FOOTNOTES:1See Vol. I., pp. 78-83.2Aristotle,Metaph., VIII., iii., 1043, b, 25.3Zeller,Phil. d. Gr., II., a, 277.4Diog. L., VI., 3.5According to the very probable conjecture of Zeller,l. c.6Zeller,l. c.; Diog. L., VI., 12.7Diog., VI., 3.8For the authorities, see Zeller,op. cit., p. 263.9Diog., IX., 62.10Metaph., IV., iv., 1008, b, 12 ff.11Diss., III., xxii.12Diog., VIII., i. ff.13Diog., VI., 96.14Zeller,Ph. d. Gr., III., a, 29.15Diog., VII., 5.16Diog., VII., 183.17Ibid., 179.18Ibid., 25.19Ibid., 180 L.20Plutarch,De Stoic. Repug., iii., 2.21It is significant that the only Stoic who fell back on pure Cynicism should have been Aristo of Chios, a genuine Greek, while the only one who, like Aristotle, identified good with knowledge was Herillus, a Carthaginian.22Op. cit., p. 18, cf. p. 362.23Diog., VII., 144 ff.24Posidonius estimated the sun’s distance from the earth at 500,000,000 stades, and the moon’s distance at 2,000,000 stades, which, counting the stade at 200 yards, gives about 57,000,000 and 227,000 miles respectively. The sun’s diameter he reckoned, according to one account, at 440,000 miles, about half the real amount; according to another account at a quarter less. Zeller,op. cit., p. 190, Note 2.25For the authorities, see Zeller,op. cit., p. 139, Note 1.26Zeller, p. 155.27The Stoic necessarianism gave occasion to a repartee which has remained classical ever since, although its original authorship is known to few. A slave of Zeno’s, on receiving chastisement for a theft, tried to excuse himself by quoting his master’s principle that he was fated to steal. ‘And to be flogged for it,’ replied the philosopher, calmly continuing his predestined task. (Diog., VII., 23.)28Soph., 247, D.29Plutarch,De Comm. Notit., xxx., 2; Cicero,Acad., I., xi., 39; Diog., VII., 150; Zeller, p. 117.30Plutarch,De Stoic. Repug., xliii., 4.31Zeller, p. 201, ff.32Cicero,De Nat. Deor., II., xv., 39.33Sextus Empiricus,Adv. Math., IX., 18.34Cicero,De Nat. Deor., I., xiii., 32.35Zeller, p. 309 ff.36See Cicero,De Divinatione, I.,passim.37Plutarch,De Placit. Phil., IV., xi.38This seems the best explanation of the various statements on the subject made by our authorities, for which see Zeller, pp. 71-86.39Sextus Emp.,Adv. Math., VIII., 375.40Zeller, p. 109.41Zeller, p. 93.42Stobaeus,Eclog., II., p. 132, quoted by Ritter and Preller, p. 394; Diog., VII., 89.43‘Quid est sapientia? Semper idem velle atque idem nolle. Licet illam exceptiunculam non adicias ut rectum sit quod velis. Non potest cuiquam semper idem placere nisi rectum.’ Seneca,Epist., xx., 4.44Cicero,De Fin., I., ix., 30. In this he followed the Cyrenaics; see Diog., II., 87.45Sextus Emp.,Adv. Math., XI., 73.46‘Das platonische Gedicht vom himmlischen Gottesstaat hatte durch diestoische Auffassung der Welt als eines vom Göttlichen durchdrungenen und beseelten Körpers einen Leib bekommen, in dessen zwingenden Organismus der Einzelne als Glied beschlossen ist und sich fügen muss.’ Bruno Bauer,Christus u. d. Cäsaren, p. 328.47Zeller, p. 168, Note 2.48Diog., VII., vii., 85.49Gellius,Noct. Att., XII., v., 7, quoted by Ritter and Preller, p. 395.50Dissert., I., xix.,II.51Ibid., xxii., 9, ff.52Cicero,Tusc. Disput., IV., xix. ff.53Cic.,Tusc. Disput., IV., vi.54Zeller, p. 229.55See theDissertationsof Epictêtus throughout.56Plutarch,De Communibus Notitiis, cap. xxxiii., p. 1076 B.57Cf. Zeller, p. 583.58Zeller, pp. 260-1.59Ibid., pp. 267-8.60Ibid., p. 270.61Cicero,De Fin., III., xvii., 58;Acad., I., x., 37;De Off., I., iii., 8.62De Off., I., vi.63I., viii.64I., xviii-xxiii.65Pyrrh. Hyp., III., 201.66Cic.,De Off., III., xxiii., 91.67Cic.,De Off., III., xii., 51.68Ibid., xxiii., 89.69Plutarch,De Comm. Notit., xi., 8.70Cf. Zeller, pp. 263-4, 278-84.71Diog., VII., 130; Cic.,De Fin., III., xviii., 60; Zeller, pp. 305-9.72Diog., VII., 31, 176.73Plutarch,De Stoic. Repug., xviii., 5.74‘Omnia scelera, etiam ante effectum operis, quantum culpae satis est, perfecta sunt.’—Seneca,De Const. Sap., vii., 4. Cf. ZenoapudSext. Emp.,Adv. Math., XI., 190.75‘Prope est a te Deus, tecum est, intus est ... sacer intra nos spiritus sedet bonorum malorumque nostrorum observator et custos.’—Seneca,Epp., xli., 1. Cf. Horace,Epp., I., i., 61; Lucan, IX., 573; Persius, III., 43; Juvenal, XIII., 192-235.76It may be desirable to give some reasons in support of this opinion, as the contrary has been stated by scholars writing within a comparatively recent period. Thus Welcker says: ‘Das Gewissen ward bei den Griechen als ein göttliches Wesen, Erinys, gescheut und wie wir es sonst nicht finden, zur Gottheit erhoben’ (Griechische Götterlehre, I., 233); and again (p. 699) ‘Ἐρινύς ... ist das Gewissen.’ Similarly, M. Alfred Maury observes that, ‘les remords se personnifiaient sous la forme de déesses Erinnyies, chargées de punir tous les forfaits’ (Histoire des Religions de la Grèce Antique, I., 342). And Preller, while entertaining sounder views respecting their origin, contents himself with the caution that, ‘Man sich hüten muss die Furien blos fur die subjectiven Mächte des menschlichen Gewissen zu halten’ (Griechische Mythologie, I., 686, 3rd ed.). Now, in the first place, the Erinyes did not punish all crime, as they ought to have done had they represented conscience. According to Aeschylus (Eumen., 604-5), they considered that the murder of her husband by Clytaemnestra was no affair of theirs, there being no blood relationship between the parties concerned. They did not persecute Electra, who, short of striking the fatal blow, had as much hand in her mother’s death as Orestes. And even when a father was killed by his son, they do not always seem to have taken up the matter; for in theOdysseyit is not by the Erinyes of Laius, but by those of Epicastê that Oedipus is pursued—a conception very unlike that of Sophocles, who makes him feel as much remorse for the parricide as for the incest and its consequences. In the next place, the Erinyes are let loose not by the action itself but by the curses of the injured or offended blood-relation, as we see by Homer,Il., IX., 454 and 566; which seems to show that if they personified anything human