[3]The reference to Stendhal here, seems to point to a passage in hisLife of Napoleon(Preface, p. xv) of which Nietzsche had made a note in another place, and which reads: "Une croyance presque instinctive chez moi c'est que tout homme puissant ment quand il parle et à plus forte raison quand il écrit."
[3]The reference to Stendhal here, seems to point to a passage in hisLife of Napoleon(Preface, p. xv) of which Nietzsche had made a note in another place, and which reads: "Une croyance presque instinctive chez moi c'est que tout homme puissant ment quand il parle et à plus forte raison quand il écrit."
(h)Against Causality.
545.
I believe in absolute space as the basis of force, and I believe the latter to be limited and formed. Time, eternal. But space and time as things in themselves do not exist. "Changes" are only appearances (or mere processes of our senses to us); if we set recurrence, however regular, between them, nothing is proved beyond the fact that it has always happened so. The feeling thatpost hocispropter hoc,is easily explained as the result of a misunderstanding, it is comprehensible. But appearances cannot be "causes"!
546.
The interpretation of a phenomenon,eitheras an actionoras the endurance of an action (that is to say, every action involves the suffering of it), amounts to this: every change, every differentiation, presupposes the existence of an agent and somebody acted upon,whois "altered."
547.
Psychological history of the conceptsubject.The body, the thing, the "whole," which is visualised by the eye, awakens the thought of distinguishing between an action and an agent; the idea that the agent is the cause of the action, after having been repeatedly refined, at length left the "subject" over.
548.
Our absurd habit of regarding a mere mnemonic sign or abbreviated formula as an independent being, and ultimately as acause; as, for instance, when we say of lightning that it flashes, even the little word "I." A sort of double-sight in seeing which makes sight acause of seeing in itself: this was the feat in the invention of the "subject" of the "ego."
549.
"Subject," "object," "attribute"—these distinctions have beenmade,and are now used like schemes to cover all apparent facts. The false fundamental observation is this, that I believe it is I who does something, who suffers something, who "has" something, who "has" a quality.
550.
In every judgment lies the whole faith in subject, attribute, or cause and effect (in the form of an assumption that every effect is the result of activity, and that all activity presupposes an agent), and even this last belief is only an isolated case of the first, so that faith remains as the most fundamental belief! there are such things as subjects, everything that happens is related attributively to a subject of some sort.
I notice something, and try to discover the reason of it: originally this was, I look for anintentionbehind it, and, above all, I look for one who has an intention, for a subject, an agent:every phenomenon is an action, formerly intentions were seen behindallphenomena, this is our oldest habit. Has the animal also this habit? As a living organism, is it not also compelled to interpret things through itself. The question why? is always a question concerning thecausa finalis,and the general "purpose" of things. We have no sign of the "sense of the efficient cause"; in this respect Hume is quite right, habit (but not only that of the individual) allows us to expect that a certain process, frequently observed, will follow upon another, but nothing more! That which gives us such an extraordinarily firm faith in causality, is not the rough habit of observing the sequence of processes, but ourinabilitytointerpreta phenomenon otherwise than as the result ofdesign.It is thebelief inliving and thinking things, as the only agents ofcausation; it is the belief in will, in design—the belief that all phenomena are actions, and that all actions presuppose an agent; it is the belief in the "subject." Is not this belief in the concepts subject and object an arrant absurdity?
Question: Is the design the cause of a phenomenon? Or is that also illusion? Is it not the phenomenon itself?
551.
A criticism of the concept "cause."—We have absolutely no experience concerningcause, viewed psychologically we derive the whole concept from the subjective conviction, thatweourselves are causes—that is to say, that the arm moves....Butthat is an error.We distinguish ourselves, the agents, from the action, and everywhere we make use of this scheme—we try to discover an agent behind every phenomenon. What have we done? We havemisunderstooda feeling of power, tension, resistance, a muscular feeling, which is already the beginning of the action, and posited it as a cause; or we have understood the will to do this or that, as a cause, because the action follows it. There is no such thing as "Cause," in those few cases in which it seemed to be given, and in which we projected it out of ourselves inorder to understand a phenomenon,it has been shown to be an illusion. Our understanding of a phenomenon consisted in our inventing a subject who was responsible for something happening, and for the manner in which it happened. In our concept "cause" we have embraced our feeling of will, our feeling of "freedom," our feeling of responsibility and our design to do an action:causa efficiensandcausa finalisare fundamentally one.
We believed that an effect was explained when we could point to a state in which it was inherent. As a matter of fact, we invent all causes according to the scheme of the effect: the latter is known to us.... On the other hand, we are not in a position to say of any particular thing how it will "act." The thing, the subject the will, the design—all inherent in the conception "cause." We try to discover things in order to explain why something has changed. Even the "atom" is one of these fanciful inventions like the "thing" and the "primitive subject."...
At last we understand that things—consequently also atoms—effect nothing:because they are non-existent;and that the concept causality is quite! useless. Out of a necessary sequence of states, the latter's causal relationship doesnotfollow (that would be equivalent to extending theiractive principlefrom 1 to 2, to 3, to 4, to 5).There is no such thing as a cause or an effect.From the standpoint of language we do not know how to rid ourselves of them. But that does not matter. If I imaginemuscleseparated from its "effects," I have denied it....
In short:a phenomenon is neither effected nor capable of effecting. Causais afaculty to effect something,superadded fancifully to what happens....
The interpretation of causality is an illusion....A "thing" is the sum of its effects, synthetically united by means of a concept, an image. As a matter of fact, science has robbed the concept causality of all meaning, and has reserved it merely as an allegorical formula, which has made it a matter of indifference whether cause or effect be put on this side or on that. It is asserted that in two complex states (centres of force) the quantities of energy remain constant.
The calculability of a phenomenondoes not lie in the fact that a rule is observed, or that a necessity is obeyed, or that we have projected a law of causality into every phenomenon: it lies in therecurrence of "identical cases."
