Footnotes1.Philosophy of Theism: The Gifford Lectures delivered before the University of Edinburgh in 1894-96. (Second Edition, 1899.)2.Essay on Vision, sect. 147, 148.3.Principles, sect. 6.4.Preface to theThree Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous.5.By Anthony Collins.6.See vol. III, Appendix B.7.Murdoch Martin, a native of Skye, author of aVoyage to St. Kilda(1698), and aDescription of the Western Islands of Scotland(1703).8.See Stewart'sWorks(ed. Hamilton), vol. I. p. 161. There is a version of this story by DeQuincey, in his quaint essay onMurder considered as one of the Fine Arts.9.Sir John became Lord Percival in that year.10.A place more than once visited by Berkeley.11.Bakewell'sMemoirs of the Court of Augustus, vol. II. p. 177.12.A letter in Berkeley'sLife and Letters, p. 93, which led me to a different opinion, I have now reason to believe was not written by him, nor was it written in 1721. The research of Dr. Lorenz, confirmed by internal evidence, shews that it was written in October, 1684, before Berkeley the philosopher was born, and when the Duke of Ormond was Lord Lieutenant of Ireland. The writer was probably the Hon. and Rev. George Berkeley, a Prebendary of Westminster in 1687, who died in 1694. The wife of the“pious Robert Nelson”was a daughter of Earl Berkeley, and this“George”was her younger brother.13.Percival MSS.14.For the letter, see Editor's Preface to theProposal for a College in Bermuda, vol. IV. pp. 343-44.15.Afterwards Sir John James.16.Smibert the artist, who made a picture of Berkeley in 1725, and afterwards in America of the family party then at Gravesend.17.Historical Register, vol. XIII, p. 289 (1728).18.New England Weekly Courier, Feb. 3, 1729.19.For valuable information about Rhode Island, reproduced inBerkeley's Life and Correspondenceand here, I am indebted to Colonel Higginson, to whom I desire to make this tardy but grateful acknowledgement.20.James, Dalton, and Smibert.21.Whitehall, having fallen into decay, has been lately restored by the pious efforts of Mrs. Livingston Mason, in concert with the Rev. Dr. E. E. Hale, and others. This good work was completed in the summer of 1900; and the house is now as nearly as possible in the state in which Berkeley left it.22.See vol. III, Appendix C.23.Three Men of Letters, by Moses Coit Tyler (New York, 1895). He records some of the American academical and other institutions that are directly or indirectly, due to Berkeley.24.The thought implied in this paragraph is pursued in myPhilosophy of Theism, in which the ethical perfection of the Universal Mind is taken as the fundamental postulate in all human experience. If the Universal Mind is not ethically perfect, the universe (including our spiritual constitution) is radically untrustworthy.25.Life and Letters of Berkeley, p. 222.26.The third Earl of Shaftesbury, the pupil of Locke, and author of theCharacteristics. In addition to the well-known biography by Dr. Fowler, the present eminent Vice-Chancellor of Oxford, Shaftesbury has been interpreted in two other lately published works—aLifeby Benjamin Rand, Ph.D. (1900), and an edition of theCharacteristics, with an Introduction and Notes, by John M. Robertson (1900).27.The title of this book is—Things Divine and Supernatural conceived by Analogy with Things Natural and Human, by the Author ofThe Procedure, Extent and Limits of the Human Understanding. TheDivine Analogyappeared in 1733, and theProcedurein 1728.28.Spinoza argues that what iscalled“understanding”and“will”in God, has no more in common with human understanding and will than the dog-star in the heavens has with the animal we call a dog. See Spinoza'sEthica, I. 17,Scholium.29.The question of the knowableness of God, or Omnipotent Moral Perfection in the concrete, enters into recent philosophical and theological discussion in Britain. Calderwood, in hisPhilosophy of the Infinite(1854), was one of the earliest, and not the least acute, of Hamilton's critics in this matter. The subject is lucidly treated by Professor Andrew Seth (Pringle-Pattison) in hisLectures on Theism(1897) and in a supplement to Calderwood'sLife(1900). So also Huxley'sDavid Humeand Professor Iverach'sIs God Knowable?30.Stewart'sWorks. vol. I. pp. 350-1.31.Berkeley MSS. possessed by Archdeacon Rose.32.Pope's poetic tribute to Berkeley belongs to this period—“Even in a bishop I can spy desert;Secker is decent; Rundle has a heart:Manners with candour are to Benson given,To Berkeley—every virtue under heaven.”Epilogue to the Satires.Also his satirical tribute to the critics of Berkeley—“Truth's sacred fort th' exploded laugh shall win;And Coxcombs vanquish Berkeley with a grin.”Essay on Satire,Part II.33.Berkeley'sLife and Letters, p. 210.34.Bacon'sNovuin Organum. Distributio Operis.35.Section 141.36.See“Editor's Preface to Alciphron.”37.Compare Essay II in theGuardianwith this.38.Taylor, in later life, conformed to the Anglican Church.39.See Berkeley'sLife and Letters, chap. viii.40.The Primacy.41.This seems to have been his eldest son, Henry.42.His son George was already settled at Christ Church. Henry, the eldest son, born in Rhode Island, was then“abroad in the south of France for his health,”as one of his brother George's letters tells us, found among the Johnson MSS.43.See Appendix D. Reid, like Berkeley, held that“matter cannot be the cause of anything,”but this not as a consequence of the new conception of the world presented to the senses, through which alone Berkeley openshisway to its powerlessness; although Reid supposes that in his youth he followed Berkeley in this too. SeeThomas Reid(1898), in“Famous Scots Series,”where I have enlarged on this.44.Johnson MSS.45.That Berkeley was buried in Oxford is mentioned in his son's letter to Johnson, in which he says :“His remains are interred in the Cathedral of Christ Church, and next week a monument to his memory will be erected with an inscription by Dr. Markham, a Student of this