Chapter 30

Fig. 89.Anterior region of the larvaof a Midge (Corethra plumicornis).K, head.Th, thorax.ui, inferior imaginal disks.oi, superior imaginal disks.ui1,ui2, andui3, the primordia of the limbs.oi2andoi3, the primordia of the wings and'balancers.'g, brain.bg, chain of ventralganglia with nerves which enter theimaginal disks.trb, tracheal vesicle.Enlarged about 15 times.

Fig. 89.Anterior region of the larvaof a Midge (Corethra plumicornis).K, head.Th, thorax.ui, inferior imaginal disks.oi, superior imaginal disks.ui1,ui2, andui3, the primordia of the limbs.oi2andoi3, the primordia of the wings and'balancers.'g, brain.bg, chain of ventralganglia with nerves which enter theimaginal disks.trb, tracheal vesicle.Enlarged about 15 times.

This example seems to me to be preferable to that of the wings of insects in this respect, that there is no organ in the caterpillar with a specific function corresponding to the wing of the butterfly. Yet the two cases are exactly alike, and it would be a mistake to say that the first primordium of the wing within the caterpillar is not a part of the caterpillar at all. At first, certainly, it is only a group of cells on the skin, occurring at a particular spot on the dorsal surface of the second and third segments of the caterpillar, and doubtless arising from a single cell of the embryo, the 'primitive wing-cell,' which, however, has not as yet been demonstrated. But it is nevertheless an integral part of the caterpillar, which could neither be wanting, nor be larger or smaller, and so on; which, in short, does mean something for the caterpillar, although perhaps not more than any other of the skin-cells. For the butterfly, however, this area on the skin means the rudiment of the wing; for from it alone can there arise by multiplication the aggregate of cells which grows out into a hollow protuberance, enlarges by degrees into a disk, the imaginal disk, and eventually develops into the form of wing peculiar to the species. This imaginal disk is connected very early with nerves and with tracheæ, as may be beautifully seen especially in dipterous larvæ (Fig. 89,oi), and these become later the nerves and tracheæ of the wing, while thousands of peculiar scale-like hairs develop on the upper surface; in short, the rudiment becomes a perfect wing with its specific venation, and with the marking and colouring which is often so complicated in Lepidoptera. Almost every little spot and stripe of the latter is handed down with the most tenacious power of transmission from generation to generation, and each can at the same time be transmissibly varied; the same is true of the venation, which is so important systematically just because it is so strictly hereditary, yet it too can vary transmissibly, as can also the hookedbristles, the odoriferous apparatus, and, in short, the whole complex structure of the wing, with all its specific adaptations to the mode of flight, to the manner of life, and to the colour of the environment. How is it possible that all this can develop from a skin-cell? Is it the influence of position that effects it, and could any other cell of the caterpillar's skin do the same if it were placed in the same position? Could any neighbour-cell of the primitive wing-cell replace it if it were destroyed? It is hardly probable, and I think I can even prove that this is not so. The experiment of killing such a cell in the living animal has not yet been made; if it should succeed, we may venture to say in advance that none of the neighbouring skin-cells will be able to do its work and take its place in developing a wing; the wing in question will simply remain undeveloped. In the summer of 1897 I hatched a specimen ofVanessa antiopefrom the pupa, which, though otherwise normal and well-developed, lacked the left posterior wing altogether; no trace of it could be recognized. In this case, from some cause which could no longer be discovered, the first formative cell of the wing in the hypodermis, or its descendants, must have been destroyed, and no substitution of another took place, as the defect showed.

The young science of developmental mechanics attributes to the position of a cell in the midst of a group of cells a determining value as regards its further fate, and as far as the cells of the segmenting ovum are concerned this seems to be true in certain cases, but the assumption cannot be generally true except in a very subordinate sense. The formative cell of the wing does not become what it is because of its relative position in the organism. If this were so it could not happen that a wing should develop instead of a leg, as was observed in aZygæna, nor could there be any of those deformities already referred to, to which the name 'Heterotopia' is applied, and which consist in the development of organs of definite normal structure, or at any rate of apparently normal structure in quite unusual places, e. g. an antenna on the coxa of a leg, or of a leg instead of an antenna (inSirex), or instead of a wing. It is therefore not some influence from without that makes that particular skin-cell of the caterpillar the rudiment of the wing, but thereason lies within itself, in its own constitution. As the whole mass of determinants for the whole body and for all the stages of its development must be contained within the ovum and the sperm-cell, so the primitive cell of the butterfly's wing must contain all the determinants for the building up of this complicated part;and if the cell gets into a wrong position in the course of development because of some disturbance or other, a wing may develop from it in that position if the conditions are not too utterly divergent. These heterotopic phenomena afford a further proof of the existence of determinants, because they are quite unintelligible without the assumption of 'primary constituents' orAnlagen.