it was the imprecations of the victim, not the self-reproach of the aggressor. Thirdly, the Orestes of Aeschylus, so far from feeling conscience-smitten, disclaims all responsibility for his mother’s death, inflicted as it was in consequence of a direct command from the higher gods, accompanied by threats of heavy punishment in case of disobedience. (Eumen., 443 ff.). And, finally, the office assigned to the Erinyes of seeing that the laws of nature are not broken (vol. I., 67) shows that the Greeks conceived their existence as something altogether objective and physical. [There is a short but very sensible account of the Erinyes in Keightley’sMythology, p. 175, 4th ed.]77Cicero,De Off., I., xxxi.; Epictêtus,Man., 17,b., 30;Diss., I., ii., 33; xvi., 20; xxix., 39; II., v., 10;ib., 21; x., 4, xiv., 8; xxiii., 38; xxv., 22; Antoninus,Comm., VI., 39, 43; IX., 29; cf. Seneca,Epp., lxxxv., 34, and the saying of Marcus Aurelius quoted by Dion Cassius (Epit., LXXI., xxxiv., 4), that we cannot make men what we wish them to be; we can only turn what faculties they have to the best account in working for the public good.78For the references to these and other similar passages, see the last note.79Plutarch,De Alex. Virt., I., vi.; Diog., VII., 33.80It need hardly be observed that here also the morality of natural law has attained its highest artistic development under the hand of George Eliot—sometimes even to the neglect of purely artistic effect, as inDaniel Derondaand theSpanish Gypsy.81Zeller, p. 297, followed by Mr. Capes, in his excellent little work on Stoicism (p. 51).82Seneca,De Irâ, I., v., 2 ff.; II., xxxi., 7;De Clem., I., iii., 2; DeBenef., IV., xxvi., I,Epp., xcv., 51 ff.; Epictêtus,Diss., IV., v., 10; Antoninus, VII., 13; together with the additional references given by Zeller, p. 286 ff. It is to be observed that the mutual love attributed to human beings by the Stoic philosophers stands, not for an empirical characteristic, but for an unrealised idea of human nature. The actual feelings of men towards one another are described by Seneca in language recalling that of Schopenhauer and Leopardi. ‘Erras,’ he exclaims, ‘si istorum tibi qui occurrunt vultibus credis: hominum effigies habent, animos ferarum: nisi quod illarum perniciosior est primus incursus. Nunquam enim illas ad nocendum nisi necessitas inicit: aut fame aut timore coguntur ad pugnam: homini perdere hominem libet.’—Epp., ciii., 2.83Plato,Protagoras, 337, D.84‘He [Charles Austin] presented the Benthamic doctrines in the most startling form of which they were susceptible, exaggerating everything in them which tended to consequences offensive to any one’s preconceived feelings.’—Mill’sAutobiography, p. 78.85Zeller, p. 281.86‘Homo sacra res homini jam per lusum et jocum occiditur ... satisque spectaculi ex homine mors est.’—Seneca,Epp., xcv., 33. ‘Servi sunt? Immo homines. Servi sunt? Immo contubernales. Servi sunt? Immo humiles amici. Servi sunt? Immo conservi.’—Ibid., xlvii., 1. Compare the treatiseDe Irâ,passim.87Seneca once lets falls the words, ‘fortuna aequo jure genitos alium alii donavit.’—Consol. ad Marciam, xx, 2; but this is the only expression of the kind that we have been able to discover in a Stoic writer of the empire.88Seneca,Epp., lxxx.89‘L’empereur avait pour principe de maintenir les anciennes maximes romaines dans leur intégrité.’ (Renan’sMarc-Aurèle, p. 54.) The authority given by M. Renan is Dion Cass., LXXI., xxxiv.; where, however, there is nothing of the kind stated. Capitolinus says (Anton. Phil., cap. xi.): ‘Jus autem magis vetus restituit quam novum fecit.’90Renan, p. 30; Capitolinus,Anton. Phil., xii.; Dion Cass.,Epit., LXXI., xxix., 3.91Antoninus,Comm., VI., 46; X., 8.92The expressions used by M. Ernest Renan when treating of this subject are somewhat conflicting. In reference to the penal enactments against Christianity under Marcus Aurelius, he first states that, however objectionable they may have been, ‘en tout cas dans l’application la mansuétude du bon empereur fut à l’abri de tout reproche’ (Marc-Aurèle, p. 58.) Further on, however we are told that when the martyrs of Lyons appealed to Rome, ‘la réponse impériale arriva en fin. Elle était dure et cruelle.’ (p. 329.) And subsequently M. Renan makes the Emperor personally responsible for the atrocities practised on that occasion by observing, ‘Si Marc-Aurèle, au lieu d’employer les lions et la chaise rougie,’ &c. (p. 345.) But perhaps such inconsistencies are to be expected in a writer who has elevated the necessity of perpetual self-contradiction into a principle.93Epictêtus,Diss., III., xxiv.94Seneca,De Irâ, I., xiv., 2;De Clement., I., vi., 2.95Diog., VII., 91. Ziegler (Gesch. d. Ethik, Bonn, 1882, I., 174) holds, in opposition to Zeller, that originally every Stoic, as such, was assumed to be a perfect sage, and that the question was only whether the ideal had ever been realised outside the school. This, however, goes against the evidence of Plutarch, who tells as (De Stoic. Repug., xxxi., 5) that Chrysippus neither professed to be good himself nor supposed that any of his friends or teachers or disciples was good.96Seneca,Epp., cxvi., 4. It must be borne in mind that Panaetius was speaking at a time when the object of passion would at best be either another man’s wife or a member of thedemi-monde.97Comm., VII., 26; XII., 16.98See especially Antoninus,Comm., IX., 1.99Friedländer,Römische Sittengeschichte, I., 463; Duruy,Histoire des Romains, V., 349 ff., 370; cf. Gaston Boissier,La Religion Romaine, II., 152 ff., 212 ff.100This idea is most distinctly expressed by Marcus Aurelius, II., 1, and VII., 13.101For the authorities, see Zeller, p. 176.102See especially Seneca,Epp., lxiv., and the whole treatiseDe Providentiâ.103See,inter alia,Comm., IV., 3; VI., 15, 37; VII., 21, 49; XI., 1; XII., 7, 21, 23, 24, 26, 31, 32.104Comm., XI., 28, xii. 14. A modern disciple of Aurelius has expressed himself to the same purpose in slightly different language:—‘Long fed on boundless hopes, O race of man,How angrily thou spurn’st all simpler fare!