There is no such thing as asense of causality,as Kant would have us believe. We are aghast,we feel insecure, we will have something familiar, which can be relied upon.... As soon as we are shown the existence of something old in a new thing, we are pacified. The so-called instinct of causality is nothing more than thefear of the unfamiliar, and the attempt at finding something in it which is alreadyknown.—It is not a search for causes, but for the familiar.
552.
To combat determinism and teleology.—From the fact that something happens regularly, and that its occurrence may be reckoned upon, it does not follow that it happensnecessarily.If a quantity of force determines and conducts itself in a certain way in every particular case, it does not prove that it has "no free will." "Mechanical necessity" is not an established fact: it waswewho first read into the nature of all phenomena. We interpreted the possibility offormularisingphenomena as a result of the dominion of necessary law over all existence. But it does not follow, because I do a determined thing, that I am bound to do it.Compulsioncannot be demonstrated in things: all that the rule proves is this, that one and the same phenomenon is not another phenomenon. Owing to the very fact that we fancied the existence of subjects "agents" in things, the notion arose that all phenomena are theconsequenceof acompulsory forceexercised over the subject—exercised by whom? once more by an "agent." The concept "Cause and Effect" is a dangerous one,so long as people believe in something thatcauses,and a something that iscaused.
(a)Necessity is not an established fact, but an interpretation.
***
(b)When it is understood that the "subject" is nothing thatacts,but only a thing of fancy, there is much that follows.
Only with the subject as model we inventedthingnessand read it into the pell-mell of sensations. If we cease from believing in theactingsubject, the belief inactingthings, in reciprocal action, in cause and effect between phenomena which we call things, also falls to pieces.
In this case the world ofacting atomsalso disappears: for this world is always assumed to exist on the pre-determined grounds that subjects are necessary.
Ultimately, of course,the "thing-in-itself"also disappears: for at bottom it is the conception of a "subject-in-itself." But we have seen that the subject is an imaginary thing. The antithesis "thing-in-itself" and "appearance" is untenable; but in this way the concept "appearance" also disappears.
***
(c)If we abandon the idea of the actingsubject,we also abandon theobjectacted upon. Duration, equality to self, Being, are inherent neither in what is called subject, nor in what is called object: they are complex phenomena, and in regard to other phenomena are apparently durable—they aredistinguishable, for instance, by the different tempo with which they happen (repose—movement, fixed —loose: all antitheses which do not exist in themselves and by means of whichdifferences of degreeonly are expressed; from a certain limited point of view, though, they seem to be antitheses. There are no such things as antitheses; it is from logic that we derive our concept of contrasts—and starting out from its standpoint we spread the error over all things).
***
(d)If we abandon the ideas "subject" and "object"; then we must also abandon the idea"substance"—and therefore its various modifications too; for instance: "matter," "spirit," and other hypothetical things, "eternity and the immutability of matter," etc. We are then rid ofmateriality.
***
From a moral standpointthe world is false.But inasmuch as morality itself is a part of this world, morality also is false. The will to truth is a process ofestablishing things, it is a process ofmakingthings true and lasting, a total elimination of thatfalsecharacter, a transvaluation of it intobeing.Thus, "truth" is not something which is present and which has to be found and discovered; it is somethingwhich has to be createdand whichgivesits nameto a process,or, better still, to the Will to overpower, which in itself has no purpose: to introduce truth is aprocessus in infinitum,anactive determining—it is not a process ofbecoming conscious of something, which in itself is fixed and determined. It is merely a word for "The Will to Power."
Life is based on the hypothesis of a belief in stable and regularly recurring things, the mightier it is, the more vast must be the world of knowledge and the world called being. Logicising, rationalising, and systematising are of assistance as means of existence.
Man projects his instinct of truth, his "aim," to a certain extent beyond himself, in the form of a metaphysical world of Being, a "thing-in-itself," a world already to hand. His requirements as a creator make himinventthe world in which he works in advance; he anticipates it: this anticipation (this faith in truth) is his mainstay.
***
All phenomena, movement, Becoming, regarded as the establishment of relations of degree and of force, as a contest....
***
As soon as wefancythat some one is responsible for the fact that we are thus and thus, etc. (God, Nature), and that we ascribe our existence, our happiness, our misery, ourdestiny,to that some one, we corrupt theinnocence of Becomingfor ourselves. We then have some one who wishes to attain to something by means of us and with us.
***
The "welfare of the individual" is just as fanciful as the "welfare of the species": the first isnotsacrificed to the last; seen from afar, the speciesis just as fluid as the individual. "Thepreservationof the species" is only a result of thegrowthof the species—that is to say,of the overcoming of the specieson the road to a stronger kind.
***
Theses:—The apparent conformity of means to end ("the conformity of means to end which far surpasses the art of man) is merely the result of that "Will to Power" which manifests itself in all phenomena:—To become strongerinvolves a process of ordering, which may well be mistaken for an attempted conformity of means to end:—Theendswhich are apparent are not intended but, as soon as a superior power prevails over an inferior power, and the latter proceeds to work as a function of the former, an order ofrankis established, an organisation which must give rise to the idea that there is an arrangement of means and ends.
Against apparent "necessity":—
This is only an expression for the fact that a certain power is not also something else.
Against the apparent conformity of means to ends":—
The latter is only anexpressionfor the order among the spheres of power and their interplay.
(i)The Thing-in-Itself and Appearance.
553.
The foul blemish on Kant's criticism has at last become visible even to the coarsest eyes: Kanthad no right to his distinction "appearance" and "thing-in-itself,"—in his own writings he had deprived himself of the right of differentiating any longer in this old and hackneyed manner, seeing that he had condemned the practice of drawing any conclusions concerning the cause of an appearance from the appearance itself, as unallowable in accordance with his conception of the idea of causality and itspurely intraphenomenalvalidity, and this conception, on the other hand, already anticipates thatdifferentiation,as if the "thing in itself" were not only inferred but actuallygiven.
554.