The hypothesis of determinants in the germ-plasm is so fundamental to my theory of development that I should like to adduce another case in its support and justification. The limbs of the jointed-footed animals, or Arthropods, originally arose as a pair on each segment of the body, and they were at first alike or very similar both in their function and in their form. We find illustration of this in the millipedes, and still more in the species of the interesting genusPeripatus, which resembles them externally, as well as in the swimming and creeping bristle-footed marine worms (Chætopods) belonging to the Annelid phylum. We can quite well picture to ourselves that the whole series of these appendages was represented in the germ-plasm by a single determinant or group of determinants, which only required to be multiplied in development. Without disputing whether this has really been the case in the primitive Arthropods or not, it is certain that it can no longer be the case in the germ-plasm of the Arthropods of to-day. In these each pair of appendages must be represented by a particular determinant. We must infer this from the fact that the several pairs of these appendages have varied transmissibly, independently of each other, for some are jaws, others swimming legs, or merely bearers of the gills or of the eggs; others are walking legs, digging legs, or jumping legs. In Crustaceans a forceps-like claw is often borne by the first of the otherwise similarly constructed appendages, or also by the second or the third, or there may be no forceps, and so on; in short, we see that each individual pair has adapted itself independently to the mode of life of its species. This could only have been possible if each was represented in the germ-plasm by an element, whose variations causeda variation only in that one pair of legs, and in no other.

It may perhaps be objected that the differences in the appendages may quite well have had their origin simply during the development of the animal, while the primary constituents were the same for all, so that a single determinant in the germ-plasm would suffice. But this could only be the case if the differences depended not on internal but on external causes, that is, if the same primary constituents gave rise to a set of appendages which became different because they weresubject in the course of their development to different modifying influences. But this is not the case, at least not to the extent that this supposition would necessitate. Can it be supposed that, for instance, the jumping legs of the water-flea (Gammarus) are a necessary consequence of the somewhat divergent form of the segments from which they grow? A direct proof to the contrary may be found in 'Heterotopia,' for in the place where a posterior limb, modified for holding the eggs, normally occurs in the crab an ordinary walking leg may exceptionally develop (Fig. 90, Bethe), or an appendage resembling an antenna may take the place of an extirpated eye (Herbst). But if there were really only one determinant in the germ-plasm for all the appendages these would of necessity be all alike, apart from the larger or smaller differences which might be stamped upon them by growing from segments different in size and in nutrition. Such differences, however, are far from being sufficient to explain the great deviations seen among the appendages of most kinds of Crustaceans, and still less to explain their adaptation to quite different functions.

Fig. 90.The Common Shore-Crab (Carcinus mænas), seen from below, with the abdomen forced back. In place of the swimmeret, which ought to be borne by the fifth abdominal swimmeret, a walking leg has grown on the left side, and one which properly should belong to the right side (6). 1-5, thoracic limbs,ps1-4, swimmerets of the right side.s6,s7, posterior segments of the abdomen. After Bethe.

Fig. 90.The Common Shore-Crab (Carcinus mænas), seen from below, with the abdomen forced back. In place of the swimmeret, which ought to be borne by the fifth abdominal swimmeret, a walking leg has grown on the left side, and one which properly should belong to the right side (6). 1-5, thoracic limbs,ps1-4, swimmerets of the right side.s6,s7, posterior segments of the abdomen. After Bethe.

It need not be imagined that my argument can be controverted by saying thatoneappendage-determinant in the germ may split itself in the course of development into a series of different appendage-determinants. The question would then arise, How is it able to do so? And the answer can be no other than that the single first determinant had within it several different kinds of elements, which subsequentlyseparated to determine in different ways the various appendages. But that is just another way of saying that this single determinant actually includes within itself several different determinants. For a determinant means nothing more than an element of the germ-substance by whose presence in the germ the specific development of a particular part of the body is conditioned. If we could remove the determinants of a particular appendage from the germ-plasm this appendage would not develop; if we could cause it to vary the appendage also would turn out differently.