College.”As the son was present at, and superintended the arrangements for his father's funeral, it can be no stretch of credulity to believe that he knew where his father was buried. It may be added that Berkeley himself had provided in his Will“that my body be buried in the churchyard of the parish in which I die.”The Will, dated July 31, 1752, is givenin extensoin myLife and Lettersof Berkeley, p. 345. We have also the record of burial in the Register of Christ Church Cathedral, which shews that“on January ye 20th1753, ye Right Reverend John (sic) Berkley, LdBishop of Cloyne, was buryed”there. This disposes of the statement on p. 17 of Diprose'sAccount of the Parish of Saint Clement Danes(1868), that Berkeley was buried in that church.I may add that a beautiful memorial of Berkeley has lately been placed in the Cathedral of Cloyne, by subscriptions in this country and largely in America.46.“General ideas,”i.e.abstractgeneral ideas, distinguished, in Berkeley's nominalism, fromconcretegeneral ideas, or from general names, which are signs of any one of an indefinite number of individual objects. Cf.Principles,Introduction, sect. 16.47.Introduction to thePrinciples of Human Knowledge.48.“co-existing ideas,”i.e. phenomena presented in uniform order to the senses.49.Newton postulates a world of matter and motion, governed mechanically by laws within itself: Berkeley finds himself charged with New Principles, demanded by reason, with which Newton's postulate is inconsistent.50.He attempts this in many parts of thePrinciplesandDialogues. He recognises the difficulty of reconciling his New Principles with theidentityandpermanenceof sensible things.51.He contemplated thus early applications of his New Principles to Mathematics, afterwards made in his book ofPrinciples, sect. 118-32.52.What Berkeley callsideasare either perceptible by the senses or imagined: either way they are concrete:abstract ideasare empty words.53.i.e. the existence of bodies and qualities independently of—in abstraction from—all percipient mind. While the spiritual theism of Descartes is acceptable, he rejects his mechanical conception of the material world.54.But a“house”or a“church”includes more thanvisibleideas, so that we cannot, strictly speaking, be said to see it. We see immediately only visible signs of its invisible qualities.55.This is added in the margin.56.The total impotence of Matter, and the omnipotence of Mind or Spirit in Nature, is thus early becoming the dominant thought with Berkeley.57.This refers to an objection to the New Principles that is apparently reinforced by recent discoveries in geology. But if these contradict the Principles, so does the existence of a table while I am only seeing it.58.Existence, in short, can be realised only in the form of living percipient mind.59.Berkeley hardly distinguishes uncontingent mathematicalrelations, to which the sensible ideas or phenomena in which the relations are concretely manifested must conform.60.M. T. = matter tangible; M. V. = matter visible; M. . = matter sensible. The distinctions n question were made prominent in theEssay on Vision. See sect. 1, 121-45.61.Which the common supposition regarding primary qualities seems to contradict.62.[That need not have been blotted out—'tis good sense, if we do but determine wtwe mean bythingandidea.]—Author, on blank page of the MS.63.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. III. ch. 4, § 8, where he criticises attempts to define motion, as involving apetitio.64.George Cheyne, the physician (known afterwards as author of theEnglish Malady), published in 1705 a work on Fluxions, which procured him admission to the Royal Society. He was born in 1670.65.This reminds us of Hume, and inclines towards the empirical notion of Causation, as merely constancy in sequence—not even continuous metamorphosis.66.This is Berkeley's objection to abstract, i.e. unperceived, quantities and infinitesimals—important in the sequel.67.The“lines and figures”of pure mathematics, that is to say; which he rejects as meaningless, in his horror unrealisable abstractions.68.Things really exist, that is to say, in degrees, e.g. in a lesser degree, when they are imagined than when they are actually perceived by our senses; but, in this wide meaning of existence, they may in both cases be said to exist.69.Added on blank page of the MS.70.In Berkeley's limitation of the termideato what is presented objectively in sense, or represented concretely in imagination. Accordingly“an infinite idea”would be an idea which transcends ideation—an express contradiction.71.Does thehumanspirit depend onsensibleideas as much as they depend on spirit? Other orders of spiritual beings may be percipient of other sorts of phenomena than those presented in those few senses to which man is confined, although self-conscious activity abstracted fromallsorts of presented phenomena seems impossible. But a self-conscious spirit is not necessarily dependent onourmaterial world oroursense experience.72.[This I do not altogether approve of.]—Author, on margin.73.He afterwards guarded the difference, by contrastingnotionandidea, confining the latter to phenomena presented objectively to our senses, or represented in sensuous imagination, and applying the former to intellectual apprehension of“operations of the mind,”and of“relations”among ideas.74.SeePrinciples, sect. 89.75.Is thought, then, independent of language? Can we realise thought worthy of the name without use of words? This is Berkeley's excessive juvenile reaction against verbal abstractions.76.Every general notion isideally realisablein one or other of its possible concrete or individual applications.77.This is the germ of Berkeley's notion of the objectivity of the material world to individual percipients and so of the rise of individual self-consciousness.78.Added by Berkeley on blank page of the MS.79.Cf. p.420, note 2. Bishop Sprat'sHistory of the Royal Societyappeared