthus, to a share of the food. That might be true if the poor were a set of lazy supernumeraries living on the industrious. But the truth is that the poor man does the work, and is forced to put up in return with a part of the produce of his labour.[439]The poor-laws recognise the principle that those who get all from the labour of others should provide from their superfluities for the necessities of those in want.[440]The 'grinding necessity' of which Malthus had spoken does not raise but lower the standard; and a system of equality would lessen instead of increasing the pressure. Malthus, again, has proposed that parents should be responsible for their children. That is, says Hazlitt, Malthus would leave children to starvation, though he professes to disapprove infanticide. He would 'extinguish every spark of humanity ... towards the children of others' on pretence of preserving the 'ties of parental affection.' Malthus tries to argue that the 'iniquity ofgovernment' is not the cause of poverty. That belief, he says, has generated discontent and revolution. That is, says Hazlitt, the way to prevent revolutions and produce reforms is to persuade people that all the evils which government may inflict are their own fault. Government is to do as much mischief as it pleases, without being answerable for it.[441]The poor-laws, as Hazlitt admits, are bad, but do not show the root of the evil. The evils are really due to increasing tyranny, dependence, indolence, and unhappiness due to other causes. Pauperism has increased because the government and the rich have had their way in everything. They have squandered our revenues, multiplied sinecures and pensions, doubled salaries, given monopolies and encouraged jobs, and depressed the poor and industrious. The 'poor create their own fund,' and the necessity for it has arisen from the exorbitant demands made by the rich.[442]Malthus is a Blifil,[443]hypocritically insinuating arguments in favour of tyranny under pretence of benevolence.
Hazlitt's writing, although showing the passions of a bitter partisan, hits some of Malthus's rather cloudy argumentation. His successor, Ensor, representing the same view, finds an appropriate topic in the wrongs of Ireland. Irish poverty, he holds, is plainly due not to over-population but to under-government,[444]meaning, we must suppose, misgovernment. But the same cause explains other cases. The 'people are poor and are growing poorer,'[445]and there is no mystery about it. The expense of a court, the waste of the profits and moneyin the House of Commons, facts which are in striking contrast to the republican virtues of the United States, are enough to account for everything; and Malthus's whole aim is to 'calumniate the people.' Godwin in 1820 takes up the same taunts. Malthus ought, he thinks, to welcome war, famine, pestilence, and the gallows.[446]He has taught the poor that they have no claim to relief, and the rich that, by indulging in vice, they are conferring a benefit upon the country. The poor-laws admit a right, and he taunts Malthus for proposing to abolish it, and refusing food to a poor man on the ground that he had notice not to come into the world two years before he was born.[447]
Godwin, whose earlier atheism had been superseded by a vague deism, now thinks with Cobbett that the poor were supported by the piety of the mediæval clergy, who fed the hungry and clothed the naked from their vast revenues, while dooming themselves to spare living.[448]He appeals to the authority of the Christian religion, which indeed might be a fairargumentum ad hominemagainst 'Parson Malthus.' He declares that Nature takes more care of her work than such irreverent authors suppose, and 'does not ask our aid to keep down the excess of population.'[449]In fact, he doubts whether population increases at all. Malthus's whole theory, he says, rests upon the case of America; and with the help of Mr. Booth and some very unsatisfactory statistics, he tries to prove that the increase shown in the American census has been entirely due to immigration. Malthus safely declined to take any notice of a production whichin fact shows that Godwin had lost his early vigour. The sound Utilitarian, Francis Place, took up the challenge, and exploded some of Godwin's statistics. He shows his Radicalism by admitting that Malthus, to whose general benevolence he does justice, had not spoken of the poor as one sprung like himself from the poor would naturally do; and he accepts modes of limiting the population from which Malthus himself had shrunk. For improvement, he looks chiefly to the abolition of restrictive laws.
II. SOCIALISM
The arguments of Hazlitt and his allies bring us back to the Socialist position. Although it was represented by no writer of much literary position, Owen was becoming conspicuous, and some of his sympathisers were already laying down principles more familiar to-day. Already, in the days of the Six Acts, the government was alarmed by certain 'Spencean Philanthropists.' According to Place they were a very feeble sect, numbering only about fifty, and perfectly harmless. Their prophet was a poor man called Thomas Spence (1750-1815),[450]who had started as a schoolmaster, and in 1775 read a paper at Newcastle before a 'Philosophical Society.'[451]He proposed that the land in every village should belong to all the inhabitants—a proposal which Mr. Hyndman regards as a prophecy of more thoroughgoing schemes of Land Nationalisation. Spence drifted to London, picked up a precarious living, partly by selling books of a revolutionary kind, and diedin 1815, leaving, it seems, a few proselytes. A writer of higher literary capacity was Charles Hall, a physician at Tavistock, who in 1805 published a book onThe Effects of Civilisation.[452]The effects of civilisation, he holds, are simply pernicious. Landed property originated in violence, and has caused all social evils. A great landlord consumes unproductively as much as would keep eight thousand people.[453]He gets everything from the labour of the poor; while they are forced to starvation wages by the raising of rents. Trade and manufactures are equally mischievous. India gets nothing but jewellery from Europe, and Europe nothing but muslin from India, while so much less food is produced in either country.[454]Manufactures generally are a cause and sign of the poverty of nations.[455]
Such sporadic protests against the inequalities of wealth may be taken as parts of that 'ancient tale of wrong' which has in all ages been steaming up from the suffering world, and provoking a smile from epicurean deities. As Owenism advanced, the argument took a more distinct form. Mill[456]mentions William Thompson of Cork as a 'very estimable man,' who was the 'principal champion' of the Owenites in their debates with the Benthamites. He published in 1824 a book upon the distribution ofwealth.[457]It is wordy, and is apt to remain in the region of 'vague generalities' just at the points where specific statements would be welcome. But besides the merit of obvious sincerity and good feeling, it has the interest of showing very clearly the relation between the opposing schools. Thompson had a common ground with the Utilitarians, though they undoubtedly would consider his logic to be loose and overridden by sentimentalism. In the first place, he heartily admired Bentham: 'the most profound and celebrated writer on legislation in this or any other country.'