“Christ,” some one says, “was human as we are.No judge eyes us from heaven our sin to scan;We live no more, when we have done our span.”“Well, then, for Christ,” thou answerest, “who can care?From sin, which Heaven records not, why forbear?Live we, like brutes, our life without a plan!”So answerest thou; but why not rather say:“Hath man no second life?—Pitch this one high!Sits there no judge in Heaven, our sin to see?More strictly, then, the inward judge obey!Was Christ a man like us?—Ah! let us tryIf we then, too, can be such men as he!”’—The Better Part, by Mr. Matthew Arnold. The italics are in the original.105First Principles, § 177.106See an article entitled ‘Pantheism and Cosmic Emotion,’ by Frederic Harrison, in theNineteenth Centuryfor August, 1881.107From the Hymn of Cleanthes, translated by Mr. Francis Newman inThe Soul, p. 73, fifth edition.108Epicureanism, p. 1.109Ph. d. Gr., III., a, p. 380.110Op. cit., p. 72.111Short Studies, III., p. 246.112Gesch. des Mater., I., p. 92.113Pollock’sSpinoza, p. 64.114Epicuro e l’Epicurismo, Florence, 1877, p. 29.115Lucretii Philosophia cum fontibus comparata, Groningen, 1877, p. 137.116Dialogues Philosophiques, p. 54, quoted by Woltjer,loc. cit.117Diog. L., X., 142.118Ibid., 113.119Diog. L., X., 134.120Cicero,Acad., II., xxxiii., 106.121Cicero,De Fin., II., xxx., 96;Diog., X., 22. Cicero translates the words διαλογισμῶν μνήμῃ, ‘memoria rationum inventorumque nostrorum.’ They may refer merely to the pleasure derived from intellectual conversation.122The authorities for the life of Epicurus are given by Zeller,op. cit., p. 363 ff.123Diog., II., 92.124Zeller,Ph. d. Gr., II., a, 294.125Cf. Plato,Protag., 353, C, ff., with Epicurus in the letter to Menoeceus, quoted by Diog., X., 129.126Morale d’Épicure, p. 20.127Wallace’sÉpicureanism, p. 154; Guyau,Morale d’Épicure, p. 34.128Cicero,Tusc. Disput., III., xviii., 41; Zeller, III., a, p. 444.129Zeller, p. 460.130Ibid., p. 581.131Diog., II., 72.132Diog., X., 131.133Guyau,Morale d’Épicure, p. 55.134Diog., X., 118.135Lucret., IV., 1057-66.136Diog., X., 117, 118.137Cicero,De Fin., V., xxvii., 80; Diog., X., 118.138That is, if we assume what Aristotle says on the subject to be derived from common usage (Eth. Nic., III., ix., p. 1115, a, 33).139Cicero,Tusc. Disp., II., xii., 28.140Cicero,De Fin., I., xv.;Tusc., V., xxviii.141Diog., X., 150 ff.142Wallace, p. 162; Diog., X., 150.143Epicureanism, pp. 162-3.144Cicero,De Fin., II., vii., 20;De Nat. Deor., I., xvii., 45, xxx., 85.145Diog., X., 150-1.146V., 1145-59.147Cicero,De Fin., II., xvii., 57.148Op. cit., p. 163.149The lamented Prof. T. H. Green may be mentioned as another example of a high-minded thinker who was also an ardent and active politician. With regard to antiquity, see the splendid roll of public-spirited philosophers enumerated by Plutarch,Adv. Col., xxxii.150Op. cit., p. 164.151J. S. Mill observed, in a conversation with Mr. John Morley, reported by the latter, that ‘in his youth mere negation of religion was a firm bond of union, social and otherwise, between men who agreed in nothing else.’—Fortnightly Review, vol. XIII., p. 675.152Cicero,De Nat. Deor., L., 18-24.153Woltjer,Lucret. Ph., p. 74.154‘Das Staatsgesetz oder das dem Gesetz gleichkommende väterliche Herkommen bildet einen Gegensatz gegen ein abgeschlossenes Priesterthum und dessen natürlichen Einfluss.’ Welcker,Gr. Götterlehre, II., p. 45. ‘La religion romaine, comme toutes celles où domine l’esprit laïque, diminue le rôle du prêtre.’ Gaston Boissier,La Religion Romaine, I., p. 16.
1See Vol. I., pp. 78-83.
1See Vol. I., pp. 78-83.
2Aristotle,Metaph., VIII., iii., 1043, b, 25.
2Aristotle,Metaph., VIII., iii., 1043, b, 25.
3Zeller,Phil. d. Gr., II., a, 277.
3Zeller,Phil. d. Gr., II., a, 277.
4Diog. L., VI., 3.
4Diog. L., VI., 3.
5According to the very probable conjecture of Zeller,l. c.
5According to the very probable conjecture of Zeller,l. c.
6Zeller,l. c.; Diog. L., VI., 12.
6Zeller,l. c.; Diog. L., VI., 12.
7Diog., VI., 3.
7Diog., VI., 3.
8For the authorities, see Zeller,op. cit., p. 263.
8For the authorities, see Zeller,op. cit., p. 263.
9Diog., IX., 62.
9Diog., IX., 62.
10Metaph., IV., iv., 1008, b, 12 ff.
10Metaph., IV., iv., 1008, b, 12 ff.
11Diss., III., xxii.
11Diss., III., xxii.
12Diog., VIII., i. ff.
12Diog., VIII., i. ff.
13Diog., VI., 96.
13Diog., VI., 96.
14Zeller,Ph. d. Gr., III., a, 29.
14Zeller,Ph. d. Gr., III., a, 29.
15Diog., VII., 5.
15Diog., VII., 5.
16Diog., VII., 183.
16Diog., VII., 183.
17Ibid., 179.
17Ibid., 179.
18Ibid., 25.
18Ibid., 25.
19Ibid., 180 L.
19Ibid., 180 L.
20Plutarch,De Stoic. Repug., iii., 2.
20Plutarch,De Stoic. Repug., iii., 2.
21It is significant that the only Stoic who fell back on pure Cynicism should have been Aristo of Chios, a genuine Greek, while the only one who, like Aristotle, identified good with knowledge was Herillus, a Carthaginian.
21It is significant that the only Stoic who fell back on pure Cynicism should have been Aristo of Chios, a genuine Greek, while the only one who, like Aristotle, identified good with knowledge was Herillus, a Carthaginian.
22Op. cit., p. 18, cf. p. 362.
22Op. cit., p. 18, cf. p. 362.
23Diog., VII., 144 ff.
23Diog., VII., 144 ff.
24Posidonius estimated the sun’s distance from the earth at 500,000,000 stades, and the moon’s distance at 2,000,000 stades, which, counting the stade at 200 yards, gives about 57,000,000 and 227,000 miles respectively. The sun’s diameter he reckoned, according to one account, at 440,000 miles, about half the real amount; according to another account at a quarter less. Zeller,op. cit., p. 190, Note 2.
24Posidonius estimated the sun’s distance from the earth at 500,000,000 stades, and the moon’s distance at 2,000,000 stades, which, counting the stade at 200 yards, gives about 57,000,000 and 227,000 miles respectively. The sun’s diameter he reckoned, according to one account, at 440,000 miles, about half the real amount; according to another account at a quarter less. Zeller,op. cit., p. 190, Note 2.
25For the authorities, see Zeller,op. cit., p. 139, Note 1.
25For the authorities, see Zeller,op. cit., p. 139, Note 1.
26Zeller, p. 155.
26Zeller, p. 155.