It is obvious that neither things-in-themselvesnorappearances can be related to each other in the form of cause and effect: and from this it follows that the concept "cause and effect" isnot applicablein a philosophy which believes in things-in-themselves and in appearances. Kant's mistake—... As a matter of fact, from a psychological standpoint, the concept "cause and effect" is derived from an attitude of mind which believes it sees the action of will upon will everywhere, which believes only in living things, and at bottom only in souls (not in things). Within the mechanical view of the world (which is logic and its application to space and time) that concept is reduced to the mathematical formula with which—and this is a fact which cannot be sufficiently emphasised—nothing is ever understood, but ratherdefined—deformed.
555.
The greatest of all fables is the one relating to knowledge. People would like to know how things-in-themselves are constituted: but behold, there are no things-in-themselves! But even supposing therewerean "in-itself," an unconditional thing, it could on that very accountnot be known! Something unconditioned cannot be known: otherwise it would not be unconditioned! Knowing, however, is always a process of "coming into relation with something"; the knowledge-seeker, on this principle, wants the thing, which he would know, to be nothing to him, and to be nothing to anybody at all: and from this there results a contradiction,—in the first place, between thiswillto know, and this desire that the thing to be knownshouldbe nothing to him (wherefore know at all then?); and secondly, because something which is nothing to anybody, does not evenexist,and therefore cannot be known. Knowing means: "to place one's self in relation with something," to feel one's self conditioned by something and one's self conditioning it under all circumstances, then, it is a process ofmaking stable or fixed,ofdefining,ofmaking conditions conscious(not a process ofsoundingthings, creatures, or objects in-themselves).
556.
A "thing-in-itself" is just as absurd as a "sense-in-itself," a "meaning-in-itself." There is no suchthing as a "fact-in-itself,"for a meaning must always be given to it before it can become a fact.
The answer to the question, "What is that?" is a process offixing a meaningfrom a different standpoint. The "essence" the "essential factor," is something which is only seen as a whole in perspective, and which presupposes a basis which is multifarious. Fundamentally the question is "What is that for me?" (for us, for everything that lives, etc. etc.).
A thing would be defined when all creatures had asked and answered this question, "What is that?" concerning it. Supposing that one single creature, with its own relations and standpoint in regard to all things, were lacking, that thing would still remain undefined.
In short: the essence of a thing is really only anopinionconcerning that "thing." Or, better still; "it is worth" is actually what is meant by"it is"or by "that is."
One may not ask: "Whointerprets, then?" for the act of interpretingitselfas a form of the Will to Power, manifests itself (not as "Being," but as aprocess,asBecoming) as a passion.
The origin of "things" is wholly the work of the idealising, thinking, willing, and feeling subject. The concept thing as well as all its attributes.—Even "the subject" is a creation of this order, a "thing" like all others: a simplification, aiming at a definition of thepowerthat fixes, invents, and thinks, as such, as distinct from all isolated fixing, inventing, and thinking. Thus a capacity defined or distinct from all other individual capacities; atbottom action conceived collectively in regard to all the action which has yet to come (action and the probability of similar action).
557.
The qualities of a thing are its effects upon other "things."
If one imagines other "things" to be non-existent, a thing has no qualities.
That is to say;there is nothing without other things.
That is to say; there is no "thing-in-itself."
558.
The thing-in-itself is nonsense. If I think all the "relations," all the "qualities" all the "activities" of a thing, away, the thing itself doesnotremain: for "thingness" was onlyinvented fancifullyby us to meet certain logical needs—that is to say, for the purposes of definition and comprehension (in order to correlate that multitude of relations, qualities, and activities).
559.
"Things which have a naturein themselves"—a dogmatic idea, which must be absolutely abandoned.
560.
That things should have anature in themselves,quite apart from interpretation and subjectivity,is a perfectly idle hypothesis: it would presupposethatinterpretationand theact of being subjectiveare not essential, that a thing divorced from all its relations can still be a thing.
Or, the other way round: the apparentobjectivecharacter of things; might it not be merely the result of adifference of degreewithin the subject perceiving?—could not that which changes slowly strike us as being objective, lasting, Being, "in-itself"?—could not the objective view be only a false way of conceiving things and a contrastwithinthe perceiving subject?
561.
If all unity were only unity as organisation. But the "thing" in which we believe wasinventedonly as a substratum to the various attributes. If the thing "acts," it means: we regardall the otherqualities which are to hand, and which are momentarily latent, as the cause accounting for the fact that one individual quality steps forward—that is to say,we take the sum of its qualities—x—as the cause of the qualityx; which is obviouslyquiteabsurd and imbecile!
All unity isonly soin the form oforganisationandcollective action:in the same way as a human community is a unity—that is to say,the reverse ofatomicanarchy; thus it is a body politic, whichstands forone, yetisnot one.
562.
"At some time in the development of thought, a point must have been reached when man became conscious of the fact that what he calledthequalities of a thingwere merely the sensations of the feeling subject: and thus the qualities ceased from belonging to the thing." The "thing-in-itself" remained over. 'The distinction between the thing-in-itself and the thing-for-us, is based upon that older and artless observation which would fain grant energy to things: but analysis revealed that even force was only ascribed to them by our fancy, as was also—substance. "The thing affects a subject?" Thus the root of the idea of substance is in language, not in things outside ourselves! The thing-in-itself is not a problem at all!
Being will have to be conceived as a sensation which is no longer based upon anything quite devoid of sensation.
In movement no newmeaningis given to feeling. That which is, cannot be the substance of movement: it is therefore a form of Being.
N.B.—The explanation of life may be sought, in the first place, through mental images of phenomena whichprecedeit (purposes);Secondly, through mental images of phenomena which follow behind it (the mathematico-physical explanation).
N.B.—The explanation of life may be sought, in the first place, through mental images of phenomena whichprecedeit (purposes);
Secondly, through mental images of phenomena which follow behind it (the mathematico-physical explanation).
The two should not be confounded. Thus: the physical explanation, which is the symbolisation of the world by means of feeling and thought, cannot in itself make feeling and thinking originate again and show its derivation: physics must rather construct the world of feeling, consistentlywithout feeling or purposeright up to the highest man. And teleology is only ahistory of purposes,and is never physical.
563.