[458]He accepts the 'greatest happiness principle' as applicable to the social problem. He argues for equality upon Bentham's ground. Take a penny from a poor man to give it to the rich man, and the poor man clearly loses far more happiness than the rich man gains. With Bentham, too, he admits the importance of 'security,' and agrees that it is not always compatible with equality. A man should have the fruits of his labour; and therefore the man who labours most should have most. But, unlike Bentham, he regards equality as more important than security. To him the main consideration is the monstrous mass of evil resulting from vast accumulations of wealth in a few hands. In the next place, he adapts to his own purpose the Ricardian theory of value. All value whatever, he argues, is created by labour. The labourer, he infers, should have the value which he creates. As things are, the labourer parts with most of it to the capitalist or the owner of rents. The capitalist claims a right to thewhole additional production due to the employment of capital. The labourer, on the other hand, may claim a right to the whole additional production, after replacing the wear and tear and allowing to the capitalist enough to support him in equal comfort with the productive labourers.[459]Thompson holds that while either system would be compatible with 'security,' the labourer's demand is sanctioned by 'equality.' In point of fact, neither system has been fully carried out; but the labourer's view would tend to prevail with the spread of knowledge and justice. While thus anticipating later Socialism, he differs on a significant point. Thompson insists upon the importance of 'voluntary exchange' as one of his first principles. No one is to be forced to take what he does not himself think a fair equivalent for his labour. Here, again, he would coincide with the Utilitarians. They, not less than he, were for free trade and the abolition of every kind of monopoly. But that view may lead by itself to the simple adoption of the do-nothing principle, or, as modern Socialists would say, to the more effectual plunder of the poor. The modern Socialist infers that the means of production must be in some way nationalised. Thompson does not contemplate such a consummation. He denounces, like all the Radicals of the day, monopolies and conspiracy laws. Sinecures and standing armies and State churches are the strongholds of tyranny and superstition. The 'hereditary possession of wealth' is one of the master-evils, and with sinecures will disappear the systems of entails and unequal distribution of inheritance.[460]Such institutions have encouraged the use of fraud and force,and indirectly degraded the labourer into a helpless position. He would sweep them all away, and with them all disqualifications imposed upon women.[461]This once done, it will be necessary to establish a universal and thoroughgoing system of education. Then the poor man, freed from the shackles of superstition and despotism, will be able to obtain his rights as knowledge and justice spread through the whole community. The desire to accumulate for selfish purposes will itself disappear. The labourer will get all that he creates; the aggregate wealth will be enormously multiplied, though universally diffused; and the form taken by the new society will, as he argues at great length, be that of voluntary co-operative associations upon Owen's principles.
The economists would, of course, reject the theory that the capitalists should have no profits; but, in spite of this, they might agree to a great extent with Thompson's aspirations. Thompson, however, holds the true Socialist sentiment of aversion to Malthus. He denies energetically what he takes to be the Malthusian doctrine: that increased comfort will always produce increased numbers.[462]This has been the 'grand scarecrow to frighten away all attempts at social improvement.' Thompson accordingly asserts that increased comfort always causes increased prudence ultimately; and looks forward to a stationary state in which the births will just balance the deaths. I need not inquire here which theory puts the cart before the horse. The opposition possibly admits of reconciliation; but here I onlyremark once more how Malthus stood for the appeal to hard facts which always provoked the Utopians as much as it corresponded to the stern Utilitarian view.
Another writer, Thomas Hodgskin, honorary secretary of the Birkbeck Institution, who published a tract calledLabour defended against the Claims of Capital, or the Unproductiveness of Capital proved(1825), and afterwards gave some popular lectures on political economy, has been noticed as anticipating Socialist ideas. He can see, he says, why something should go to the maker of a road and something be paid by the person who gets the benefit of it. But he does not see why the road itself should have anything.[463]Hodgskin writes without bitterness, if without much logic. It is not for me to say whether modern Socialists are well advised in admitting that these crude suggestions were anticipations of their own ideas. The most natural inference would be that vague guesses about the wickedness of the rich have been in all ages current among the poor, and now and then take more pretentious form. Most men want very naturally to get as much and to work as little as they can, and call their desire a first principle of justice.
Perhaps, however, it is fairer to notice in how many points there was unconscious agreement; and how by converting very excellent maxims into absolute dogmas, from which a whole system was deducible, the theories appeared to be mutually contradictory, and, taken separately, became absurd. The palpable and admitted evil was the growth of pauperism and demoralisation of the labourer. The remedy, according to the Utilitarians, is to raise the sense of individual responsibility, to makea man dependent upon his own exertions, and to give him security that he will enjoy their fruit. Let government give education on one hand and security on the other, and equality will follow in due time. The sentimental Radical naturally replies that leaving a man to starve does not necessarily make him industrious; that, in point of fact, great and growing inequality of wealth has resulted; and that the rights of man should be applied not only to political privilege, but to the possession of property. The Utilitarians have left out justice by putting equality in the background. Justice, as Bentham replied, has no meaning till you have settled by experience what laws will produce happiness; and your absolute equality would destroy the very mainspring of social improvement. Meanwhile the Conservative thinks that both parties are really fostering the evils by making individualism supreme, and that organisation is necessary to improvement; while one set of Radicals would perpetuate a mere blind struggle for existence, and the other enable the lowest class to enforce a dead level of ignorance and stupidity. They therefore call upon government to become paternal and active, and to teach not only morality but religion; and upon the aristocracy to discharge its functions worthily, in order to stamp out social evils and prevent a servile insurrection. But how was the actual government of George IV. and Sidmouth and Eldon to be converted to a sense of its duties? On each side appeal is made to a sweeping and absolute principle, and amazingly complex and difficult questions of fact are taken for granted. The Utilitarians were so far right that they appealed to experience, as, in fact, such questions have to be settled by the slow co-operationof many minds in many generations. Unfortunately the Utilitarians had, as we have seen, a very inadequate conception of what experience really meant, and were fully as rash and dogmatic as their opponents. I must now try to consider what were the intellectual conceptions implied by their mode of treating these problems.