27The Stoic necessarianism gave occasion to a repartee which has remained classical ever since, although its original authorship is known to few. A slave of Zeno’s, on receiving chastisement for a theft, tried to excuse himself by quoting his master’s principle that he was fated to steal. ‘And to be flogged for it,’ replied the philosopher, calmly continuing his predestined task. (Diog., VII., 23.)
27The Stoic necessarianism gave occasion to a repartee which has remained classical ever since, although its original authorship is known to few. A slave of Zeno’s, on receiving chastisement for a theft, tried to excuse himself by quoting his master’s principle that he was fated to steal. ‘And to be flogged for it,’ replied the philosopher, calmly continuing his predestined task. (Diog., VII., 23.)
28Soph., 247, D.
28Soph., 247, D.
29Plutarch,De Comm. Notit., xxx., 2; Cicero,Acad., I., xi., 39; Diog., VII., 150; Zeller, p. 117.
29Plutarch,De Comm. Notit., xxx., 2; Cicero,Acad., I., xi., 39; Diog., VII., 150; Zeller, p. 117.
30Plutarch,De Stoic. Repug., xliii., 4.
30Plutarch,De Stoic. Repug., xliii., 4.
31Zeller, p. 201, ff.
31Zeller, p. 201, ff.
32Cicero,De Nat. Deor., II., xv., 39.
32Cicero,De Nat. Deor., II., xv., 39.
33Sextus Empiricus,Adv. Math., IX., 18.
33Sextus Empiricus,Adv. Math., IX., 18.
34Cicero,De Nat. Deor., I., xiii., 32.
34Cicero,De Nat. Deor., I., xiii., 32.
35Zeller, p. 309 ff.
35Zeller, p. 309 ff.
36See Cicero,De Divinatione, I.,passim.
36See Cicero,De Divinatione, I.,passim.
37Plutarch,De Placit. Phil., IV., xi.
37Plutarch,De Placit. Phil., IV., xi.
38This seems the best explanation of the various statements on the subject made by our authorities, for which see Zeller, pp. 71-86.
38This seems the best explanation of the various statements on the subject made by our authorities, for which see Zeller, pp. 71-86.
39Sextus Emp.,Adv. Math., VIII., 375.
39Sextus Emp.,Adv. Math., VIII., 375.
40Zeller, p. 109.
40Zeller, p. 109.
41Zeller, p. 93.
41Zeller, p. 93.
42Stobaeus,Eclog., II., p. 132, quoted by Ritter and Preller, p. 394; Diog., VII., 89.
42Stobaeus,Eclog., II., p. 132, quoted by Ritter and Preller, p. 394; Diog., VII., 89.
43‘Quid est sapientia? Semper idem velle atque idem nolle. Licet illam exceptiunculam non adicias ut rectum sit quod velis. Non potest cuiquam semper idem placere nisi rectum.’ Seneca,Epist., xx., 4.
43‘Quid est sapientia? Semper idem velle atque idem nolle. Licet illam exceptiunculam non adicias ut rectum sit quod velis. Non potest cuiquam semper idem placere nisi rectum.’ Seneca,Epist., xx., 4.
44Cicero,De Fin., I., ix., 30. In this he followed the Cyrenaics; see Diog., II., 87.
44Cicero,De Fin., I., ix., 30. In this he followed the Cyrenaics; see Diog., II., 87.
45Sextus Emp.,Adv. Math., XI., 73.
45Sextus Emp.,Adv. Math., XI., 73.
46‘Das platonische Gedicht vom himmlischen Gottesstaat hatte durch diestoische Auffassung der Welt als eines vom Göttlichen durchdrungenen und beseelten Körpers einen Leib bekommen, in dessen zwingenden Organismus der Einzelne als Glied beschlossen ist und sich fügen muss.’ Bruno Bauer,Christus u. d. Cäsaren, p. 328.
46‘Das platonische Gedicht vom himmlischen Gottesstaat hatte durch diestoische Auffassung der Welt als eines vom Göttlichen durchdrungenen und beseelten Körpers einen Leib bekommen, in dessen zwingenden Organismus der Einzelne als Glied beschlossen ist und sich fügen muss.’ Bruno Bauer,Christus u. d. Cäsaren, p. 328.
47Zeller, p. 168, Note 2.
47Zeller, p. 168, Note 2.
48Diog., VII., vii., 85.
48Diog., VII., vii., 85.
49Gellius,Noct. Att., XII., v., 7, quoted by Ritter and Preller, p. 395.
49Gellius,Noct. Att., XII., v., 7, quoted by Ritter and Preller, p. 395.
50Dissert., I., xix.,II.
50Dissert., I., xix.,II.
51Ibid., xxii., 9, ff.
51Ibid., xxii., 9, ff.
52Cicero,Tusc. Disput., IV., xix. ff.
52Cicero,Tusc. Disput., IV., xix. ff.
53Cic.,Tusc. Disput., IV., vi.
53Cic.,Tusc. Disput., IV., vi.
54Zeller, p. 229.
54Zeller, p. 229.
55See theDissertationsof Epictêtus throughout.
55See theDissertationsof Epictêtus throughout.
56Plutarch,De Communibus Notitiis, cap. xxxiii., p. 1076 B.
56Plutarch,De Communibus Notitiis, cap. xxxiii., p. 1076 B.
57Cf. Zeller, p. 583.
57Cf. Zeller, p. 583.
58Zeller, pp. 260-1.
58Zeller, pp. 260-1.
59Ibid., pp. 267-8.
59Ibid., pp. 267-8.
60Ibid., p. 270.
60Ibid., p. 270.
61Cicero,De Fin., III., xvii., 58;Acad., I., x., 37;De Off., I., iii., 8.
61Cicero,De Fin., III., xvii., 58;Acad., I., x., 37;De Off., I., iii., 8.
62De Off., I., vi.
62De Off., I., vi.
63I., viii.
63I., viii.
64I., xviii-xxiii.
64I., xviii-xxiii.
65Pyrrh. Hyp., III., 201.
65Pyrrh. Hyp., III., 201.
66Cic.,De Off., III., xxiii., 91.
66Cic.,De Off., III., xxiii., 91.
67Cic.,De Off., III., xii., 51.
67Cic.,De Off., III., xii., 51.
68Ibid., xxiii., 89.
68Ibid., xxiii., 89.
69Plutarch,De Comm. Notit., xi., 8.
69Plutarch,De Comm. Notit., xi., 8.
70Cf. Zeller, pp. 263-4, 278-84.
70Cf. Zeller, pp. 263-4, 278-84.
71Diog., VII., 130; Cic.,De Fin., III., xviii., 60; Zeller, pp. 305-9.
71Diog., VII., 130; Cic.,De Fin., III., xviii., 60; Zeller, pp. 305-9.
72Diog., VII., 31, 176.
72Diog., VII., 31, 176.
73Plutarch,De Stoic. Repug., xviii., 5.
73Plutarch,De Stoic. Repug., xviii., 5.
74‘Omnia scelera, etiam ante effectum operis, quantum culpae satis est, perfecta sunt.’—Seneca,De Const. Sap., vii., 4. Cf. ZenoapudSext. Emp.,Adv. Math., XI., 190.