In this general sense the determinants of the germ-plasm are not hypothetical, but actual; just as surely as if we had seen them with our eyes, and followed their development. Hypothesis begins when we attempt to make creatures of flesh and blood out of these mere symbols, and to say how they are constituted. But even here there are some things which may be maintained with certainty; for instance, that they arenotminiature models, in Bonnet's sense, of the parts which they determine; and, further, that they are not lifeless material, mere substances, but living parts, vital units. If this were not so they would not remain as they are throughout the course of development, but would be displaced and destroyed by the metabolism, instead of dominating it as living matter alone can do—doubtless undergoing oxidation, but at the same time assimilating material from without, and thereby growing. There cannot be lifeless determinants; they must be living units capable of nutrition, growth, and multiplication by division.

And now we have arrived at the point at which a discussion of the organization of the living substance in general can best be interpolated.

The Viennese physiologist, Ernst Brücke, forty years ago promulgated the theory that living matter could not be a mere mixture of chemical molecules of any kind whatever; it must be 'organized,' that is, it must be composed of small, invisible, vital units. If, as we must certainly assume, the mechanical theory of life is correct, if there is no vital force in the sense of the 'Natur-Philosophie,' Brücke's pronouncement is undoubtedly true; for a fortuitous mixture of molecules could no more produce the phenomena of life than asinglemolecule could, because, as far as our experience goes, molecules do not live; they neither assimilate, nor grow, nor multiply. Life can therefore arise only through a particular combination of diverse molecules, and all living substance must consist of such definite groups of molecules. Shortly after Brücke, Herbert Spencer likewise assumed the reality of such vital 'units,' and the same assumptionhas been made in more recent times by Wiesner, De Vries, and myself. In the meantime we can say nothing more definite about the composition of these bearers of life, or 'biophors,' as I call them, than that albumen-molecules, water, salts, and some other substances play the chief part in their composition. This has been found out by analysis of dead protoplasm; but in what form these substances are contained in the biophors, and how they affect each other in order to produce the phenomena of life by going through a ceaseless cycle of disruptions and reconstructions, is still entirely hidden from us.

We have, however, nothing to do with that here; we content ourselves with recognizing in the biophors the characteristics of life, and picturing to ourselves that all living substance, cell-substance, and nuclear substance, muscle-, nerve-, and gland-substance, in all their diverse forms, consist of biophors, though, of course, of the most varied composition. There must be innumerable kinds of biophors in all the diverse parts of the millions of forms of life which now live upon the earth; but all must be constructed on a certain fundamental plan, which conditions their marvellous capacity for life; all possess the fundamental characters of life—dissimilation, assimilation, growth, and multiplication by division. We must also ascribe to them in some degree the power of movement and sensibility.

As to their size, we can only say that they are far below the limits of visibility, and that even the minutest granules which we can barely perceive by means of our most powerful microscopes cannot be small individual biophors, but must be aggregates of these. On the other hand, the biophors must be larger than any chemical molecule, because they themselves consist of a group of molecules, among which are some of complex composition, and therefore of relatively considerable size.

It may now be asked whether the determinants, whose existence we have already inferred, are not identical with these 'biophors' or smallest living particles; but that is not the case, at least not generally. We called determinants those parts of the germ-substance which determine a 'hereditary character' of the body; that is, whose presence in the germ determines that a particular part of the body, whether it consists of a group of cells, a single cell, or a part of a cell, shall develop in a specific manner, and whose variations cause the variations of these particular parts alone.