FOOTNOTES:[392]The discussions of population most frequently mentioned are:—W. Godwin,Thoughts occasioned by Dr. Parr's Spital Sermon, etc., 1801; R. Southey, in (Aikin's)Annual Review for 1803, pp. 292-301; Thomas Jarrold,Dissertations on Man, etc., 1806; W. Hazlitt,Reply to the Essay on Population, 1807; A. Ingram,Disquisitions on Population, 1808; John Weyland,Principles of Population, etc., 1806; James Grahame,Inquiry into the Principle of Population, 1816; George Ensor,Inquiry concerning the Population of Nations, 1818; W. Godwin,On Population, 1820; Francis Place,Principles of Population, 1822; David Booth,Letter to the Rev. T. R. Malthus, 1823; M. T. Sadler,Law of Population, 1830; A. Alison,Principles of Population, 1840; T. Doubleday,True Law of Population, 1842.[393]Quarterly Review, Dec. 1812 (reprinted in Southey'sMoral and Political Essays, 1832).[394]Quarterly Review, July 1817, by (Archbishop) Sumner, Malthus's commentator in theRecords of Creation. Ricardo'sLetters to Trower, p. 47.[395]Spence's Tracts on Political Economywere collected with a preface in 1822. Spence is better known as an entomologist, and collaborated with William Kirby.[396]Tracts(1822), p. xiii.[397]Ibid.p. 59.[398]Chalmers'sWorkswere published in twenty-five volumes in 1841-42.[399]Chalmers'sWorks, i. 237.[400]This essay is not in his collectedWorks, though in vol. xxi. it is promised for the next volume.[401]Works, xix. and xx.[402]Mill'sPolitical Economy, bk. i. ch. v. § 7 and 8. See Chalmers, xix. 140.[403]National Resources(Appendix).[404]Works, xix. 306.[405]Ibid.xix. 226, 233.[406]National Resources, p. 48.[407]Works, xix. 64.[408]Works, xix. 226.[409]Ibid.xix. 235.[410]National Resources, p. 158.[411]Ibid.p. 160.[412]Works, xix. 262.[413]Works, xix. 75.[414]Ibid.xix. 118-47.[415]Ibid.xix. 343.[416]SeeIbid.xix. 171. J. S. Mill speaks of Chalmers's speculations with a respect which it is difficult to understand.[417]Chalmers holds that the Ricardian doctrine of rent inverts the true order. Fertile lands do not pay rent because poor lands are brought into cultivation, but poor lands are cultivated because fertile lands pay rent. He apparently wishes, like Malthus, to regard rent as a blessing, not a curse. The point is not worth arguing. SeeWorks, xix. 320.[418]Works, xix. 304-5.[419]Ibid.xix. 370.[420]Ibid.xix. 366.[421]Ibid.xix. 322.[422]Works, xx. 247, 296.[423]Ibid.xx. 290.[424]Works, xix. 380.[425]The copy of Malthus's second edition with Coleridge's notes used by Southey is in the British Museum.[426]See Southey'sPolitical.[427]Thoughts occasioned by Dr. Parr's Spital Sermon.A copy annotated by Coleridge is in the British Museum.[428]Thoughts, etc., pp. 56, 61, 62.[429]Ibid.p. 71.[430]Lines added to Goldsmith'sTraveller.[431]Reply to the Essay on Population, etc., 1807. The book was anonymous. The first three letters had appeared in Cobbett'sRegister. Two others with an appendix are added.[432]Bentham'sWorks, x. 603, 604; andDictionary of National Biography.[433]SeeDictionary of National Biography.[434]Hazlitt'sReply, p. 19.[435]Ibid.pp. 139-41.[436]Ibid.p. 117.[437]Reply, p. 263.[438]Ibid.p. 344.[439]Ibid.p. 284.[440]Ibid.p. 287.[441]Reply, p. 351.[442]Ibid.pp. 362-64.[443]Ibid.p. 352.[444]Ensor'sEnquiry, p. 294.[445]Ibid.p. 441.[446]Godwin on Population, p. 506.[447]Ibid.p. 553.[448]Ibid.p. 558.[449]Godwin, p. 219.[450]See account of him reprinted from Mackenzie'sHistory of NewcastleandDictionary of National Biography.[451]Reprinted by Mr. Hyndman in 1822, with a preface.[452]SeeDictionary of National Biography. Hall's book was reprinted by J. M. Morgan in the 'Phœnix Library,' 1850. See Anton Menger'sDas Recht auf den vollen Arbeitsertrag(second edition, 1891), for notices of Hall, Thompson, and others.[453]Effects of Civilisation(1850), p. 86.[454]Ibid.p. 71.[455]Ibid.p. 115.[456]Autobiography, p. 125. See Holyoake'sHistory of Co-operation, i. 16, 109, 278-83, 348, for some interesting notices of Thompson. Menger (Recht auf den vollen Arbeitsertrag, p. 100n.) holds that Thompson not only anticipated but inspired Marx: Rodbertus, he says, drew chiefly upon St. Simon and Proudhon.[457]An Inquiry into the Principles of the Distribution of Wealth most conducive to Human Happiness; applied to the Newly Proposed System of Voluntary Equality of Wealth.—1824.[458]Distribution of Wealth, p. 327.[459]Distribution of Wealth, p. 167, etc.[460]Ibid.p. 310.[461]He wrote, as J. S. Mill observes, anAppeal[1825] against James Mill's views on this matter—a fact which no doubt commended him to the son.[462]Distribution of Wealth, pp. 425, 535, etc.[463]Labour Defended, p. 16.
[392]The discussions of population most frequently mentioned are:—W. Godwin,Thoughts occasioned by Dr. Parr's Spital Sermon, etc., 1801; R. Southey, in (Aikin's)Annual Review for 1803, pp. 292-301; Thomas Jarrold,Dissertations on Man, etc., 1806; W. Hazlitt,Reply to the Essay on Population, 1807; A. Ingram,Disquisitions on Population, 1808; John Weyland,Principles of Population, etc., 1806; James Grahame,Inquiry into the Principle of Population, 1816; George Ensor,Inquiry concerning the Population of Nations, 1818; W. Godwin,On Population, 1820; Francis Place,Principles of Population, 1822; David Booth,Letter to the Rev. T. R. Malthus, 1823; M. T. Sadler,Law of Population, 1830; A. Alison,Principles of Population, 1840; T. Doubleday,True Law of Population, 1842.