in 1667.80.Much need; for what he means byideahas not been attended to by his critics.81.What“Second Book”is this? Does he refer to the“Second Part”of thePrinciples, which never appeared? God is the culmination of his philosophy, inSiris.82.This is Berkeley's material substance. Individual material substances are for him, steady aggregates of sense-given phenomena, having the efficient and final cause of their aggregation in eternally active Mind—active mind, human and Divine, being essential to their realisation for man.83.Cf. Introduction to thePrinciples, especially sect. 18-25.84.Stillingfleet charges Locke with“discarding substance out of the reasonable part of the world.”85.The philosophers supposed the real things to exist behind our ideas, in concealment: Berkeley was now beginning to think that the objective ideas or phenomena presented to the senses, the existence of which needs no proof, werethemselvesthe significant and interpretable realities of physical science.86.If the material world can berealonly in and through a percipient intelligence, as the realising factor.87.Cf.Principles, sect. 13, 119-122, which deny the possibility of an idea or mental picture corresponding to abstract number.88.“Præcedaneous,”i.e. precedent.89.Who refunds human as well as natural causation into Divine agency.90.In which Locke treats“Of the Reality of Knowledge,”including questions apt to lead Berkeley to inquire, Whether we could in reason suppose reality in the absence of all realising mind.91.Locke's“abstract idea”is misconceived and caricatured by Berkeley in his impetuosity.92.This and other passages refer to the scepticism, that is founded on the impossibility of our comparing our ideas of things with unperceived real things; so that we can never escape from the circle of subjectivity. Berkeley intended to refute this scepticism.93.Probably Samuel Madden, who afterwards edited theQuerist.94.This“First Book”seems to be“Part I”of the projectedPrinciples—the only Part ever published. Here he inclines to“perception or thought in general,”in the language of Descartes; but in the end he approximates to Locke's“sensation and reflection.”SeePrinciples, sect. 1, and notes.95.Does he mean, like Hume afterwards, that ideas or phenomena constitute the ego, so that I am only the transitory conscious state of each moment?96.“Consciousness”—a term rarely used by Berkeley or his contemporaries.97.This too, if strictly interpreted, looks like an anticipation of Hume's reduction of the ego into successive“impressions”—“nothing but a bundle or collection of different perceptions, which succeed one another with inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and movement.”See Hume'sTreatise, Part IV. sect. 6.98.What“Third Book”is here projected? Was a“Third Part”of thePrinciplesthen in embryo?99.This is scarcely done in the“Introduction”to thePrinciples.100.Berkeley, as we find in theCommonplace Book, is fond of conjecturing how a man all alone in the world, freed from the abstractions of language, would apprehend the realities of existence, which he must then face directly, without the use or abuse of verbal symbols.101.This“N. B.”is expanded in the Introduction to thePrinciples.102.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 4.103.What is immediately realised in our percipient experience must be presumed or trusted in as real, if we have any hold of reality, or the moral right to postulate that our universe is fundamentally trustworthy.104.But he distinguishes, in thePrinciplesand elsewhere, between an idea of sense and a percipient ego.105.They reappear inSiris.106.In one of Berkeley's letters to Johnson, a quarter of a century after theCommonplace Book, when he was in America, he observes that“the mechanical philosophers pretend to demonstrate that matter is proportional to gravity. But their argument concludes nothing, and is a mere circle”—as he proceeds to show.107.In thePrinciples, sect. 1-33, he seeks to fulfil the expository part of this intention; in sect. 33-84, also in theDialogues between Hylas and Philonous, he is“particular in answering objections.”108.If Matter is arbitrarily credited with omnipotence.109.On freedom as implied in a moral and responsible agent, cf.Siris, sect. 257 and note.110.Is not this one way of expressing the Universal Providence and constant uniting agency of God in the material world?111.Hereideaseems to be used in its wider signification, includingnotion.112.“infinitely greater”—Does infinity admit of imaginable degrees?113.'embrangled'—perplexed—involved in disputes.114.SeePrinciples, Introduction, sect. 24.115.“homonymy,”i.e. equivocation.116.Voluntary or responsible activity is not an idea or datum of sense, nor can it be realised in sensuous imagination. He uses“thing”in the wide meaning which comprehends persons.117.Voluntary or responsible activity is not an idea or datum of sense, nor can it be realised in sensuous imagination. He uses“thing”in the wide meaning which comprehends persons.118.Is this consistent with other entries?119.Essay, Bk. II. ch. i. sect. 9-19.120.This is one way of meeting the difficulty of supposed interruptions of conscious or percipient activity.121.This seems to imply that voluntary action is mysteriously self-originated.122.“perception.”He does not include the percipient.123.“without,”i.e. unrealised by any percipient.124.This would makeideathe term only for what is imagined, as distinguished from what is perceived in sense.125.In a strict use of words, onlypersonsexercise will—notthings.126.As we must do in imagination, which (unlike sense) is representative; for the mental images represent original data of sense-perception.127.Does he not allow that we havemeaning, if notideas, when we use the terms virtue and vice and moral action?128.As Locke says we are.129.“Existenceandunityare ideas that are suggested to the understanding by every object without and every idea within. When ideas are in our minds, we consider thattheyexist.”Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 7. sect. 7.130.i.e. of Existence in the abstract—unperceived and unperceiving—realised neither in percipient life nor in moral action.131.This suggests that God knows sensible things without being sentient of any.132.Cf.Principles, Introd., sect. 1-5.133.Cf. Preface toPrinciples; also toDialogues.134.i.e. that ethics was a science of phenomena or ideas.135.i.e. of theindependentexistence of Matter.136.'bodies'—i.e. sensible things—not unrealised Matter.137.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 13.138.Locke died in October, 1704.139.“without the mind,”i.e. abstracted from all active percipient life.140.e.g. secondary qualities of sensible things, in which pleasure and pain are prominent.141.e.g. primary qualities, in which pleasure and pain are latent.142.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 13. § 21, ch. 17. § 4; also Bk. IV. ch. 3. § 6; also his controversy with Bishop Stillingfleet regarding the possibility of Matter thinking. With Berkeley real space is a finite creature, dependent for realisation on living percipient Spirit.143.But what of the origination of the volition itself?144.Essay, Bk. I. ch. iv. § 18. See also Locke'sLettersto Stillingfleet.145.It is, according to Berkeley, the steady union or co-existence of a group of sense-phenomena.146.Essay, Bk. II. ch. i. § 10—where he argues for interruptions of consciousness.“Men think not always.”147.In other words, the material world is wholly impotent: all activity in the universe is spiritual.148.On the order of its four books and the structure of Locke'sEssay, see the Prolegomena in my edition of theEssay, pp. liv-lviii.149.i.e. independent imperceptible Matter.150.What of the earliest geological periods, asks Ueberweg? But is there greater difficulty in such instances than in explaining the existence of a table or a house, while one is merely seeing, without touching?151.Locke explains“substance”as“an uncertain supposition of we know not what.”Essay, Bk. I. ch. 4. § 18.152.Locke makes certainty consist in the agreement of“our ideas with the reality of things.”SeeEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 4. § 18. Here the sceptical difficulty arises, which Berkeley meets under his Principle. If we have no perception of reality, we cannot compare our ideas with it, and so cannot have any criterion of reality.153.[This seems wrong. Certainty, real certainty, is of sensible ideas. I may be certain without affirmation or negation.—Author.] This needs further explanation.154.This entry and the preceding tends to resolve all judgments which are not what Kant calls analytical into contingent.155.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 1, §§ 3-7, and ch. 3. §§ 7-21. The stress Berkeley lays on“co-existence”is significant.156.i.e. we must not doubt the reality of the immediate data of sense but accept it, as“the mob”do.157.But is imagination different from actual perception only indegreeof reality?158.Cf.Principles, sect. 13, 120; also Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 7. sect. 7.159.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 1.160.Berkeley's aim evidently is to deliver men from empty abstractions, by a return to more reasonably interpreted common-sense.161.The sort ofexternalworld that is intelligible to us is that of whichanother personis percipient, and which isobjectiveto me, in a percipient experience foreign to mine.162.Cf. Berkeley'sArithmeticaandMiscellanea Mathematica, published while he was making his entries in thisCommonplace Book.163.Minima sensibilia?164.Pleasures,quâpleasures, are natural causes of correlative desires, as pains or uneasinesses are of correlative aversions. This is implied in the very nature of pleasure and pain.165.Here we have his explanation ofidea.166.Absent things.167.Here, as elsewhere, he resolves geometry, as strictly demonstrable, into a reasoned system of analytical or verbal propositions.168.Compare this with note 3, p. 34; also with the contrast between Sense and Reason, inSiris. Is the statement consistent with implied assumptions even in thePrinciples, apart from which they could not cohere?169.To have anideaof God—as Berkeley uses idea—would imply that God is an immediately perceptible, or at least an imaginable object.170.Cf.Principles, sect. 89.171.Ch. 11. § 5.172.Why add—“or perception”?173.Here we have Berkeley's favourite thought of the divine arbitrariness of the constitution of Nature, and of its laws of change.174.This suggests the puzzle, that the cause of every volition must be a preceding volition, and so onad infinitum.175.Recherche, I. 19.176.i.e. of his own individual mind.177.i.e. toapercipient mind, but not necessarily tomine; for natural laws are independent of individual will, although the individual participates in perception of the ordered changes.178.Cf. theArithmetica.179.i.e. which are not phenomena. This recognition of originative Will even then distinguished Berkeley.180.Is this Part II of thePrinciples, which was lost in Italy?181.The thought of articulaterelationsto which real existence must conform, was not then at least in Berkeley's mind. Hence the empiricism and sensationalism into which he occasionally seems to rush in theCommonplace Book, in his repulsion from empty abstractions.182.This is the essence of Berkeley's philosophy—“a blind agent is a contradiction.”183.This is the basis of Berkeley's reasoning for the necessarilyunrepresentativecharacter of the ideas or phenomena that are presented to our senses.Theyare the originals.184.Berkeley's horror of abstract or unperceived space and atoms is partly explained by dogmas in natural philosophy that are now antiquated.185.Ralph [?] Raphson, author ofDemonstratio de Deo(1710), and also ofDe Spatio Reali, seu ente Infinito: conamen mathematico-metaphysicum(1697), to which Berkeley refers in one of his letters