74‘Omnia scelera, etiam ante effectum operis, quantum culpae satis est, perfecta sunt.’—Seneca,De Const. Sap., vii., 4. Cf. ZenoapudSext. Emp.,Adv. Math., XI., 190.
75‘Prope est a te Deus, tecum est, intus est ... sacer intra nos spiritus sedet bonorum malorumque nostrorum observator et custos.’—Seneca,Epp., xli., 1. Cf. Horace,Epp., I., i., 61; Lucan, IX., 573; Persius, III., 43; Juvenal, XIII., 192-235.
75‘Prope est a te Deus, tecum est, intus est ... sacer intra nos spiritus sedet bonorum malorumque nostrorum observator et custos.’—Seneca,Epp., xli., 1. Cf. Horace,Epp., I., i., 61; Lucan, IX., 573; Persius, III., 43; Juvenal, XIII., 192-235.
76It may be desirable to give some reasons in support of this opinion, as the contrary has been stated by scholars writing within a comparatively recent period. Thus Welcker says: ‘Das Gewissen ward bei den Griechen als ein göttliches Wesen, Erinys, gescheut und wie wir es sonst nicht finden, zur Gottheit erhoben’ (Griechische Götterlehre, I., 233); and again (p. 699) ‘Ἐρινύς ... ist das Gewissen.’ Similarly, M. Alfred Maury observes that, ‘les remords se personnifiaient sous la forme de déesses Erinnyies, chargées de punir tous les forfaits’ (Histoire des Religions de la Grèce Antique, I., 342). And Preller, while entertaining sounder views respecting their origin, contents himself with the caution that, ‘Man sich hüten muss die Furien blos fur die subjectiven Mächte des menschlichen Gewissen zu halten’ (Griechische Mythologie, I., 686, 3rd ed.). Now, in the first place, the Erinyes did not punish all crime, as they ought to have done had they represented conscience. According to Aeschylus (Eumen., 604-5), they considered that the murder of her husband by Clytaemnestra was no affair of theirs, there being no blood relationship between the parties concerned. They did not persecute Electra, who, short of striking the fatal blow, had as much hand in her mother’s death as Orestes. And even when a father was killed by his son, they do not always seem to have taken up the matter; for in theOdysseyit is not by the Erinyes of Laius, but by those of Epicastê that Oedipus is pursued—a conception very unlike that of Sophocles, who makes him feel as much remorse for the parricide as for the incest and its consequences. In the next place, the Erinyes are let loose not by the action itself but by the curses of the injured or offended blood-relation, as we see by Homer,Il., IX., 454 and 566; which seems to show that if they personified anything human it was the imprecations of the victim, not the self-reproach of the aggressor. Thirdly, the Orestes of Aeschylus, so far from feeling conscience-smitten, disclaims all responsibility for his mother’s death, inflicted as it was in consequence of a direct command from the higher gods, accompanied by threats of heavy punishment in case of disobedience. (Eumen., 443 ff.). And, finally, the office assigned to the Erinyes of seeing that the laws of nature are not broken (vol. I., 67) shows that the Greeks conceived their existence as something altogether objective and physical. [There is a short but very sensible account of the Erinyes in Keightley’sMythology, p. 175, 4th ed.]
76It may be desirable to give some reasons in support of this opinion, as the contrary has been stated by scholars writing within a comparatively recent period. Thus Welcker says: ‘Das Gewissen ward bei den Griechen als ein göttliches Wesen, Erinys, gescheut und wie wir es sonst nicht finden, zur Gottheit erhoben’ (Griechische Götterlehre, I., 233); and again (p. 699) ‘Ἐρινύς ... ist das Gewissen.’ Similarly, M. Alfred Maury observes that, ‘les remords se personnifiaient sous la forme de déesses Erinnyies, chargées de punir tous les forfaits’ (Histoire des Religions de la Grèce Antique, I., 342). And Preller, while entertaining sounder views respecting their origin, contents himself with the caution that, ‘Man sich hüten muss die Furien blos fur die subjectiven Mächte des menschlichen Gewissen zu halten’ (Griechische Mythologie, I., 686, 3rd ed.). Now, in the first place, the Erinyes did not punish all crime, as they ought to have done had they represented conscience. According to Aeschylus (Eumen., 604-5), they considered that the murder of her husband by Clytaemnestra was no affair of theirs, there being no blood relationship between the parties concerned. They did not persecute Electra, who, short of striking the fatal blow, had as much hand in her mother’s death as Orestes. And even when a father was killed by his son, they do not always seem to have taken up the matter; for in theOdysseyit is not by the Erinyes of Laius, but by those of Epicastê that Oedipus is pursued—a conception very unlike that of Sophocles, who makes him feel as much remorse for the parricide as for the incest and its consequences. In the next place, the Erinyes are let loose not by the action itself but by the curses of the injured or offended blood-relation, as we see by Homer,Il., IX., 454 and 566; which seems to show that if they personified anything human it was the imprecations of the victim, not the self-reproach of the aggressor. Thirdly, the Orestes of Aeschylus, so far from feeling conscience-smitten, disclaims all responsibility for his mother’s death, inflicted as it was in consequence of a direct command from the higher gods, accompanied by threats of heavy punishment in case of disobedience. (Eumen., 443 ff.). And, finally, the office assigned to the Erinyes of seeing that the laws of nature are not broken (vol. I., 67) shows that the Greeks conceived their existence as something altogether objective and physical. [There is a short but very sensible account of the Erinyes in Keightley’sMythology, p. 175, 4th ed.]
77Cicero,De Off., I., xxxi.; Epictêtus,Man., 17,b., 30;Diss., I., ii., 33; xvi., 20; xxix., 39; II., v., 10;ib., 21; x., 4, xiv., 8; xxiii., 38; xxv., 22; Antoninus,Comm., VI., 39, 43; IX., 29; cf. Seneca,Epp., lxxxv., 34, and the saying of Marcus Aurelius quoted by Dion Cassius (Epit., LXXI., xxxiv., 4), that we cannot make men what we wish them to be; we can only turn what faculties they have to the best account in working for the public good.
77Cicero,De Off., I., xxxi.; Epictêtus,Man., 17,b., 30;Diss., I., ii., 33; xvi., 20; xxix., 39; II., v., 10;ib., 21; x., 4, xiv., 8; xxiii., 38; xxv., 22; Antoninus,Comm., VI., 39, 43; IX., 29; cf. Seneca,Epp., lxxxv., 34, and the saying of Marcus Aurelius quoted by Dion Cassius (Epit., LXXI., xxxiv., 4), that we cannot make men what we wish them to be; we can only turn what faculties they have to the best account in working for the public good.
78For the references to these and other similar passages, see the last note.
78For the references to these and other similar passages, see the last note.
79Plutarch,De Alex. Virt., I., vi.; Diog., VII., 33.
79Plutarch,De Alex. Virt., I., vi.; Diog., VII., 33.
80It need hardly be observed that here also the morality of natural law has attained its highest artistic development under the hand of George Eliot—sometimes even to the neglect of purely artistic effect, as inDaniel Derondaand theSpanish Gypsy.