[392]The discussions of population most frequently mentioned are:—W. Godwin,Thoughts occasioned by Dr. Parr's Spital Sermon, etc., 1801; R. Southey, in (Aikin's)Annual Review for 1803, pp. 292-301; Thomas Jarrold,Dissertations on Man, etc., 1806; W. Hazlitt,Reply to the Essay on Population, 1807; A. Ingram,Disquisitions on Population, 1808; John Weyland,Principles of Population, etc., 1806; James Grahame,Inquiry into the Principle of Population, 1816; George Ensor,Inquiry concerning the Population of Nations, 1818; W. Godwin,On Population, 1820; Francis Place,Principles of Population, 1822; David Booth,Letter to the Rev. T. R. Malthus, 1823; M. T. Sadler,Law of Population, 1830; A. Alison,Principles of Population, 1840; T. Doubleday,True Law of Population, 1842.
[393]Quarterly Review, Dec. 1812 (reprinted in Southey'sMoral and Political Essays, 1832).
[393]Quarterly Review, Dec. 1812 (reprinted in Southey'sMoral and Political Essays, 1832).
[394]Quarterly Review, July 1817, by (Archbishop) Sumner, Malthus's commentator in theRecords of Creation. Ricardo'sLetters to Trower, p. 47.
[394]Quarterly Review, July 1817, by (Archbishop) Sumner, Malthus's commentator in theRecords of Creation. Ricardo'sLetters to Trower, p. 47.
[395]Spence's Tracts on Political Economywere collected with a preface in 1822. Spence is better known as an entomologist, and collaborated with William Kirby.
[395]Spence's Tracts on Political Economywere collected with a preface in 1822. Spence is better known as an entomologist, and collaborated with William Kirby.
[396]Tracts(1822), p. xiii.
[396]Tracts(1822), p. xiii.
[397]Ibid.p. 59.
[397]Ibid.p. 59.
[398]Chalmers'sWorkswere published in twenty-five volumes in 1841-42.
[398]Chalmers'sWorkswere published in twenty-five volumes in 1841-42.
[399]Chalmers'sWorks, i. 237.
[399]Chalmers'sWorks, i. 237.
[400]This essay is not in his collectedWorks, though in vol. xxi. it is promised for the next volume.
[400]This essay is not in his collectedWorks, though in vol. xxi. it is promised for the next volume.
[401]Works, xix. and xx.
[401]Works, xix. and xx.
[402]Mill'sPolitical Economy, bk. i. ch. v. § 7 and 8. See Chalmers, xix. 140.
[402]Mill'sPolitical Economy, bk. i. ch. v. § 7 and 8. See Chalmers, xix. 140.
[403]National Resources(Appendix).
[403]National Resources(Appendix).
[404]Works, xix. 306.
[404]Works, xix. 306.
[405]Ibid.xix. 226, 233.
[405]Ibid.xix. 226, 233.
[406]National Resources, p. 48.
[406]National Resources, p. 48.
[407]Works, xix. 64.
[407]Works, xix. 64.
[408]Works, xix. 226.
[408]Works, xix. 226.
[409]Ibid.xix. 235.
[409]Ibid.xix. 235.
[410]National Resources, p. 158.
[410]National Resources, p. 158.
[411]Ibid.p. 160.
[411]Ibid.p. 160.
[412]Works, xix. 262.
[412]Works, xix. 262.
[413]Works, xix. 75.
[413]Works, xix. 75.
[414]Ibid.xix. 118-47.
[414]Ibid.xix. 118-47.
[415]Ibid.xix. 343.
[415]Ibid.xix. 343.
[416]SeeIbid.xix. 171. J. S. Mill speaks of Chalmers's speculations with a respect which it is difficult to understand.
[416]SeeIbid.xix. 171. J. S. Mill speaks of Chalmers's speculations with a respect which it is difficult to understand.
[417]Chalmers holds that the Ricardian doctrine of rent inverts the true order. Fertile lands do not pay rent because poor lands are brought into cultivation, but poor lands are cultivated because fertile lands pay rent. He apparently wishes, like Malthus, to regard rent as a blessing, not a curse. The point is not worth arguing. SeeWorks, xix. 320.
[417]Chalmers holds that the Ricardian doctrine of rent inverts the true order. Fertile lands do not pay rent because poor lands are brought into cultivation, but poor lands are cultivated because fertile lands pay rent. He apparently wishes, like Malthus, to regard rent as a blessing, not a curse. The point is not worth arguing. SeeWorks, xix. 320.
[418]Works, xix. 304-5.
[418]Works, xix. 304-5.
[419]Ibid.xix. 370.
[419]Ibid.xix. 370.
[420]Ibid.xix. 366.
[420]Ibid.xix. 366.
[421]Ibid.xix. 322.
[421]Ibid.xix. 322.
[422]Works, xx. 247, 296.
[422]Works, xx. 247, 296.
[423]Ibid.xx. 290.
[423]Ibid.xx. 290.
[424]Works, xix. 380.
[424]Works, xix. 380.
[425]The copy of Malthus's second edition with Coleridge's notes used by Southey is in the British Museum.
[425]The copy of Malthus's second edition with Coleridge's notes used by Southey is in the British Museum.
[426]See Southey'sPolitical.
[426]See Southey'sPolitical.
[427]Thoughts occasioned by Dr. Parr's Spital Sermon.A copy annotated by Coleridge is in the British Museum.
[427]Thoughts occasioned by Dr. Parr's Spital Sermon.A copy annotated by Coleridge is in the British Museum.
[428]Thoughts, etc., pp. 56, 61, 62.
[428]Thoughts, etc., pp. 56, 61, 62.
[429]Ibid.p. 71.
[429]Ibid.p. 71.
[430]Lines added to Goldsmith'sTraveller.
[430]Lines added to Goldsmith'sTraveller.
[431]Reply to the Essay on Population, etc., 1807. The book was anonymous. The first three letters had appeared in Cobbett'sRegister. Two others with an appendix are added.
[431]Reply to the Essay on Population, etc., 1807. The book was anonymous. The first three letters had appeared in Cobbett'sRegister. Two others with an appendix are added.
[432]Bentham'sWorks, x. 603, 604; andDictionary of National Biography.
[432]Bentham'sWorks, x. 603, 604; andDictionary of National Biography.
[433]SeeDictionary of National Biography.