to Johnson. See also Green'sPrinciples of Natural Philosophy(1712). The immanence of omnipotent goodness in the material world was unconsciously Berkeley's presupposition. In God we have our being.186.Note here Berkeley's version of the causal principle, which is really the central presupposition of his whole philosophy—viz. every event in the material world must be the issue of acting Will.187.So Locke on an ideally perfect memory.Essay, Bk. II. ch. x. § 9.188.John Sergeant was the author ofSolid Philosophy asserted against the Fancies of the Ideists(London, 1697); also ofthe Method to Science(1696). He was a deserter from the Church of England to the Church of Rome, and wrote several pieces in defence of Roman theology—some of them in controversy with Tillotson.189.Spirit and Matter are mutually dependent; but Spirit is the realising factor and real agent in the universe.190.See Descartes,Meditations, III; Spinoza,Epist.II, ad Oldenburgium.191.Cf.Principles, sect. 2.192.Is“inclusion”here virtually a synonym for verbal definition?193.SeePrinciples, sect. 2. The universe of Berkeley consists of Active Spirits that perceive and produce motion in impotent ideas or phenomena, realised in the percipient experience of persons. All supposed powers in Matter are refunded into Spirit.194.When self-conscious agents are included among“things.”We can have no sensuous image, i.e. idea, ofspirit, although he maintains we can use the word intelligently.195.Berkeley insists that we should individualise our thinking—“ipsis consuescere rebus,”as Bacon says,—to escape the dangers of artificial signs. This is the drift of his assault on abstract ideas, and his repulsion from what is not concrete. He would even dispense with words in his meditations in case of being sophisticated by abstractions.196.Nature or the phenomenal world in short is the revelation of perfectly reasonable Will.197.Gerard De Vries, the Cartesian.198.Are the things of sense only modes in which percipient persons exist?199.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 9. § 8.200.Time being relative to the capacity of the percipient.201.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 9. § 8.202.To perceive what is not an idea (as Berkeley uses idea) is to perceive what is not realised, and therefore not real.203.So things have apotentialobjective existence in the Divine Will.204.With Berkeley, change is time, and time, abstracted from all changes, is meaningless.205.Could he know, by seeing only, even that hehada body?206.“the ideas attending these impressions,”i.e. the ideas that are correlatives of the (by us unperceived) organic impressions.207.The Italian physical and metaphysical philosopher Fardella (1650-1718) maintained, by reasonings akin to those of Malebranche, that the existence of the material world could not be scientifically proved, and could only be maintained by faith in authoritative revelation. See hisUniversæ Philosophiæ Systema(1690), and especially hisLogica(1696).208.Locke'sEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 11.209.What does he mean by“unknown substratum”?210.He gets rid of the infinite in quantity, because it is incapable of concrete manifestation to the senses. When a phenomenon given in sense reaches theminimum sensibile, it reaches what is for us the margin of realisable existence: it cannot be infinitely little and still a phenomenon: insensible phenomena of sense involve a contradiction. And so too of the infinitely large.211.In short he would idealise the visible world but not the tangible world. In thePrinciples, Berkeley idealises both.212.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 149-59, where he concludes that“neither abstract nor visible extension makes the object of geometry.”213.By the adult, who has learned to interpret its visual signs.214.Inasmuch as no physical consequencesfollowthe volition; which however is still self-originated.215.“A succession of ideas I take toconstitutetime, and not to be only the sensible measure thereof, as Mr. Locke and others think.”(Berkeley's letter to Johnson.)216.Cf.Essay, Bk. II. ch. 16, sect. 8.217.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 67-77.218.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 88-120.219.This is of the essence of Berkeley's philosophy.220.But in moral freedom originates in the agent, instead of being“consecutive”to his voluntary acts or found only in their consequences.221.“Strigose”(strigosus)—meagre.222.As he afterwards expresses it, we have intelligiblenotions, but notideas—sensuous pictures—of the states or acts of our minds.223.[“Omnes reales rerum proprietates continentur in Deo.”What means Le Clerc &c. by this? Log. I. ch. 8.]—Author, on margin.224.“Si non rogas intelligo.”225.This way of winning others to his own opinions is very characteristic of Berkeley. See p.92and note.226.SeeThird Dialogue, onsamenessin things andsamenessin persons, which it puzzles him to reconcile with his New Principles.227.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 52-61.228.Cf.Principles, sect. 101-134.229.“distance”—on opposite page in the MS. Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 140.230.Direct perception of phenomena is adequate to the perceived phenomena; indirect or scientific perception is inadequate, leaving room for faith and trust.231.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 107-8.232.The Divine Ideas of Malebranche and the sensuous ideas of Berkeley differ.233.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 71.234.Cf. Malebranche,Recherche, Bk. I. c. 6. That and the following chapters seem to have been in Berkeley's mind.235.He here assumes that extension (visible) is implied in the visible idea we call colour.236.This strikingly illustrates Berkeley's use of“idea,”and what he intends when he argues against“abstract”ideas.237.An interesting autobiographical fact. From childhood he was indisposed to take things on trust.238.Essay on Vision, sect. 88-119.239.