Our method of acquiring "knowledge" is limited to a process of establishingquantities,but we can by no means help feeling the difference of quantity as differences ofquality.Quality is merely arelativetruth forus; it is not a "thing-in-itself."
Our senses have a certain definite quantum as a mean, within the limits of which they perform their functions—that is to say, we become conscious of bigness and smallness in accordance with the conditions of our existence. If we sharpened or blunted our senses tenfold, we should perish—that is to say, we feel evenproportionsasqualitiesin regard to our possibilities of existence.
564.
But could not allquantitiesbe merely tokens ofqualities? Another consciousness and scale of desires must correspond to greater power in fact, another point of view; growth in itself is the expression of a desireto become more;the desire for a greaterquantumsprings from a certainquale,in a purely quantitative world, everything would be dead, stiff, and motionless.—The reduction of all qualities to quantities is nonsense: it is discovered that they can only stand together, an analogy—
565.
Qualities are our insurmountable barriers; we cannot possibly help feeling meredifferences of quantityas something fundamentally different from quantity—that is to say, asqualities,which wecan no longer reduce to terms of quantity. But everything in regard to which the word "knowledge" has any sense at all, belongs to the realm of reckoning, weighing, and measuring, to quantity whereas, conversely, all our valuations (that is to say, our sensations) belong precisely to the realm of qualities,i.e.to those truths which belong to us alone and to our point of view, and which absolutely cannot be "known." It is obvious that every one of us, different creatures, must feel different qualities, and must therefore live in a different world from the rest. Qualities are an idiosyncrasy proper to human nature; the demand that these our human interpretations and values, should be general and perhaps real values, belongs to the hereditary madnesses of human pride.
566.
The "real world," in whatever form it has been conceived hitherto—was always the world of appearanceover again.
567.
The world of appearance,i.e.a world regarded in the light of values; ordered, selected according to values—that is to say, in this case, according to the standpoint of utility in regard to the preservation and the increase of power of a certain species of animals.
It isthe point of view,then, which accounts for the character of "appearance." As if a world could remain over, when the point of view is cancelled! By such meansrelativitywould also be cancelled!
Every centre of energy has itspoint of viewof the whole of theremainderof the world—that is to say, its perfectly definitevaluation,its mode of action, its mode of resistance. The "world of appearance" is thus reduced to a specific kind of action on the world proceeding from a centre.
But there is no other kind of action: and the "world" is only a word for the collective play of these actions.Realityconsists precisely in this particular action and reaction of every isolated factor against the whole.
There no longer remains a shadow of arightto speak here of "appearance." ...
Thespecific way of reactingis the only way of reacting; we do not know how many kinds and what sort of kinds there are.
But there is no "other," no "real," no essential being,—for thus a worldwithoutaction and reaction would be expressed....
The antithesis: world of appearance and real world, is thus reduced to the antitheses "world" and "nonentity."
568.
A criticism of the concept "real and apparentworld."—Of these two the first is a mere fiction, formed out of a host of imaginary things.
Appearance itself belongs to reality: it is a form of its being;i.e.in a world where there is no such thing as being, a certain calculable world ofidenticalcases must first be created throughappearance;atempoin which observation and comparison is possible, etc.
"Appearance" is an adjusted and simplified world, in which ourpracticalinstincts have worked: for us it is perfectly true: for welivein it, we can live in it:this is the proofof its truth as far as we are concerned....
The world, apart from the fact that we have to live in it—the world, which we havenotadjusted to our being, our logic, and our psychological prejudices—doesnotexist as a world "in-itself"; it is essentially a world of relations: under certain circumstances it has adifferent aspectfrom every different point at which it is seen: it presses against every point, and every point resists it—and these collective relations are in every caseincongruent.
Themeasure of powerdetermines whatbeingpossesses the other measure of power: under what form, force, or constraint, it acts or resists.
Our particular case is interesting enough: we have created a conception in order to be able to live in a world, in order to perceive just enough to enable us toendurelife in that world....
569.
The nature of our psychological vision is determined by the fact—
(1) Thatcommunicationis necessary, and that for communication to be possible something must be stable, simplified, and capable of being stated precisely (above all, in the so-calledidenticalcase). In order that it may be communicable, it must be felt as somethingadjusted,as "recognisable." The material of the senses, arranged by the understanding,reduced to coarse leading features, made similar to other things, and classified with its like. Thus: the indefiniteness and the chaos of sense-impressions are, as it were,made logical.
(2) Thephenomenalworld is the adjusted world whichwe believe to be real,Its "reality" lies in the constant return of similar, familiar, and related things, in theirrationalised character,and in the belief that we are here able to reckon and determine.
(3) The opposite of this phenomenal world is not "the real world," but the amorphous and unadjustable world consisting of the chaos of sensations—that is to say,another kindof phenomenal; world, a world which to us is "unknowable."
(4) The question how things-in-themselves are constituted, quite apart from our sense-receptivity and from the activity of our understanding, must be answered by the further question: how were we able to knowthat things existed?"Thingness" is one of our own inventions. The question is whether there are not a good many more ways of creating such a world of appearance—and whether this creating, rationalising, adjusting, and falsifying be not the best-guaranteedrealityitself: in short, whether that which "fixes the meaning of things" is not the only reality: and whether the "effect of environment upon us" be not merely the result of such will-exercising subjects.... The other "creatures" act upon us; ouradjustedworld of appearance is an arrangement and anoverpoweringof its activities: a sort ofdefensivemeasure.The subject alone is demonstrable; thehypothesismight be advancedthat subjects are all that exist,—that"object" is only a form of action of subject upon subject ... amodus of the subject.
(k)The Metaphysical Need.
570.
If one resembles all the philosophers that have gone before, one can have no eyes for what has existed and what will exist—one sees only whatis.But as there is no such thing as Being; all that the philosophers had to deal with was a host offancies,this was their "world."
571.
To assert theexistenceas a whole of things concerning which we know nothing, simply because there is an advantage in not being able to know anything of them, was a piece of artlessness on Kant's part, and the result of the recoil-stroke of certain needs—especially in the realm of morals and metaphysics.
572.