80It need hardly be observed that here also the morality of natural law has attained its highest artistic development under the hand of George Eliot—sometimes even to the neglect of purely artistic effect, as inDaniel Derondaand theSpanish Gypsy.
81Zeller, p. 297, followed by Mr. Capes, in his excellent little work on Stoicism (p. 51).
81Zeller, p. 297, followed by Mr. Capes, in his excellent little work on Stoicism (p. 51).
82Seneca,De Irâ, I., v., 2 ff.; II., xxxi., 7;De Clem., I., iii., 2; DeBenef., IV., xxvi., I,Epp., xcv., 51 ff.; Epictêtus,Diss., IV., v., 10; Antoninus, VII., 13; together with the additional references given by Zeller, p. 286 ff. It is to be observed that the mutual love attributed to human beings by the Stoic philosophers stands, not for an empirical characteristic, but for an unrealised idea of human nature. The actual feelings of men towards one another are described by Seneca in language recalling that of Schopenhauer and Leopardi. ‘Erras,’ he exclaims, ‘si istorum tibi qui occurrunt vultibus credis: hominum effigies habent, animos ferarum: nisi quod illarum perniciosior est primus incursus. Nunquam enim illas ad nocendum nisi necessitas inicit: aut fame aut timore coguntur ad pugnam: homini perdere hominem libet.’—Epp., ciii., 2.
82Seneca,De Irâ, I., v., 2 ff.; II., xxxi., 7;De Clem., I., iii., 2; DeBenef., IV., xxvi., I,Epp., xcv., 51 ff.; Epictêtus,Diss., IV., v., 10; Antoninus, VII., 13; together with the additional references given by Zeller, p. 286 ff. It is to be observed that the mutual love attributed to human beings by the Stoic philosophers stands, not for an empirical characteristic, but for an unrealised idea of human nature. The actual feelings of men towards one another are described by Seneca in language recalling that of Schopenhauer and Leopardi. ‘Erras,’ he exclaims, ‘si istorum tibi qui occurrunt vultibus credis: hominum effigies habent, animos ferarum: nisi quod illarum perniciosior est primus incursus. Nunquam enim illas ad nocendum nisi necessitas inicit: aut fame aut timore coguntur ad pugnam: homini perdere hominem libet.’—Epp., ciii., 2.
83Plato,Protagoras, 337, D.
83Plato,Protagoras, 337, D.
84‘He [Charles Austin] presented the Benthamic doctrines in the most startling form of which they were susceptible, exaggerating everything in them which tended to consequences offensive to any one’s preconceived feelings.’—Mill’sAutobiography, p. 78.
84‘He [Charles Austin] presented the Benthamic doctrines in the most startling form of which they were susceptible, exaggerating everything in them which tended to consequences offensive to any one’s preconceived feelings.’—Mill’sAutobiography, p. 78.
85Zeller, p. 281.
85Zeller, p. 281.
86‘Homo sacra res homini jam per lusum et jocum occiditur ... satisque spectaculi ex homine mors est.’—Seneca,Epp., xcv., 33. ‘Servi sunt? Immo homines. Servi sunt? Immo contubernales. Servi sunt? Immo humiles amici. Servi sunt? Immo conservi.’—Ibid., xlvii., 1. Compare the treatiseDe Irâ,passim.
86‘Homo sacra res homini jam per lusum et jocum occiditur ... satisque spectaculi ex homine mors est.’—Seneca,Epp., xcv., 33. ‘Servi sunt? Immo homines. Servi sunt? Immo contubernales. Servi sunt? Immo humiles amici. Servi sunt? Immo conservi.’—Ibid., xlvii., 1. Compare the treatiseDe Irâ,passim.
87Seneca once lets falls the words, ‘fortuna aequo jure genitos alium alii donavit.’—Consol. ad Marciam, xx, 2; but this is the only expression of the kind that we have been able to discover in a Stoic writer of the empire.
87Seneca once lets falls the words, ‘fortuna aequo jure genitos alium alii donavit.’—Consol. ad Marciam, xx, 2; but this is the only expression of the kind that we have been able to discover in a Stoic writer of the empire.
88Seneca,Epp., lxxx.
88Seneca,Epp., lxxx.
89‘L’empereur avait pour principe de maintenir les anciennes maximes romaines dans leur intégrité.’ (Renan’sMarc-Aurèle, p. 54.) The authority given by M. Renan is Dion Cass., LXXI., xxxiv.; where, however, there is nothing of the kind stated. Capitolinus says (Anton. Phil., cap. xi.): ‘Jus autem magis vetus restituit quam novum fecit.’
89‘L’empereur avait pour principe de maintenir les anciennes maximes romaines dans leur intégrité.’ (Renan’sMarc-Aurèle, p. 54.) The authority given by M. Renan is Dion Cass., LXXI., xxxiv.; where, however, there is nothing of the kind stated. Capitolinus says (Anton. Phil., cap. xi.): ‘Jus autem magis vetus restituit quam novum fecit.’
90Renan, p. 30; Capitolinus,Anton. Phil., xii.; Dion Cass.,Epit., LXXI., xxix., 3.
90Renan, p. 30; Capitolinus,Anton. Phil., xii.; Dion Cass.,Epit., LXXI., xxix., 3.
91Antoninus,Comm., VI., 46; X., 8.
91Antoninus,Comm., VI., 46; X., 8.
92The expressions used by M. Ernest Renan when treating of this subject are somewhat conflicting. In reference to the penal enactments against Christianity under Marcus Aurelius, he first states that, however objectionable they may have been, ‘en tout cas dans l’application la mansuétude du bon empereur fut à l’abri de tout reproche’ (Marc-Aurèle, p. 58.) Further on, however we are told that when the martyrs of Lyons appealed to Rome, ‘la réponse impériale arriva en fin. Elle était dure et cruelle.’ (p. 329.) And subsequently M. Renan makes the Emperor personally responsible for the atrocities practised on that occasion by observing, ‘Si Marc-Aurèle, au lieu d’employer les lions et la chaise rougie,’ &c. (p. 345.) But perhaps such inconsistencies are to be expected in a writer who has elevated the necessity of perpetual self-contradiction into a principle.
92The expressions used by M. Ernest Renan when treating of this subject are somewhat conflicting. In reference to the penal enactments against Christianity under Marcus Aurelius, he first states that, however objectionable they may have been, ‘en tout cas dans l’application la mansuétude du bon empereur fut à l’abri de tout reproche’ (Marc-Aurèle, p. 58.) Further on, however we are told that when the martyrs of Lyons appealed to Rome, ‘la réponse impériale arriva en fin. Elle était dure et cruelle.’ (p. 329.) And subsequently M. Renan makes the Emperor personally responsible for the atrocities practised on that occasion by observing, ‘Si Marc-Aurèle, au lieu d’employer les lions et la chaise rougie,’ &c. (p. 345.) But perhaps such inconsistencies are to be expected in a writer who has elevated the necessity of perpetual self-contradiction into a principle.
93Epictêtus,Diss., III., xxiv.