“thoughts,”i.e. ideas of sense?240.This, in a crude way, is the distinction of δύναμις and ἐνέργεια. It helps to explain Berkeley's meaning, when he occasionally speaks of the ideas or phenomena that appear in the sense experience of different persons as if they were absolutely independent entities.241.To be“in an unperceiving thing,”i.e. to be real, yet unperceived. Whatever is perceived is, because realised only through a percipient act, anidea—in Berkeley's use of the word.242.This as to the“Platonic strain”is not in the tone ofSiris.243.John Keill (1671-1721), an eminent mathematician, educated at the University of Edinburgh; in 1710 Savilian Professor of Astronomy at Oxford, and the first to teach the Newtonian philosophy in that University. In 1708 he was engaged in a controversy in support of Newton's claims to the discovery of the method of fluxions.244.This suggests a negative argument for Kant's antinomies, and for Hamilton's law of the conditioned.245.Newton became Sir Isaac on April 16, 1705. Was this written before that date?246.These may beconsideredseparately, but notpicturedas such.247.In as far as they have not been sensibly realised in finite percipient mind.248.[Or rather that invisible length does exist.]—Author, on margin.249.Bonaventura Cavalieri (1598-1647), the Italian mathematician. HisGeometry of Indivisibles(1635) prepared the way for the Calculus.250.[By“the excuse”is meant the finiteness of our mind—making it possible for contradictions to appear true to us.]—Author, on margin.251.He allows elsewhere that words with meanings not realisable in imagination, i.e. in the form of idea, may discharge a useful office. SeePrinciples, Introduction, sect. 20.252.We do not perceive unperceived matter, but only matter realised in living perception—the percipient act being the factor of its reality.253.The secondary qualities of things.254.Because, while dependent on percipient sense, they are independent ofmypersonal will, being determined to appear under natural law, by Divine agency.255.Keill'sIntroductio ad veram Physicam(Oxon. 1702)—Lectio 5—a curious work, dedicated to the Earl of Pembroke.256.[Extension without breadth—i. e. insensible, intangible length—is not conceivable. 'Tis a mistake we are led into by the doctrine of abstraction.]—Author, on margin of MS.257.Here“Sir Isaac.”Hence written after April, 1705.258.Essay, Bk. IV. ch. iv. sect. 18; ch. v. sect. 3, &c.259.He appliesthingto self-conscious persons as well as to passive objects of sense.260.Scaligerana Secunda, p. 270.261.[These arguments must be proposed shorter and more separate in the Treatise.]—Author, on margin.262.“Idea”here used in its wider meaning—for“operations of mind,”as well as for sense presented phenomena that are independent of individual will. Cf.Principles, sect. 1.263.“sensations,”i.e. objective phenomena presented in sense.264.SeePrinciples, sect. 1.265.SeePrinciples, sect. 2.266.An“unperceiving thing”cannot be the factor of material reality.267.[To the utmost accuracy, wanting nothing of perfection.Theirsolutions of problems, themselves must own to fall infinitely short of perfection.]—Author, on margin.268.Jean de Billy and René de Billy, French mathematicians—the former author ofNova Geometriæ Clavisand other mathematical works.269.According to Baronius, in the fifth volume of his“Annals,”Ficinus appeared after death to Michael Mercatus—agreeably to a promise he made when he was alive—to assure him of the life of the human spirit after the death of the body.270.So far as we are factors of their reality, in sense and in science, or can be any practical way concerned with them.271.Cf.Principles, sect. 101-34.272.“something,”i.e.abstractsomething.273.Lord Pembroke (?)—to whom thePrincipleswere dedicated, and to whom Locke dedicated hisEssay.274.This is an interesting example of a feature that is conspicuous in Berkeley—the art of“humoring an opponent in his own way of thinking,”which it seems was an early habit. It is thus that he insinuates his New Principles in theEssay on Vision, and so prepares to unfold and defend them in the book ofPrinciplesand the threeDialogues—straining language to reconcile them with ordinary modes of speech.275.In Diderot'sLettre sur les aveugles, à l'usage de ceux qui voient, where Berkeley, Molyneux, Condillac, and others are mentioned. Cf. also Appendix, pp. 111, 112; andTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 71, with the note, in which some recorded experiments are alluded to.276.De Anima, II. 6, III. 1, &c. Aristotle assigns a pre-eminent intellectual value to the sense of sight. See, for instance, hisMetaphysics, I. 1.277.Sir A. Grant, (Ethics of Aristotle, vol. II. p. 172) remarks, as to the doctrine that the Common Sensibles are apprehended concomitantly by the senses, that:“this is surely the true view; we see in the apprehension of number, figure, and the like, not an operation of sense, but the mind putting its own forms and categories, i.e. itself, on the external object. It would follow then that the senses cannot really be separated from the mind; the senses and the mind each contribute an element to every knowledge. Aristotle's doctrine of κοινὴ αἴσθησις would go far, if carried out, to modify his doctrine of the simple and innate character of the senses, e.g. sight (cf.Eth.II. 1, 4), and would prevent its collision with Berkeley'sTheory of Vision.”