An artist cannot endure reality; he turns away or back from it: his earnest opinion is that the worth of a thing consists in that nebulous residue of it which one derives from colour, form, sound, and thought; he believes that the more subtle, attenuated, and volatile, a thing or a man becomes,the more valuable he becomes: the less real,the greater the worth. This is Platonism: but Plato was guilty of yet further audacity in the matter ofturning tables—he measured the degree of reality according to the degree of value, and said: The more there is of "idea" the more there is of Being. He twisted the concept "reality" round and said: "What ye regard as real is an error, and the nearer we get to the 'idea' the nearer we are to 'truth.'"—Is this understood? It was thegreatest of all rechristenings:and because Christianity adopted it, we are blind to its astounding features. At bottom, Plato, like the artist he was,placed appearance beforeBeing! and therefore lies and fiction before truth! unreality before actuality!—He was, however, so convinced of the value of appearance, that he granted it the attributes of "Being," "causality," "goodness," and "truth," and, in short, all those things which are associated with value.
The concept value itself regarded as a cause: first standpoint.
The ideal granted all attributes, conferring honour: second standpoint.
573.
The idea of the "true world" or of "God" as absolutely spiritual, intellectual, and good, is anemergency measureto the extent to which theantagonisticinstincts are all-powerful....
Moderation and existing humanity is reflected exactly in the humanisation of the gods. The Greeks of the strongest period, who entertained no fear whatever of themselves, but on the contrary were pleased with themselves, brought down their gods to all their emotions.
The spiritualisation of the idea of God is thus very far from being a sign ofprogress: one is heartily conscious of this when one reads Goethe—in his works the vaporisation of God into virtue and spirit is felt as being upon a lower plane.
574.
The nonsense of all metaphysics shown to reside in the derivation of the conditioned out of the unconditioned.
It belongs to the nature of thinking that it adds the unconditioned to the conditioned, that it invents it—just as it thought of and invented the "ego" to cover the multifariousness of its processes i it measures the world according to a host of self-devised measurements—according to its fundamental fictions "the unconditioned," "end and means," "things," "substances," and according to logical laws, figures, and forms.
There would be nothing which could be called knowledge, if thought did not first sore-createthe world into "things" which are in its own image. It is onlythroughthought that there isuntruth.
Theoriginof thought, like that offeelings,cannot be traced: but that isnoproof of its primordiality or absoluteness! It simply shows that we cannot getbehind it,because we have nothing else save thought and feeling.
575.
To know is topoint to past experience:in its nature it is aregressus in infinitum.That whichhalts (in the face of a so-calledcausa primaor the unconditioned, etc.) islaziness,weariness.
576.
Concerning the psychology of metaphysics—the influence of fear. That which has been most feared, the cause of thegreatest suffering(lust of power, voluptuousness, etc.), has been treated with the greatest amount of hostility by men, and eliminated from the "real" world. Thus thepassionshave been step by stepstruck out,God posited as the opposite of evil—that is to say, reality is conceived to be thenegation of the passions and the emotions(i.e.nonentity).
Irrationality,impulsive action, accidental action, is, moreover, hated by them (as the cause of incalculable suffering).Consequentlythey denied this element in the absolute, and interpreted it as absolute "rationality" and "conformity of means to ends."
Changeandperishabilitywere also feared; and by this fear an oppressed soul is revealed, full of distrust and painful experiences (the case withSpinoza: a man differently constituted would have regarded this change as a charm).
A nature overflowing andplayingwith energy, would call precisely thepassions, irrationalityandchange, goodin a eudemonistic sense, together with their consequences: danger, contrast, ruin, etc.
577.
Against the value of that which always remains the same (remember Spinoza's artlessness andDescartes' likewise), the value of the shortest and of the most perishable, the seductive flash of gold on the belly of the serpentvita——
578.
Moral values in epistemology itself:—
The faith in reason—why not mistrust?The "real world" is the good world—why?Appearance, change, contradiction, struggle, regarded as immoral: the desire for a world whichknows nothingof these things.The transcendental world discovered,so thata place may be kept for "moral freedom" (as in Kant).Dialectics as the road to virtue (in Plato and Socrates: probably because sophistry was held to be the road to immorality).Time and space are ideal: consequently there is unity in the essence of things; consequently no sin, no evil, no imperfection, ajustificationof God.Epicurusdeniedthe possibility of knowledge, in order to keep the moral (particularly the hedonistic) values as the highest.Augustine does the same, and later Pascal ("corrupted reason"), in favour of Christian values.Descartes' contempt for everything variable; likewise Spinoza's.
The faith in reason—why not mistrust?
The "real world" is the good world—why?
Appearance, change, contradiction, struggle, regarded as immoral: the desire for a world whichknows nothingof these things.
The transcendental world discovered,so thata place may be kept for "moral freedom" (as in Kant).
Dialectics as the road to virtue (in Plato and Socrates: probably because sophistry was held to be the road to immorality).
Time and space are ideal: consequently there is unity in the essence of things; consequently no sin, no evil, no imperfection, ajustificationof God.
Epicurusdeniedthe possibility of knowledge, in order to keep the moral (particularly the hedonistic) values as the highest.
Augustine does the same, and later Pascal ("corrupted reason"), in favour of Christian values.
Descartes' contempt for everything variable; likewise Spinoza's.
579.
Concerning the psychology of metaphysics.—This world is only apparent:thereforethere must be areal world;—this world is conditioned:consequentlythere must be an unconditioned world;—this world is contradictory:consequentlythere is a world free from contradiction;—this world is evolving:consequentlythere is somewhere a static world:—a host of false conclusions (blind faith in reason: if A exists, then its opposite B must alsoexist). Paininspires these conclusions: at bottom they arewithesthat such a world might exist; the hatred of a world which leads to suffering is likewise revealed by the fact that another andbetterworld is imagined: theresentmentof the metaphysician against reality is creative here.