93Epictêtus,Diss., III., xxiv.
94Seneca,De Irâ, I., xiv., 2;De Clement., I., vi., 2.
94Seneca,De Irâ, I., xiv., 2;De Clement., I., vi., 2.
95Diog., VII., 91. Ziegler (Gesch. d. Ethik, Bonn, 1882, I., 174) holds, in opposition to Zeller, that originally every Stoic, as such, was assumed to be a perfect sage, and that the question was only whether the ideal had ever been realised outside the school. This, however, goes against the evidence of Plutarch, who tells as (De Stoic. Repug., xxxi., 5) that Chrysippus neither professed to be good himself nor supposed that any of his friends or teachers or disciples was good.
95Diog., VII., 91. Ziegler (Gesch. d. Ethik, Bonn, 1882, I., 174) holds, in opposition to Zeller, that originally every Stoic, as such, was assumed to be a perfect sage, and that the question was only whether the ideal had ever been realised outside the school. This, however, goes against the evidence of Plutarch, who tells as (De Stoic. Repug., xxxi., 5) that Chrysippus neither professed to be good himself nor supposed that any of his friends or teachers or disciples was good.
96Seneca,Epp., cxvi., 4. It must be borne in mind that Panaetius was speaking at a time when the object of passion would at best be either another man’s wife or a member of thedemi-monde.
96Seneca,Epp., cxvi., 4. It must be borne in mind that Panaetius was speaking at a time when the object of passion would at best be either another man’s wife or a member of thedemi-monde.
97Comm., VII., 26; XII., 16.
97Comm., VII., 26; XII., 16.
98See especially Antoninus,Comm., IX., 1.
98See especially Antoninus,Comm., IX., 1.
99Friedländer,Römische Sittengeschichte, I., 463; Duruy,Histoire des Romains, V., 349 ff., 370; cf. Gaston Boissier,La Religion Romaine, II., 152 ff., 212 ff.
99Friedländer,Römische Sittengeschichte, I., 463; Duruy,Histoire des Romains, V., 349 ff., 370; cf. Gaston Boissier,La Religion Romaine, II., 152 ff., 212 ff.
100This idea is most distinctly expressed by Marcus Aurelius, II., 1, and VII., 13.
100This idea is most distinctly expressed by Marcus Aurelius, II., 1, and VII., 13.
101For the authorities, see Zeller, p. 176.
101For the authorities, see Zeller, p. 176.
102See especially Seneca,Epp., lxiv., and the whole treatiseDe Providentiâ.
102See especially Seneca,Epp., lxiv., and the whole treatiseDe Providentiâ.
103See,inter alia,Comm., IV., 3; VI., 15, 37; VII., 21, 49; XI., 1; XII., 7, 21, 23, 24, 26, 31, 32.
103See,inter alia,Comm., IV., 3; VI., 15, 37; VII., 21, 49; XI., 1; XII., 7, 21, 23, 24, 26, 31, 32.
104Comm., XI., 28, xii. 14. A modern disciple of Aurelius has expressed himself to the same purpose in slightly different language:—‘Long fed on boundless hopes, O race of man,How angrily thou spurn’st all simpler fare!“Christ,” some one says, “was human as we are.No judge eyes us from heaven our sin to scan;We live no more, when we have done our span.”“Well, then, for Christ,” thou answerest, “who can care?From sin, which Heaven records not, why forbear?Live we, like brutes, our life without a plan!”So answerest thou; but why not rather say:“Hath man no second life?—Pitch this one high!Sits there no judge in Heaven, our sin to see?More strictly, then, the inward judge obey!Was Christ a man like us?—Ah! let us tryIf we then, too, can be such men as he!”’—The Better Part, by Mr. Matthew Arnold. The italics are in the original.
104Comm., XI., 28, xii. 14. A modern disciple of Aurelius has expressed himself to the same purpose in slightly different language:—
‘Long fed on boundless hopes, O race of man,How angrily thou spurn’st all simpler fare!“Christ,” some one says, “was human as we are.No judge eyes us from heaven our sin to scan;We live no more, when we have done our span.”“Well, then, for Christ,” thou answerest, “who can care?From sin, which Heaven records not, why forbear?Live we, like brutes, our life without a plan!”So answerest thou; but why not rather say:“Hath man no second life?—Pitch this one high!Sits there no judge in Heaven, our sin to see?More strictly, then, the inward judge obey!Was Christ a man like us?—Ah! let us tryIf we then, too, can be such men as he!”’—The Better Part, by Mr. Matthew Arnold. The italics are in the original.
‘Long fed on boundless hopes, O race of man,How angrily thou spurn’st all simpler fare!“Christ,” some one says, “was human as we are.No judge eyes us from heaven our sin to scan;We live no more, when we have done our span.”“Well, then, for Christ,” thou answerest, “who can care?From sin, which Heaven records not, why forbear?Live we, like brutes, our life without a plan!”So answerest thou; but why not rather say:“Hath man no second life?—Pitch this one high!Sits there no judge in Heaven, our sin to see?More strictly, then, the inward judge obey!Was Christ a man like us?—Ah! let us tryIf we then, too, can be such men as he!”’—The Better Part, by Mr. Matthew Arnold. The italics are in the original.
‘Long fed on boundless hopes, O race of man,How angrily thou spurn’st all simpler fare!“Christ,” some one says, “was human as we are.No judge eyes us from heaven our sin to scan;We live no more, when we have done our span.”“Well, then, for Christ,” thou answerest, “who can care?From sin, which Heaven records not, why forbear?Live we, like brutes, our life without a plan!”So answerest thou; but why not rather say:“Hath man no second life?—Pitch this one high!Sits there no judge in Heaven, our sin to see?More strictly, then, the inward judge obey!Was Christ a man like us?—Ah! let us tryIf we then, too, can be such men as he!”’—The Better Part, by Mr. Matthew Arnold. The italics are in the original.
‘Long fed on boundless hopes, O race of man,
How angrily thou spurn’st all simpler fare!
“Christ,” some one says, “was human as we are.
No judge eyes us from heaven our sin to scan;
We live no more, when we have done our span.”
“Well, then, for Christ,” thou answerest, “who can care?
From sin, which Heaven records not, why forbear?
Live we, like brutes, our life without a plan!”
So answerest thou; but why not rather say:
“Hath man no second life?—Pitch this one high!
Sits there no judge in Heaven, our sin to see?
More strictly, then, the inward judge obey!
Was Christ a man like us?—Ah! let us try
If we then, too, can be such men as he!”’
—The Better Part, by Mr. Matthew Arnold. The italics are in the original.
105First Principles, § 177.
105First Principles, § 177.
106See an article entitled ‘Pantheism and Cosmic Emotion,’ by Frederic Harrison, in theNineteenth Centuryfor August, 1881.
106See an article entitled ‘Pantheism and Cosmic Emotion,’ by Frederic Harrison, in theNineteenth Centuryfor August, 1881.
107From the Hymn of Cleanthes, translated by Mr. Francis Newman inThe Soul, p. 73, fifth edition.