—See also Sir W. Hamilton,Reid's Works, pp. 828-830.Dugald Stewart (Collected Works, vol. I. p. 341, note) quotes Aristotle'sEthics, II. 1, as evidence that Berkeley's doctrine,“with respect to the acquired perceptions of sight, was quite unknown to the best metaphysicians of antiquity.”278.A work resembling Berkeley's in its title, but in little else, appeared more than twenty years before theEssay—theNova Visionis Theoriaof Dr. Briggs, published in 1685.279.SeeTreatise on the Eye, vol. II. pp. 299, &c.280.See Reid'sInquiry, ch. v. §§ 3, 5, 6, 7; ch. vi. § 24, andEssays on the Intellectual Powers, II. ch. 10 and 19.281.While Sir W. Hamilton (Lectures on Metaphysics, lxxviii) acknowledges the scientific validity of Berkeley's conclusions, as to the way we judge of distances, he complains, in the same lecture, that“the whole question is thrown into doubt by the analogy of the lower animals,”i.e. by their probablevisual instinctof distances; and elsewhere (Reid'sWorks, p. 137, note) he seems to hesitate about Locke's Solution of Molyneux's Problem, at least in its application to Cheselden's case. Cf. Leibniz,Nouveaux Essais, Liv. II. ch. 9, in connexion with this last.282.An almost solitary exception in Britain to this unusual uniformity on a subtle question in psychology is found in Samuel Bailey'sReview of Berkeley's Theory of Vision, designed to show the unsoundness of that celebrated Speculation, which appeared in 1842. It was the subject of two interesting rejoinders—a well-weighed criticism, in theWestminster Review, by J.S. Mill, since republished in hisDiscussions; and an ingenious Essay by Professor Ferrier, inBlackwood's Magazine, republished in hisPhilosophical Remains. The controversy ended on that occasion with Bailey'sLetter to a Philosopher in reply to some recent attempts to vindicate Berkeley's Theory of Vision, and in further elucidation of its unsoundness, and a reply to it by each of his critics. It was revived in 1864 by Mr. Abbott of Trinity College, Dublin, whose essay onSight and Touchis“an attempt to disprove the received (or Berkeleian) Theory of Vision.”283.Afterwards (in 1733) Earl of Egmont. Born about 1683, he succeeded to the baronetcy in 1691, and, after sitting for a few years in the Irish House of Commons, was in 1715 created Baron Percival, in the Irish peerage. In 1732 he obtained a charter to colonise the province of Georgia in North America. His name appears in the list of subscribers to Berkeley's Bermuda Scheme in 1726. He died in 1748. He corresponded frequently with Berkeley from 1709 onwards.284.Similar terms are applied to the sense of seeing by writers with whom Berkeley was familiar. Thus Locke (Essay, II. ix. 9) refers to sight as“the most comprehensive of all our senses.”Descartes opens hisDioptriqueby designating it as“le plus universal et le plus noble de nos sens;”and he alludes to it elsewhere (Princip.IV. 195) as“le plus subtil de tous les sens.”Malebranche begins his analysis of sight (Recherche, I. 6) by describing it as“le premier, le plus noble, et le plus étendu de tous les sens.”The high place assigned to this sense by Aristotle has been already alluded to. Its office, as the chief organ through which a conception of the material universe as placed in ambient space is given to us, is recognised by a multitude of psychologists and metaphysicians.285.On Berkeley's originality in his Theory of Vision see the Editor's Preface.286.In the first edition alone this sentence followed:—“In treating of all which, it seems to me, the writers of Optics have proceeded on wrong principles.”287.Sect. 2-51 explain the way in which we learn in seeing to judge of Distance or Outness, and of objects as existing remote from our organism, viz. by their association with what we see, and with certain muscular and other sensations in the eye which accompany vision. Sect. 2 assumes, as granted, the invisibility of distance in the line of sight. Cf. sect. 11 and 88—First Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous—Alciphron, IV. 8—Theory of Vision Vindicated and Explained, sect. 62-69.288.i.e. outness, or distance outward from the point of vision—distance in the line of sight—the third dimension of space. Visible distance is visible space or interval between two points (see sect. 112). We can be sensibly percipient of it only whenbothpoints are seen.289.This section is adduced by some of Berkeley's critics as if it were the evidence discovered by him for hisTheory, instead of being, as it is, a passing reference to the scientific ground of the already acknowledged invisibility of outness, or distance in the line of sight. See, for example, Bailey'sReview of Berkeley's Theory of Vision, pp. 38-43, also hisTheory of Reasoning, p. 179 and pp. 200-7—Mill'sDiscussions, vol. II. p. 95—Abbott'sSight and Touch, p. 10, where this sentence is presented as“the sole positive argument advanced by Berkeley.”The invisibility of outness is not Berkeley's discovery, but the way we learn to interpret its visual signs, and what these are.290.i.e. aerial and linear perspective are acknowledged signs of remote distances. But the question, in this and the thirty-six following sections, concerns the visibility ofneardistances only—a few yards in front of us. It was“agreed by all”that beyond this limit distances are suggested by our experience of their signs.291.Cf. this and the four following sections with the quotations in the Editor's Preface, from Molyneux'sTreatise of Dioptrics.292.In the author's last edition we have this annotation:“See what Des Cartes and others have written upon the subject.”293.In the first edition this section opens thus:“I have here set down the common current accounts that are given of our perceiving near distances by sight, which, though they are unquestionably received for true by mathematicians, and accordingly made use of by them in determining the apparent places of objects, do nevertheless,”&c.294.Omitted in the author's last edition.295.i.e. although immediately invisible, it is mediately seen. Mark, here and elsewhere, the ambiguity of the termperception, which now signifies the act of being conscious of sensuous phenomena, and again the act of inferring phenomena of which we are at the time insentient; while it is also applied to the object perceived instead of to the percipient act; and sometimes to imagination, and the higher acts of intelligence.296.“Some men”—“mathematicians,”in first edition.297.i.e. themediateperception.298.