The secondseries of questions:whereforesuffer? ... and from this a conclusion is derived concerning the relation of the real world to our apparent, changing, suffering, and contradictory world: (1) Suffering as the consequence of error: how is error possible? (2) Suffering as the consequence of guilt: how is guilt possible? (A host of experiences drawn from the sphere of nature or society, universalised and made absolute.) But if the conditioned world be causally determined by the unconditioned, then thefreedom to err, to be sinful,must also be derived from the same quarter: and once more the question arises,to what purpose?... The world of appearance, of Becoming, of contradiction, of suffering, is thereforewilled; to what purpose?
The error of these conclusions; two contradictory concepts are formed—because one of them corresponds to a reality, the other "must" also correspond to a reality. "Whence" would one otherwisederive its contradictory concept?Reasonis thus a source of revelation concerning the absolute.
But theoriginof the above contradictionsneed not necessarilybe a supernatural source of reason: it is sufficient to oppose the real genesisof the concepts, this springs from practical spheres, from utilitarian spheres, hence thestrong faithit commands(one is threatened with ruinif one's conclusions are not in conformity with this reason; but this fact is no "proof" of what the latter asserts).
The preoccupation of metaphysicians with pain,is quite artless. "Eternal blessedness": psychological nonsense. Brave and creative men never make pleasure and pain ultimate questions—they are incidental conditions: both of them must be desired when onewill attain tosomething. It is a sign of fatigue and illness in these metaphysicians and religious men, that they should press questions of pleasure and pain into the foreground. Evenmoralityin their eyes derives its great importanceonlyfrom the fact that it is regarded as an essential condition for abolishing pain.
The same holds good of the preoccupation with appearance and errorthe cause of pain. A superstition that happiness and truth are related (confusion: happiness in "certainty," in "faith").
580.
To what extent are the variousepistemological positions(materialism, sensualism, idealism) consequences of valuations? The source of the highestfeelings of pleasure ("feelings of value") may also judge concerning the problem ofreality!
The measure ofpositive knowledgeis quite a matter of indifference and beside the point; as witness the development of Indici.
The Buddhisticnegationof reality in general (appearance pain) is perfectly consistent: undemonstrability, inaccessibility, lack of categories, not only for an "absolute world," but a recognition of theerroneous proceduresby means of which the whole concept has been reached. "Absolute reality," "Being in itself," a contradiction. In a world ofBecoming,reality is merely asimplificationfor the purpose of practical ends, or adeceptionresulting from the coarseness of certain organs, or a variation in the tempo of Becoming.
The logical denial of the world and Nihilism is a consequence of the fact that we must oppose nonentity with Being, and that Becoming is denied. ("Something" becomes.)
581.
BeingandBecoming.—"Reason" developed upon a sensualistic basis upon theprejudices of the senses—that is to say, with the belief in the truth of the judgment of the senses.
"Being," as the generalisation of the concept "Life" (breath), "to be animate," "to will," "to act upon," "become."
The opposite is: "to be inanimate," "notto become," "notto will."Thus: "Being" isnotopposed to "not-Being," to "appearance," nor isit opposed to death (for only that can be dead which can also live).
The "soul," the "ego," posited asprimeval facts;and introduced whereverthere is Becoming.
582.
Being—we have no other idea of it than that which we derive from "living."—How then can everything "be" dead?
583.
A.
I see with astonishment that science resigns itself to-day to the fate of being reduced to the world of appearance: we certainly have no organ of knowledge for the real world—be it what it may.
At this point we may well ask: With what organ of knowledge is this contradiction established?...
The fact that a world which is accessible to our organs is also understood to be dependent upon these organs, and the fact that we should understand a world as subjectively conditioned, arenoproofs of the actualpossibilityof an objective world. Who urges us to believe that subjectivityisreal or essential?
The absolute is even an absurd concept: an "absolute mode of existence" is nonsense, the concept "being," "thing," is alwaysrelativeto us.
The trouble is that, owing to the old antithesis "apparent" and "real," the correlative valuations "of little value" and "absolutely valuable" have been spread abroad.
The world of appearance does not strike us as a "valuable" world; appearance is on a lower plane than the highest value. Only a "real" world can be absolutely "valuable"....
Prejudice of prejudices!It is perfectly possible in itself that the real nature of things would be so unfriendly, so opposed to the first conditions of life, that appearance is necessary in order to make life possible.... This is certainly the case in a large number of situations—for instance, marriage.
Our empirical world would thus be conditioned, even in its limits to knowledge, by the instinct of self-preservation, we regard that as good, valuable, and true, which favours the preservation of the species....
(a)We have no categories which allow us to distinguish between a real and an apparent world. (At the most, there could exist a world of appearance, but notourworld of appearance.)
(b)Taking therealworld for granted, it might still be theless valuableto us; for the quantum of illusion might be of the highest order, owing to its value to us as a preservative measure. (Unlessappearancein itself were sufficient to condemn anything?)
(c)That there exists a correlation between thedegrees of valueand thedegrees of reality(so that the highest values also possessed the greatestdegree of reality), is a metaphysical postulate which starts out with the hypothesis that weknowthe order of rank among values; and that this order is amoralone. It is only on this hypothesis thattruthis necessary as a definition of all that is of a superior value.
B.
It is of cardinal importance that thereal worldshould be suppressed. It is the most formidable inspirer of doubts, and depredator of values, concerning theworld which we are: it was our most dangerousattemptheretofore on the life of Life.
Waragainst all the hypotheses upon which a real world has been imagined. The notion thatmoral valuesare thehighestvalues, belongs to this hypothesis.
The superiority of the moral valuation would be refuted, if it could be shown to be the result of animmoralvaluation—a specific case of real immorality: it would thus reduce itself to anappearance,and as anappearanceit would cease from having any right to condemn appearance.
C.
Then the "Will to Truth" would have to be examined psychologically: it is not a moral power, but a form of the Will to Power. This would have to be proved by the fact that it avails itself of everyimmoralmeans there is; above all, of the metaphysicians.
At the present moment we are face to face with the necessity of testing the assumption that moral values are the highest values,Method in researchis attained only when allmoral prejudiceshave been overcome: it represents a conquest over morality....
584.