107From the Hymn of Cleanthes, translated by Mr. Francis Newman inThe Soul, p. 73, fifth edition.
108Epicureanism, p. 1.
108Epicureanism, p. 1.
109Ph. d. Gr., III., a, p. 380.
109Ph. d. Gr., III., a, p. 380.
110Op. cit., p. 72.
110Op. cit., p. 72.
111Short Studies, III., p. 246.
111Short Studies, III., p. 246.
112Gesch. des Mater., I., p. 92.
112Gesch. des Mater., I., p. 92.
113Pollock’sSpinoza, p. 64.
113Pollock’sSpinoza, p. 64.
114Epicuro e l’Epicurismo, Florence, 1877, p. 29.
114Epicuro e l’Epicurismo, Florence, 1877, p. 29.
115Lucretii Philosophia cum fontibus comparata, Groningen, 1877, p. 137.
115Lucretii Philosophia cum fontibus comparata, Groningen, 1877, p. 137.
116Dialogues Philosophiques, p. 54, quoted by Woltjer,loc. cit.
116Dialogues Philosophiques, p. 54, quoted by Woltjer,loc. cit.
117Diog. L., X., 142.
117Diog. L., X., 142.
118Ibid., 113.
118Ibid., 113.
119Diog. L., X., 134.
119Diog. L., X., 134.
120Cicero,Acad., II., xxxiii., 106.
120Cicero,Acad., II., xxxiii., 106.
121Cicero,De Fin., II., xxx., 96;Diog., X., 22. Cicero translates the words διαλογισμῶν μνήμῃ, ‘memoria rationum inventorumque nostrorum.’ They may refer merely to the pleasure derived from intellectual conversation.
121Cicero,De Fin., II., xxx., 96;Diog., X., 22. Cicero translates the words διαλογισμῶν μνήμῃ, ‘memoria rationum inventorumque nostrorum.’ They may refer merely to the pleasure derived from intellectual conversation.
122The authorities for the life of Epicurus are given by Zeller,op. cit., p. 363 ff.
122The authorities for the life of Epicurus are given by Zeller,op. cit., p. 363 ff.
123Diog., II., 92.
123Diog., II., 92.
124Zeller,Ph. d. Gr., II., a, 294.
124Zeller,Ph. d. Gr., II., a, 294.
125Cf. Plato,Protag., 353, C, ff., with Epicurus in the letter to Menoeceus, quoted by Diog., X., 129.
125Cf. Plato,Protag., 353, C, ff., with Epicurus in the letter to Menoeceus, quoted by Diog., X., 129.
126Morale d’Épicure, p. 20.
126Morale d’Épicure, p. 20.
127Wallace’sÉpicureanism, p. 154; Guyau,Morale d’Épicure, p. 34.
127Wallace’sÉpicureanism, p. 154; Guyau,Morale d’Épicure, p. 34.
128Cicero,Tusc. Disput., III., xviii., 41; Zeller, III., a, p. 444.
128Cicero,Tusc. Disput., III., xviii., 41; Zeller, III., a, p. 444.
129Zeller, p. 460.
129Zeller, p. 460.
130Ibid., p. 581.
130Ibid., p. 581.
131Diog., II., 72.
131Diog., II., 72.
132Diog., X., 131.
132Diog., X., 131.
133Guyau,Morale d’Épicure, p. 55.
133Guyau,Morale d’Épicure, p. 55.
134Diog., X., 118.
134Diog., X., 118.
135Lucret., IV., 1057-66.
135Lucret., IV., 1057-66.
136Diog., X., 117, 118.
136Diog., X., 117, 118.
137Cicero,De Fin., V., xxvii., 80; Diog., X., 118.
137Cicero,De Fin., V., xxvii., 80; Diog., X., 118.
138That is, if we assume what Aristotle says on the subject to be derived from common usage (Eth. Nic., III., ix., p. 1115, a, 33).
138That is, if we assume what Aristotle says on the subject to be derived from common usage (Eth. Nic., III., ix., p. 1115, a, 33).
139Cicero,Tusc. Disp., II., xii., 28.
139Cicero,Tusc. Disp., II., xii., 28.
140Cicero,De Fin., I., xv.;Tusc., V., xxviii.
140Cicero,De Fin., I., xv.;Tusc., V., xxviii.
141Diog., X., 150 ff.
141Diog., X., 150 ff.
142Wallace, p. 162; Diog., X., 150.
142Wallace, p. 162; Diog., X., 150.
143Epicureanism, pp. 162-3.
143Epicureanism, pp. 162-3.
144Cicero,De Fin., II., vii., 20;De Nat. Deor., I., xvii., 45, xxx., 85.
144Cicero,De Fin., II., vii., 20;De Nat. Deor., I., xvii., 45, xxx., 85.
145Diog., X., 150-1.
145Diog., X., 150-1.
146V., 1145-59.
146V., 1145-59.
147Cicero,De Fin., II., xvii., 57.
147Cicero,De Fin., II., xvii., 57.
148Op. cit., p. 163.
148Op. cit., p. 163.
149The lamented Prof. T. H. Green may be mentioned as another example of a high-minded thinker who was also an ardent and active politician. With regard to antiquity, see the splendid roll of public-spirited philosophers enumerated by Plutarch,Adv. Col., xxxii.
149The lamented Prof. T. H. Green may be mentioned as another example of a high-minded thinker who was also an ardent and active politician. With regard to antiquity, see the splendid roll of public-spirited philosophers enumerated by Plutarch,Adv. Col., xxxii.
150Op. cit., p. 164.
150Op. cit., p. 164.
151J. S. Mill observed, in a conversation with Mr. John Morley, reported by the latter, that ‘in his youth mere negation of religion was a firm bond of union, social and otherwise, between men who agreed in nothing else.’—Fortnightly Review, vol. XIII., p. 675.
151J. S. Mill observed, in a conversation with Mr. John Morley, reported by the latter, that ‘in his youth mere negation of religion was a firm bond of union, social and otherwise, between men who agreed in nothing else.’—Fortnightly Review, vol. XIII., p. 675.
152Cicero,De Nat. Deor., L., 18-24.
152Cicero,De Nat. Deor., L., 18-24.
153Woltjer,Lucret. Ph., p. 74.
153Woltjer,Lucret. Ph., p. 74.
154‘Das Staatsgesetz oder das dem Gesetz gleichkommende väterliche Herkommen bildet einen Gegensatz gegen ein abgeschlossenes Priesterthum und dessen natürlichen Einfluss.’ Welcker,Gr. Götterlehre, II., p. 45. ‘La religion romaine, comme toutes celles où domine l’esprit laïque, diminue le rôle du prêtre.’ Gaston Boissier,La Religion Romaine, I., p. 16.
154‘Das Staatsgesetz oder das dem Gesetz gleichkommende väterliche Herkommen bildet einen Gegensatz gegen ein abgeschlossenes Priesterthum und dessen natürlichen Einfluss.’ Welcker,Gr. Götterlehre, II., p. 45. ‘La religion romaine, comme toutes celles où domine l’esprit laïque, diminue le rôle du prêtre.’ Gaston Boissier,La Religion Romaine, I., p. 16.