[433]SeeDictionary of National Biography.
[434]Hazlitt'sReply, p. 19.
[434]Hazlitt'sReply, p. 19.
[435]Ibid.pp. 139-41.
[435]Ibid.pp. 139-41.
[436]Ibid.p. 117.
[436]Ibid.p. 117.
[437]Reply, p. 263.
[437]Reply, p. 263.
[438]Ibid.p. 344.
[438]Ibid.p. 344.
[439]Ibid.p. 284.
[439]Ibid.p. 284.
[440]Ibid.p. 287.
[440]Ibid.p. 287.
[441]Reply, p. 351.
[441]Reply, p. 351.
[442]Ibid.pp. 362-64.
[442]Ibid.pp. 362-64.
[443]Ibid.p. 352.
[443]Ibid.p. 352.
[444]Ensor'sEnquiry, p. 294.
[444]Ensor'sEnquiry, p. 294.
[445]Ibid.p. 441.
[445]Ibid.p. 441.
[446]Godwin on Population, p. 506.
[446]Godwin on Population, p. 506.
[447]Ibid.p. 553.
[447]Ibid.p. 553.
[448]Ibid.p. 558.
[448]Ibid.p. 558.
[449]Godwin, p. 219.
[449]Godwin, p. 219.
[450]See account of him reprinted from Mackenzie'sHistory of NewcastleandDictionary of National Biography.
[450]See account of him reprinted from Mackenzie'sHistory of NewcastleandDictionary of National Biography.
[451]Reprinted by Mr. Hyndman in 1822, with a preface.
[451]Reprinted by Mr. Hyndman in 1822, with a preface.
[452]SeeDictionary of National Biography. Hall's book was reprinted by J. M. Morgan in the 'Phœnix Library,' 1850. See Anton Menger'sDas Recht auf den vollen Arbeitsertrag(second edition, 1891), for notices of Hall, Thompson, and others.
[452]SeeDictionary of National Biography. Hall's book was reprinted by J. M. Morgan in the 'Phœnix Library,' 1850. See Anton Menger'sDas Recht auf den vollen Arbeitsertrag(second edition, 1891), for notices of Hall, Thompson, and others.
[453]Effects of Civilisation(1850), p. 86.
[453]Effects of Civilisation(1850), p. 86.
[454]Ibid.p. 71.
[454]Ibid.p. 71.
[455]Ibid.p. 115.
[455]Ibid.p. 115.
[456]Autobiography, p. 125. See Holyoake'sHistory of Co-operation, i. 16, 109, 278-83, 348, for some interesting notices of Thompson. Menger (Recht auf den vollen Arbeitsertrag, p. 100n.) holds that Thompson not only anticipated but inspired Marx: Rodbertus, he says, drew chiefly upon St. Simon and Proudhon.
[456]Autobiography, p. 125. See Holyoake'sHistory of Co-operation, i. 16, 109, 278-83, 348, for some interesting notices of Thompson. Menger (Recht auf den vollen Arbeitsertrag, p. 100n.) holds that Thompson not only anticipated but inspired Marx: Rodbertus, he says, drew chiefly upon St. Simon and Proudhon.
[457]An Inquiry into the Principles of the Distribution of Wealth most conducive to Human Happiness; applied to the Newly Proposed System of Voluntary Equality of Wealth.—1824.
[457]An Inquiry into the Principles of the Distribution of Wealth most conducive to Human Happiness; applied to the Newly Proposed System of Voluntary Equality of Wealth.—1824.
[458]Distribution of Wealth, p. 327.
[458]Distribution of Wealth, p. 327.
[459]Distribution of Wealth, p. 167, etc.
[459]Distribution of Wealth, p. 167, etc.
[460]Ibid.p. 310.
[460]Ibid.p. 310.
[461]He wrote, as J. S. Mill observes, anAppeal[1825] against James Mill's views on this matter—a fact which no doubt commended him to the son.
[461]He wrote, as J. S. Mill observes, anAppeal[1825] against James Mill's views on this matter—a fact which no doubt commended him to the son.
[462]Distribution of Wealth, pp. 425, 535, etc.
[462]Distribution of Wealth, pp. 425, 535, etc.
[463]Labour Defended, p. 16.
[463]Labour Defended, p. 16.
PSYCHOLOGY
I. THOMAS BROWN
The politicians and economists, of whom I have spoken, took first principles for granted. The intellectual temperament, which made certain methods congenial to them, would no doubt have led them to an analogous position in philosophy. Bentham had touched upon philosophical points in a summary way, and James Mill, as we shall see, gave a more explicit statement. But such men as Ricardo and Malthus had no systematic philosophy, though a certain philosophy was congenial to their methods. Desire to reach a solid groundwork of fact, hearty aversion to mere word-juggling, and to effeminate sentimentalism, respect for science and indifference to, if not contempt for, poetry, resolution to approve no laws or institutions which could not be supported on plain grounds of utility, and to accept no theory which could not be firmly based on verifiable experience, imply moral and intellectual tendencies, in which we may perhaps say that the Utilitarians represent some of the strongest and most valuable qualities of the national character. Taking these qualities for granted, let us consider how the ultimate problems presented themselves to the school thus distinguished.