The aberrations of philosophy are the outcome of the fact that, instead of recognising in logic and the categories of reason merely a means to the adjustment of the world for utilitarian ends (that is to say, especially, a usefulfalsification), they were taken to be the criterion of truth—particularly ofreality.The "criterion of truth" was, as a matter of fact, merely thebiological utility of a systematic falsification of this sort, on principle:and, since a species of animals knows nothing more important than its own preservation, it was indeed allowable here to speak of "truth." Where the artlessness came in, however, was in taking this anthropocentric idiosyncrasy as themeasure of things,as the canon for recognising the "real" and the "unreal": in short, in making a relative thing absolute. And behold, all at once, the world fell into the two halves, "real" and "apparent": and precisely that world which man's reason had arranged for him to live and to settle in, was discredited. Instead of using the forms as mere instruments for making the world manageable and calculable, the mad fancy of philosophers intervened, and saw that in these categories the concept of that world is given whichdoes not correspond to the concept of the world in which man lives.... The means were misunderstood as measures of value, and even used as a condemnation of their original purpose....
The purpose was, to deceive one's self in a useful way: the means thereto was the invention of forms and signs, with the help of which the confusing multifariousness of life could be reduced to a useful and wieldy scheme.
But woe! amoral categorywas now brought into the game: no creature would deceive itself, no creature may deceive itself—consequently there is only a will to truth. What is "truth"?
The principle of contradiction provided the scheme: the real world to which the way is being sought cannot be in contradiction with itself, cannot change, cannot evolve, has no beginning and no end.
That is the greatest error which has ever been committed, the really fatal error of the world: it was believed that in the forms of reason a criterion of reality had been found—whereas their only purpose was to master reality, bymisunderstandingit intelligently....
And behold, the world became false precisely owing to the qualitieswhich constitute its reality,namely, change, evolution, multifariousness, contrast, contradiction, war. And thenceforward the whole fatality was there.
1. How does one get rid of the false and merely apparent world? (it was the real and only one).
2. How does one become one's self as remoteas possible from the world of appearance? (the concept of the perfect being as a contrast to the real being; or, more correctly still, asthe contradiction of life....).
The whole direction of values was towards theslander of life; people deliberately confounded ideal dogmatism with knowledge in general: so that the opposing parties also began to rejectsciencewith horror.
Thus the road to science wasdoublybarred: first, by the belief in the real world; and secondly, by the opponents of this belief. Natural science and psychology were (1) condemned in their objects, (2) deprived of their artlessness....
Everything is so absolutely bound and related to everything else in the real world, that to condemn, or tothink awayanything, means to condemn and think away the whole. The words "this should not be," "this ought not to be," are a farce.... If one imagines the consequences, one would ruin the very source of Life by suppressing everything which is in any sense whateverdangerous or destructive.Physiology proves thismuch better!
We see how morality(a) poisonsthe whole concept of the world,(b)cuts off the way toscience, (c)dissipates and undermines all real instincts (by teaching that their root isimmoral).
We thus perceive a terrible tool of decadence at work, which succeeds in remaining immune, thanks to the holy names and holy attitudes it assumes.
585.
The awful recovery of ourconsciousness:not of the individual, but of the human species. Let us reflect; let us think backwards; let us follow the narrow and broad highway.
A.
Man seeks "the truth": a world that does not contradict itself, that does not deceive, that does not change, arealworld—a world in which there is no suffering: contradiction, deception, variability—-the causes of suffering! He does not doubt that there is such a thing as a world as it ought to be; he would fain find a road to it. (Indian criticism: even the ego is apparent andnotreal.)
Whence does man derive the concept ofreality? —Why does he make variability, deception, contradiction, the origin ofsuffering;why not rather of his happiness? ...
The contempt and hatred of all that perishes, changes, and varies: whence comes this valuation of stability? Obviously, the will to truth ismerelythe longing for astable world.
The senses deceive; reason corrects the errors:therefore,it was concluded, reason is the road to a static state; the mostspiritualideas must be nearest to the "real world."—It is from the senses that the greatest number of misfortunes come they are cheats, deluders, and destroyers.
Happiness can be promised only by Being: change and happiness exclude each other. Theloftiest desire is thus to be one with Being. That is the formula for the way to happiness.
In summa:The world as itoughtto be exists; this world in which we live is an error—this our world shouldnotexist.
The belief in Beingshows itself only as a result: the real primummobileis the disbelief in Becoming, the mistrust of Becoming, the scorn of all Becoming....
What kind of a man reflects in this way? An unfruitful,sufferingkind, a world-weary kind. If we try and fancy what the opposite kind of man would be like, we have a picture of a creature who would not require the belief in Being; he would rather despise it as dead, tedious, and indifferent....
The belief that the world which ought to be, is, really exists, is a belief proper to the unfruitful,who do not wish to create a world as it should be.They take it for granted, they seek for means and ways of attaining to it. "The will to truth"—is the impotence of the will to create.
The fiction of a world which corresponds to our desires; psychological artifices and interpretations calculated to associate all that we honour and regard as pleasant, with thisreal world.
"The will to truth" at this stage is essentiallythe art of interpretation:to which also belongs that interpretation which still possesses strength.
The same species of men, grown one degree poorer,no longer possessed of the powerto interpret and to create fictions, produces the Nihilists.A Nihilist is the man who says of the world as it is, that it oughtnotto exist, and of the world as it ought to be, that it does not exist. According to this, existence (action, suffering, willing, and feeling) has no sense: the pathos of the "in vain" is the Nihilist's pathos—and as pathos it is moreover aninconsistencyon the part of the Nihilist.
He who is not able to introduce his will into things, the man without either will or energy, at least invests them with some meaning,i.e.he believes that a will is already in them.
The degree of a man'swill-powermay be measured from the extent to which he can dispense with the meaning in things, from the extent to which he is able to endure a world without meaning:because he himself arranges a small portion of it.
Thephilosophical objective view of thingsmay thus be a sign of poverty both of will and of energy. For energy organises what is closest and next; the "scientists," whose only desire is toascertainwhat exists, are such as cannot arrange thingsas they ought to be.