Again, it may be asked how large and how numerous such 'hereditary parts' may be, whether they correspond to every distinct part of a cell, or to every cell of the body, or only to the larger cell groups. Obviously the areas which are individually determined fromthe germ must differ in size, according as we have to do with an organism which is small or large, simple or more complex. Unicellular organisms, such as Infusorians, probably possess special determinants for a number of cell-organs and cell-parts, although we cannot directly observe the independent and transmissible variation of these organs; lowly multicellular animals, such as the calcareous sponges, will require a relatively small number of determinants, but in the higher multicellular organisms, as, for instance, in most Arthropods, the number must be very high, reaching many thousands if not hundreds of thousands, for in them almost everything in the body is specialized, and must have varied through independent variation from the germ. Thus in many Crustaceans the smelling-hairs occur singly on special joints of the antennæ, and the number of joints furnished with a smelling-hair is different in different species; the size, too, of the smelling-hairs themselves varies greatly, being, for instance, much smaller in our common Asellus than in the blind form from the depths of our lakes, in which the absence of sight is compensated for by an increased acuteness of the sense of smell. Thus the smelling-hairs may vary transmissibly in themselves, while any joint of the antennæ may also produce one independently through variation. In this case accordingly we must assume that there are special determinants for the smelling-hairs, and for the joints of the antennæ. But we cannot always and everywhere refer identical or approximately similar organs, when there are many of them, to a corresponding number of determinants. Certainly the hairs of mammals or the scales of butterflies' wings do not all vary individually and independently, but those of a certain region vary together, and are therefore probably represented in the germ-plasm by a single determinant. These regions often appear to be very small, as is best seen by the fine lines, spots, and bands which compose the marking of a butterfly's wing, and still more in the odoriferous scales occurring in some butterflies, as, for instance, in the blue butterflies (Lycæna). These little lute-shaped scales do not occur in all species, and they occur in very unequal numbers even in those which possess them; there are certain species which exhibit only about a dozen, and these are all on one little spot of the wing. Since these odoriferous scales must have arisen as modifications of the ordinary hair-like scales, as one of my pupils, Dr. Köhler, has demonstrated by comparative studies, these ordinary hair-like scales must have varied transmissibly at certain spots, that is, their determinants have varied while those of the surrounding scales have not.

The case is the same in respect to the sound-producing apparatusof many insects. Many grasshoppers produce sounds by fiddling with the thigh of the hind leg on the wing, others by rubbing one anterior wing upon the other, and, indeed, always with one particular vein in one upon a particular vein in the other. One of these serves as the bow, the other as the string, of the violin, and the bow is furnished with teeth (Fig. 91), ranged beside each other in a long row, which have the same function as the colophonium of the violin, that is, to grasp and release the strings alternately, and thus to produce resounding vibrations. My pupils, Dr. Petrunkewitsch and Dr. Georg von Guaita, have recently proved that these teeth have arisen as modifications of the hairs which are scattered everywhere over the wing and leg. But only in this one place, on the so-called 'stridulating-vein,' have they been modified to form stridulating teeth (schr). Thus this vein must be capable of transmissible variation by itself alone, that is, there must be parts contained in the germ-plasm, the variation of which causes a variation solely of this individual vein and its hairs, possibly even a variation only on certain hairs on this vein.

Fig. 91.Hind leg of a Locustid(Stenobothrus protorma), after Graber.fe,femur.ti, tibia.ta, tarsal joints.schr,the stridulating ridge.

Fig. 91.Hind leg of a Locustid(Stenobothrus protorma), after Graber.fe,femur.ti, tibia.ta, tarsal joints.schr,the stridulating ridge.

On the other hand, there are also large regions, whole cell-masses of the body, which in all probability vary onlyen bloc, as, for instance, the milliards of blood-cells in Man, the hundreds of thousands or millions of cells in the liver and other glandular organs, the thousands of fibres of a muscle, or of the sinews or fascia, the cells of a cartilage or a bone, and so on. In all these cases a single determinant, or at least a few in the germ-plasm, may be enough. But in numerous cases it is impossible to say how large the region is which is controlled by a single determinant, and it is, of course, of no importance to the theory. In unicellular organisms the determinants will control parts of cells, in multicellular organisms often whole cells and groups of cells.

Perhaps an inference as to the nature of the determinants may be drawn from this with some probability, in as far as mere parts of cells may be supposed to have simpler determinants than whole cells and groups of cells. The determinants in the chromosomes of unicellular organisms may therefore often consist of single biophors, so that in this case the conception of biophors would coincide with that of determinants. In multicellular organisms, on the other hand, I should be inclined on the whole to picture the determinant as a group of biophors, which are bound together by internal forces to form a higher vital unity. This determinant must live as a whole, that is, assimilate, grow, and multiply by division, like every vital unit, and its biophors must be individually variable, so that the separate parts of a cell controlled by them may also be capable of transmissible variation. That they are so, every highly differentiated cell of a higher animal teaches us; even the smelling-hairs of a crab exhibit a stalk, a terminal knob, and an internal filament, and many muscle-, nerve-, and gland-cells are much more complex in structure.


Back to IndexNext