I have already observed that the Scottish philosophy, taught by Reid and Dugald Stewart, represented the only approach to a living philosophical system in these islands at the beginning of the century. It held this position for a long period. Mill, who had heard Dugald Stewart's lectures, knew nothing of German thought. He was well read in French philosophers, and in harmony with one leading sect. The so-calledidéologues,[464]who regarded Condillac as representing the true line of intellectual progress, were in France the analogues of the English Utilitarians. Destutt de Tracy and Cabanis were their most conspicuous leaders in this generation. The philosophy of Reid and Stewart crossed the channel, and supplied the first assailants of theidéologueswith their controversial weapons. Thus, until the German influence came to modify the whole controversy, the vital issue seemed to lie between the doctrine of Reid or 'intuitionism' on the one hand, and the purely 'experiential' school on the other, whether, as in France, it followed Condillac, or, as in England, looked back chiefly to Hartley. Both sections traced their intellectual ancestry to Locke and Hobbes, with some reference to Bacon, and, by the French writers, to Descartes. Stewart, again, as I have said, was the accepted Whig philosopher. It is true that the Whig sat habitually in the seat of Gallio. Jeffrey, whether he fully realised the fact or not, was at bottom a sceptic in philosophy as in politics. John Allen, the prophet of Holland House, was a thorough sceptic, and says[465]that Horner, one of Stewart's personaladmirers, was really a follower of Hume. The Whigs were inclined to Shaftesbury's doctrine that sensible men had all one religion, and that sensible men never said what it was. Those who had a more definite and avowable creed were content to follow Stewart's amiable philosophising. Brougham professed, let us hope, sincerely, to be an orthodox theist, and explained the argument from design in a commentary upon Paley. Sydney Smith expounded Reid and Stewart in lectures which showed at least that he was still a wit when talking 'philosophy' at the Royal Institution; and, though he hated 'enthusiasm' in dissenters, evangelicals, and tractarians, and kept religion strictly in its place—a place well outside of practical politics—managed to preach a wholesome, commonplace morality in terms of Christian theology. The difference between the Whig and the Radical temper showed itself in philosophical as in political questions. The Radical prided himself on being logical and thoroughgoing, while the Whig loved compromise, and thought that logic was very apt to be a nuisance. The systematic reticence which the Utilitarians held to be necessary prevented this contrast from showing itself distinctly on the surface. The Utilitarians, however, though they avoided such outspoken scepticism as would startle the public, indicated quite sufficiently to the initiated their essential position. It implied what they fully recognised in private conversation—a complete abandonment of theology. They left the obvious inferences to be drawn by others. In philosophy they could speak out in a well-founded confidence that few people were able to draw inferences. I will begin by considering the doctrine against which they protested;for the antagonism reveals, I think, the key to their position.
When Stewart was obliged by infirmity to retire from the active discharge of his duties, he was succeeded by Thomas Brown (1778-1820). Brown had shown early precocity, and at the age of fifteen had attracted Stewart's notice by some remarks on a psychological point. He published at twenty a criticism of Darwin'sZoonomia, and he became one of theEdinburgh Reviewcircle. When theReviewwas started he contributed an article upon Kant. In those happy days it was so far from necessary to prepare oneself for such a task by studying a library of commentators that the young reviewer could frankly admit his whole knowledge to be derived from Villers'Philosophie de Kant(1801).[466]Soon afterwards he took an important share in a once famous controversy. John Leslie, just elected to the mathematical chair at Edinburgh, was accused of having written favourably of Hume's theory of causation. Whigs and Tories took this up as a party question,[467]and Brown undertook to explain in a pamphlet what Hume's theory was, and to show that it did not lead to atheism. Leslie's friends triumphed, though it does not appear how far Brown's arguments contributed to their success. The pamphlet was rewritten and enlarged, and a thirdedition of 1818 gives a full exposition of his theory. Brown had meanwhile become Stewart's leading disciple, and in 1810 was elected to be his colleague. Brown held the position, doing all the active duties, until his premature death in 1820. Brown, according to his biographer, wrote his lectures immediately before delivery, and completed them during his first two years of office. His theories, as well as his words, were often, according to the same authority, extemporised. Brown found that he could not improve what he had written under 'very powerful excitement.' Moreover, he had an unlucky belief that he was a poet. From 1814 till 1819 he brought out yearly what he supposed to be a poem. These productions, theParadise of Coquetsand the rest, are in the old-fashioned taste, and have long passed into oblivion.
The lectures, published posthumously, became a text-book for students, and reached a nineteenth edition in 1851. Their faults, considered as philosophical treatises, are palpable. They have the wordiness of hasty composition, and the discursive rhetoric intended to catch the attention of an indolent audience. Brown does not see that he is insulting his hearers when he apologises for introducing logic into lectures upon metaphysics, and indemnifies them by quotations from Akenside and theEssay on Man. Brown, however, showed great acuteness and originality. He made deviations, and took pains to mark his deviations, from Reid, though he spoke more guardedly of his own friend, Stewart. Stewart, who had strongly supported Brown's election, was shocked when, on the publication of the lectures, he came to discover that his colleague had been preachingheresy, and wrote with obvious annoyance of Brown's hastiness and dangerous concessions to the enemy.[468]Brown, however, impressed his contemporaries by his ability. Sydney Smith is probably reporting the current judgment of his own circle when he says[469]that in metaphysics Stewart was a 'humbug' compared with Brown. I certainly think that Stewart, whom I should be sorry to call a humbug, shows less vigour and subtlety. Brown, at any rate, impressed both the Mills, and his relation to them is significant.
Brown's essay upon Causation indicates this relation. In this, indeed, there is little, if any, divergence from Stewart, though he attacks Reid with considerable asperity. He urges that Reid, while really agreeing with Hume, affected to answer him under cover of merely verbal distinctions.[470]The main point is simple. Hume had asserted that all events seem to be 'entirely loose and separate,' or, in other words, 'conjoined but never connected.' Yet he points out that, in fact, when we have found two events to be 'conjoined,' we call one cause and the other effect, and assume a 'necessary connection' between them. He then asks, What is the origin of this belief, and what, therefore, is the logical warrant for its validity? Brown entirely accepts Hume's statement of the facts. The real meaning of our statements is evaded by appealing to the conception of 'power.' When the loadstone (in his favourite illustration) attracts the iron, we say it has a 'power' of attracting iron. But to speak thus ofa power is simply to describe the same facts in other words. We assert this, and nothing more than this, that when the loadstone comes near the iron, each moves towards the other. 'Power' is a word which only covers a statement of 'invariable antecedence.' Brown traces the various confusions which have obscured the true nature of this belief. He insists especially that we can no more discover power in mental than in physical sequences. The will had been supposed to be the type of causal power; but volition, according to Brown, reveals simply another succession of desires and bodily actions. The hypothesis of 'power' has been really the source of 'illusion.' The tendency to personify leads us to convert metaphor into fact, to invent a subject of this imaginary 'power,' and thus to create a mythology of beings to carry on the processes of nature. In other words, Brown here follows Hume or even anticipates Comte. As J. S. Mill remarks,[471]this erroneous identification of 'power' with 'will' gives the 'psychological rationale of Comte's great historical generalisation'; and, so far, Brown, as a follower of Hume, is clearly on the way to positivism.