Theartists,an intermediary species, they at least set up a symbol of what should exist,—they are productive inasmuch as they actuallyalterand transform; not like the scientists, who leave everything as it is.
The connection between philosophers and the pessimistic religions;the same species of man(they attribute the highest degree of realityto thethings which are valued highest).
The connection between philosophers and moral menand their evaluations (themoralinterpretation of the world as the sense of the world: after the collapse of the religious sense).
The overcoming of philosophersby the annihilation of the world of being: intermediary period of Nihilism; before there is sufficient strength present to transvalue values, and to make the world of becoming, and of appearance, theonlyworld to be deified and called good.
B.
Nihilism as a normal phenomenon may be a symptom of increasingstrengthor of increasingweakness:—
Partly owing to the fact that the strengthto createandto willhas grown to such an extent, that it no longer requires this collective interpretation and introduction of asense("present duties," state, etc.);
Partly owing to the fact that even the creative power necessary to invent sense, declines, and disappointment becomes the ruling condition. The inability tobelievein a sense becomes "unbelief."
What is the meaning ofsciencein regard to both possibilities?
(1) It is a sign of strength and self-control; it shows anabilityto dispense with healing, consoling worlds of illusion.
(2) It is also able to undermine, to dissect, to disappoint, and to weaken.
C.
The belief in truth,the need of holding to something which is believed to be true: psychological reduction apart from the valuations that have existed hitherto. Fear and laziness.
At the same timeunbelief:Reduction. In what way does it acquire anew value,if a real world does not exist at all (by this means the capacity of valuing, which hitherto has beenlavishedupon the world of being, becomes free once more).
586.
Therealand the"apparent" world.
A.
Theerroneous conceptswhich proceed from this concept are of three kinds:—
(a)An unknown world:—we are adventurers, we are inquisitive,—that which is known to us makes us weary (the danger of the concept lies in the fact it suggests that "this" world is known to us....);
(b) Anotherworld, where things are different:—something in us draws comparisons, and thereby our calm submission and our silence lose their value—perhaps all will be for the best, we have not hoped in vain.... The world where things are different—who knows?—where we ourselves will be different....
(c)Arealworld:—that is the most singularblow and attack which we have ever received; so many things have become encrusted in the word "true," that we involuntarily give these to the "real world"; therealworld must also be atruthfulworld, such a one as would not deceive us or make fools of us; to believe in it in this way is to be almostforcedto believe (from convention, as is the case among people worthy of confidence).
***
The concept, "theunknownworld," suggests that this world is known to us (is tedious);
The concept, "the other world," suggests that this worldmight be different,it suppresses necessity and fate (it is useless tosubmitand toadapt one's self);
The concept,the true world,suggests that this world is untruthful, deceitful, dishonest, not genuine, and not essential, andconsequentlynot a world calculated to be useful to us (it is unadvisable to become adapted to it;betterresist it).
***
Thus weescapefrom "this" world in three different ways:——
(a)With ourcuriosity—as though the interesting part was somewhere else;
(b)With oursubmission—as though it was not necessary to submit, as though this world was not an ultimate necessity;
(c)With oursympathyand respect—as though this world did not deserve them, as though it was mean and dishonest towards us....
In summa: we have become revolutionaries inthree different ways; we have madexour criticism of the "known world."
B.
The first step to reason:to understand to what extent we have beenseduced,—for it might bepreciselythe reverse:
(a)Theunknownworld could be so constituted as to give us a liking for "this" world—it may be a more stupid and meaner form of existence.
(b)The other world, very far from taking account of our desires which were never realised here, might be part of the mass of things whichthisworld makes possible for us; to learn to know this world would be a means of satisfying us,
(c)Thetrueworld: but who actually says that the apparent world must be of less value than the true world? Do not our instincts contradict this judgment? Is not man eternally occupied in creating an imaginative world, because he will have a better world than reality?In the first place,how do we know thatourworld isnotthe true world? ... for it might be that the other world is the world of "appearance" (as a matter of fact, the Greeks, for instance, actually imagined aregion of shadows, a life of appearance,besiderealexistence). And finally, what right have we to establishdegrees of reality,as it were? That is something different from an unknown world—that is already thewill to know something of the unknown.The "other," the "unknown" world—good! but to speak of the "true world" is asgood as "knowingsomething about it,"—that is thecontraryof the assumption of anx-world....
In short, the worldxmight be in every way a more tedious, a more inhuman, and a less dignified world than this one.
It would be quite another matter if it were assumed that there were severalx-worlds—that is to say, every possible kind of world besides our own. But this hasnever been assumed....
C.
Problem: why has theimage of the other worldalways been to the disadvantage of "this" one—that is to say, always stood as a criticism of it; what does this point to?—
A people that are proud of themselves, and who are on the ascending path of Life, always; pictureanotherexistence as lower and less valuable than theirs; they regard the strange unknown world as their enemy, as their opposite; they feel no curiosity, but rather repugnance in regard to what is strange to them.... Such a body of men would never admit that another people were the "true people"....
The very fact that such a distinction is possible,—that this world should be called the world of appearance, and that the other should be called the true world,—is symptomatic.
The places of origin of the idea, of "another world":
The philosopher who invents a rational world wherereasonand logical functions areadequate:—this is the root of the "true" world.The religious man who invents a "divine world";—this is the root of the "denaturalised" and the "anti-natural" world.The moral man who invents a "free world":—this is the root of the good, the perfect, the just, and the holy world.
The philosopher who invents a rational world wherereasonand logical functions areadequate:—this is the root of the "true" world.
The religious man who invents a "divine world";—this is the root of the "denaturalised" and the "anti-natural" world.
The moral man who invents a "free world":—this is the root of the good, the perfect, the just, and the holy world.
Thecommon factorin the three places of origin:psychologicalerror, physiological confusion.
With what attributes is the "other world," as it actually appears in history, characterised? With the stigmata of philosophical, religious, and moral prejudices.
The "other world" as it appears in the light of these facts, issynonymouswithnot-Being,with not-living, with thewillnot to live....
General aspect:it was the instinct of thefatigue of living,and not that of life, which created the "other world."