The world, then, is a vast aggregate of 'loose' phenomena. A contemplation of things reveals no reason for one order rather than another. You may look at your loadstone as long as you please, but you will find no reason for its attracting iron. You may indeed interpolate a number of minute intervening sequences, and the process often suggests a vague something more than sequence; but this is a mere illusion.[472]Could we, in fact, see all the minute changes in bodies we should actually perceive that cause means nothing but 'the immediate invariable antecedence of an event.'[473]Brown especially argues against the attempts of d'Alembert and Euler to deduce the first laws of motion from the principle of 'sufficient reason.'[474]That, as he argues in detail, is merely begging the question, by introducing the principle of causation under an alias.
What, then, is the principle? We believe, he says,[475]that 'every event must have a cause,' and that circumstances exactly 'similar must have results exactly similar.' This belief, though applicable to all events, does not give us the 'slightest aid' to determining, independently of experience, any particular event. We observe that B follows A, but, for all we can say, it might as well follow any other letter of the alphabet. Yet we are entitled to say in general that it does uniformly follow some particular letter. The metaphor which describes cause and effect as a 'bond' tying A and B together is perfectly appropriate if taken to express the bare fact of sequence;[476]but we fall into error if we fancy there is really any bond whatever beside the events themselves.
The belief, then, in causation has precisely the same import according to Hume and Brown; and both agree that it is not produced by 'reasoning.' The proposition 'B has once succeeded A,' or 'has succeeded A a thousand times,' is entirely different from the proposition 'B will for ever succeed A.'[477]No process of logical inference can extract one from the other. Shall we, then, give up a belief in causation? The belief inany case exists as a fact. Hume explains it by custom or association. Brown argues, and I think with much force, that Hume's explanation is insufficient. Association may explain (if it does more than restate) the fact that one 'idea' calls up another idea, but such association may and often does occur without suggesting any belief. The belief, too, precedes the association. We begin by believing too much, not too little, and assume a necessary connection of many phenomena which we afterwards find to be independent. The true answer is therefore different. There are three sources of belief, 'perception,' 'reasoning,' and 'intuition.'[478]Now, we cannot 'perceive' anything but a present coincidence; neither can we establish a connection by any process of 'reasoning,' and therefore the belief must be an 'intuition.' This, accordingly, is Brown's conclusion. 'There are principles,' he says, 'independent of reasoning, in the mind which save it from the occasional follies of all our ratiocinations';[479]or rather, as he explains, which underlie all reasoning. The difference, then, between Hume and Brown (and, as Brown argues, between Hume and Reid's real doctrine) is not as to the import, but as to the origin, of the belief. It is an 'intuition' simply because it cannot be further analysed. It does not allow us to pass a single step beyond experience; it merely authorises us to interpret experience. We can discover any actual law of connection between phenomena only by observing that they occur in succession.We cannot get beyond or behind the facts—and therefore intuitionism in this sense is not opposed to empiricism, but a warrant for empirical conclusions. An 'intuition,' briefly, is an unanalysable belief. Brown asserts that a certain element of thought has not been explained, and assumes it to be therefore inexplicable or ultimate. Brown's account of causation had a great influence upon both the Mills, and especially affected the teaching of the younger Mill.
Another point is important. Reid, as I have said, had specially prided himself upon his supposed overthrow of Berkeley's idealism. He was considered to have shown, in spite of sceptics, that the common belief in an external world was reasonable. Brown in his lectures ridiculed Reid's claim. This 'mighty achievement,' the 'supposed overthrow of a great system,' was 'nothing more than the proof that certain phrases are metaphorical, which were intended by their authors to be understoodonlyas metaphors.'[480]The theory was dead before Reid slew it, though the phrases were still used as a mere 'relic,' or survival of an obsolete doctrine.[481]The impossibility of constructing extension out of our sensations is theexperimentum crucisupon which Reid was ready to stake his case. If the attempt at such a construction could succeed, he would 'lay his hand upon his mouth' and give up the argument.[482]Brown takes up thechallenge thus thrown out. He holds that our knowledge of an external world is derived from a source which Reid overlooked. He modifies the Scottish psychology by introducing the muscular senses. His theory is that the infant which has learned to move discovers that on some occasions its movements are modified by a sense of 'impeded effort.'[483]The sudden interruption to a well-known series excites in its mind the notion of 'a cause which is not in itself.' This is the source of our belief in an external world. That belief is essentially the belief in some cause which we know to be other than our own mental constitution or the series of 'internal' phenomena, and of which we can know nothing else. It is enough to indicate a theory which has been elaborated by later psychologists, and plays a great part (for example) in the theories of Mill, Bain, and Mr. Herbert Spencer. It shows the real tendency of Brown's speculations. In the first place, it must be noticed that the theory itself had been already emphatically stated by Destutt de Tracy. Hamilton accuses Brown of plagiarism.[484]Whether his accusation be justifiable or not, it is certainly true that Brown had in some way reached the same principles which had been already set forth by a leading 'ideologist.' Brown, that is, though the official exponent of the Scottish philosophy,was in this philosophical tenet at one with the school which they regarded as materialistic or sceptical. The path by which he reaches his conclusions is also characteristic.
Brown has reversed the interpretation of Reid'sexperimentum crucis. I will give up my case, says Reid, if you can make the external world out of sensations. That, replies Brown, is precisely what we can do. How from sensations do we get what Berkeley called 'outness'? We get it, says Brown, from the sense of resistance or 'impeded effort.' That reveals to us the fact that there is something independent of ourselves, and the belief in such a something is precisely what we mean, and all that we mean, by the belief in an external world. Consistently with this, Brown rejects Reid's distinction between the primary and secondary qualities. The distinction corresponds no doubt to some real differences, but there is no difference of the kind suggested by Reid. 'All [the qualities] are relative and equally relative—our perception of extension and resistance as much as our perception of fragrance and bitterness.'[485]We ascribe the sensations to 'external objects,' but the objects are only known by the 'medium' of our sensations. In other words, the whole world may be regarded as a set of sensations, whether of sight, smell, touch, or resistanceto muscular movement, accompanied by the belief that they are caused by something not ourselves, and of which something we can only say that it is not ourselves.
Once more, the analysis of the process by which the belief is generated is significant. From resistance, or the sensation produced when something 'resists our attempts to grasp it,' we get the 'outness.' Then perception is 'nothing more than the association of this complex notion with our other sensations—the notion of something extended and resisting, suggested by these sensations, when the suggestions themselves have previously arisen, and suggested in the same manner and on the same principle as any other associate feeling suggests any other associate feeling.'[486]The odour or colour of a rose recalls the sensation of touching and of resistance to our grasp. Thus we regard the whole group of sensations as due to the external cause which produces the sensation of resistance. Brown seems to hesitate a little as to whether he shall appeal to an 'intuition' or to 'association,' but 'as I rather think,' he says, the belief is founded 'on associations as powerful as intuition.'[487]
Whatever, then, may be the origin of the belief—'intuition' or 'association'—it is clear that it can give us no knowledge except such as is derived from sensations. Moreover, Brown is thus led, as in the doctrine of causation, to accept a really sceptical position. He declares that he is in this respect at one with both Reid and Hume. They both accept two propositions: first, that we cannot 'by mere reasoning' prove the existence of an external world; secondly, that it is 'absolutelyimpossible for us not to believe' in its existence. Hume, he says, pronounces the first proposition in a 'loud tone of voice' and 'whispers' the second. Reid, conversely, passes over the first rapidly and 'dwells on the second with a tone of confidence.'[488]Brown accepts both statements. He has already said that there is no argument against Berkeley's denial of matter any more than against the 'infinite divisibility of matter.' But he adds, it is 'physically impossible' for us to admit the conclusion, at least without 'an instant dissent from a momentary logical admission.'[489]This, indeed, is but a version of Hume's familiar statement that Berkeley's arguments admit of no reply and produce no conviction.
Another essential doctrine of the Mills, the 'association' theory, is treated differently by Brown. Brown, as we have seen, both in his theory of causation and in his theory of our belief in an external world, speaks of principles in the mind which somehow override 'ratiocination.' In the first case, he speaks of 'intuition,' but in the other, as I have said, he seems to prefer association. The difference is remarkable because the belief in an external world is upon his showing simply a case of causation. It means essentially the reference of our sensations as to an external cause. Now, in the argument upon causation, he has insisted upon the insufficiency of association to generate the belief; and he would have found it difficult to meet his own arguments if applied to the belief in an external world. Yet it does not seem to occur to him that there is any difficulty in explaining this belief in an externalworld as a case of what Mill called 'indissoluble association.' Brown, as Mill thought, was not sufficiently aware of the power of this principle, and the difference between them is marked by this divergence. Brown had a great deal to say about association, though he chose generally to substitute the word 'suggestion,' previously familiar to Reid and Berkeley.[490]He considers it, however, mainly in another relation. He proposes to trace the order in which 'trains' of ideas succeed each other in our minds. He does not dwell upon the influence of association in producing belief. His question is not primarily as to the logic, but as to the actual succession of our thoughts. He explains that he uses the word 'suggestion' in order to avoid the hypothesis that the sequence of two ideas necessarily implies a previous state of mind in which they were brought together; and endeavours to explain various cases (as, for example, association by 'contrast' as well as by 'likeness' or 'continuity') by a more 'subtile' analysis.[491]He then works out an elaborate theory of 'simple' and 'relative' suggestion. Simple 'suggestion'[492]corresponds mainly to ordinary association, as when a friend's name or his book calls up the thought of the man himself. 'Relative suggestion' arises when two or more objects are perceived and suggest various relations of likeness and so forth.[493]This provides a scheme for working out the whole doctrine of the sequences of ideas so far as the sequences depend upon the mind itself and not upon external causes. It thus leads to problems of abstraction andgeneralisation and to his whole theory of what he calls the 'intellectual states.' He again closely coincides with the French ideologists. He starts by examining Locke and Condillac. He of course professes to hold that Condillac's version of Locke is illegitimate, and ridicules the famous formulapenser c'est sentir. He is, however, equally unwilling to admit Reid's 'variety of powers.'[494]In fact, his criticism of Condillac shows more affinity than contrast. Condillac erred, he says, in holding that thoughts are 'transformed sensations.' This was a false simplification into which he considers Condillac to have been led partly by the ambiguity of the wordsentir.[495]Condillac applied to the mind the theory, true in 'the chemistry of the material chemists,' that the 'compounds are the elements themselves.'[496]He errs when he infers from the analogy that a feeling which arises out of others can be resolved into them. 'Love and hate' and other emotions are fundamentally different from the sensations by which they are occasioned, not mere 'transformations' of those sensations. We, on the other hand (that is to say, Reid and Stewart), have erred by excessive amplification. Instead of identifying different things, we have admitted a superfluous number of 'ultimate principles.'
The result is that besides the original sensations, we have to consider a number of feelings, which, while essentially different, are 'suggested' or caused by them. These are parts of the whole intellectual construction, and, though not transformed sensations, are still 'feelings' arising in consequence of the sensations. They are partsof the 'trains' or sequences of 'ideas.' It is accordingly characteristic of Brown that he habitually describes an intellectual process as a 'feeling.' The statement of a mathematical proportion, for example, is a case of 'relative suggestion.' When we consider two numbers together we have a 'feelingof the relation of proportion.'[497]The 'profoundest reasonings' are 'nothing more than a continued analysis of our thought,' by which we resolve the 'complexfeelingsof our minds' into the simpler conceptions out of which they were constructed.[498]In other words, Brown, it would seem, really accepts thepenser c'est sentir, only that he regards thesentiras including separate classes of feeling, which cannot be regarded as simple 'transformations' of sensation. They are 'states of the mind' caused by, that is, invariably following upon, the simpler states, and, of course, combining in an endless variety of different forms. Reasoning is nothing more than a series of relative 'suggestions of which the separate subjects are felt by us to be mutually related.'[499]Hence, too, arises his theory of generalisation. He is, he says, not a 'nominalist' but a 'conceptualist,' and here, for once, agrees with Reid as against Stewart.[500]The 'general term,' according to him, expresses the 'feeling or general notion of resemblance,' which arises upon a contemplation of two objects. 'In Nature,' as he observes elsewhere,[501]'there are no classes,' but the observation of a number ofparticular cases and a certain feeling to which we give a name. Here, again, Brown's view coincides with that of his French contemporaries.