“any man”—“all the mathematicians in the world,”in first edition.299.Omitted in the author's last edition.300.Omitted in the author's last edition.301.Sect. 3, 9.302.Observe the first introduction by Berkeley of the termsuggestion, used by him to express a leading factor in his account of the visible world, and again in his more comprehensive account of our knowledge of the material universe in thePrinciples. It had been employed occasionally, among others, by Hobbes and Locke. There are three ways in which the objects we have an immediate perception of in sight may be supposed to conduct us to what we do not immediately perceive: (1) Instinct, or what Reid calls“original suggestion”(Inquiry, ch. VI. sect. 20-24); (2) Custom; (3) Reasoning from accepted premisses. Berkeley's“suggestion”corresponds to the second. (Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 42.)303.In theTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 66, it is added that this“sensation”belongs properly to the sense of touch. Cf. also sect. 145 of thisEssay.304.Here“natural”=“necessary”: elsewhere=divinely arbitrary connexion.305.That ourmediatevision of outness and of objects as thus external, is due to media which have a contingent or arbitrary, instead of a necessary, connexion with the distances which they enable us to see, or of which they are the signs, is a cardinal part of his argument.306.Sect. 2.307.Here, as generally in theEssay, the appeal is to our inward experience, not to phenomena observed by our senses in the organism.308.See sect. 35 for the difference between confused and faint vision. Cf. sect. 32-38 with this section. AlsoTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 68.309.See sect. 6.310.These sections presuppose previous contiguity as an associative law of mental phenomena.311.See Reid'sInquiry, ch. vi. sect. 22.312.Sect. 16-27.—For the signs of remote distances, see sect. 3.313.These are muscular sensations felt in the organ, and degrees of confusion in a visible idea. Berkeley's“arbitrary”signs of distance, near and remote, are either (a) invisible states of the visual organ, or (b) visible appearances.314.In Molyneux'sTreatise of Dioptrics, Pt. I. prop. 31, sect. 9, Barrow's difficulty is stated. Cf. sect. 40 below.315.Christopher Scheiner, a German astronomer, and opponent of the Copernican system, born 1575, died 1650.316.Andrea Tacquet, a mathematician, born at Antwerp in 1611, and referred to by Molyneux as“the ingenious Jesuit.”He published a number of scientific treatises, most of which appeared after his death, in a collected form, at Antwerp in 1669.317.In what follows Berkeley tries to explain by his visual theory seeming contradictions which puzzled the mathematicians.318.This is offered as a verification of the theory that near distances are suggested, according to the order of nature, by non-resembling visual signs, contingently connected with real distance.319.Cf. sect. 78; alsoNew Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 31.320.Berkeley here passes from his proof of visual“suggestion”of all outward distances—i.e. intervals between extremes in the line of sight—by means of arbitrary signs, and considers the nature of visible externality. See note in Hamilton'sReid, p. 177, on the distinction between perception of the external world and perception of distance through the eye.321.See Descartes,Dioptrique, VI—Malebranche,Recherche, Liv. I. ch. 9, 3—Reid'sInquiry, VI. 11.322.Berkeley here begins to found, on the experienced connexion between extension and colour, and between visible and tangible extension, a proof thatoutnessis invisible. From Aristotle onwards it has been assumed that colour is the only phenomenon of which we are immediately percipient in seeing. Visible extension, visible figure, and visible motion are accordingly taken to be dependent on the sensation of colour.323.In connexion with this and the next illustration, Berkeley seems to argue that we are not only unable to see distance in the line of sight, but also that we do not see a distant object in itsreal visiblemagnitude. But elsewhere he affirms that onlytangiblemagnitude is entitled to be calledreal. Cf. sect. 55, 59, 61.324.The sceptical objections to the trustworthiness of the senses, proposed by the Eleatics and others, referred to by Descartes in hisMeditations, and by Malebranche in the First Book of hisRecherche, may have suggested the illustrations in this section. Cf. also Hume's EssayOn the Academical or Sceptical Philosophy. The sceptical difficulty is founded on the assumption that the object seen at different distances is thesame visible object: it is really different, and so the difficulty vanishes.325.Here Berkeley expressly introduces“touch”—a term which with him includes, not merely organic sense of contact, but also muscular and locomotive sense-experience. After this he begins to unfold the antithesis of visual and tactual phenomena, whose subsequent synthesis it is the aim of theNew Theoryto explain. Cf.Principles of Human Knowledge, sect. 43—Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 22 and 25. Note here Berkeley's reticence of his idealization of Matter—tangible as well as visible. Cf.Principles, sect. 44.326.This connexion of our knowledge of distance with our locomotive experience points to a theory which ultimately resolves space into experience of unimpeded locomotion.327.Locke (Essay, Introduction, § 8) takesideavaguely as“the term which serves best to stand whatsoever is the object of the understanding when a man thinks.”Oversight of what Berkeley intends the term idea has made his whole conception of nature and the material universe a riddle to many, of which afterwards.328.The expressive term“outness,”favoured by Berkeley, is here first used.329.“We get the idea of Space,”says Locke,“both by our sight and touch”(Essay, II. 13. § 2). Locke did not contemplate Berkeley's antithesis of visible and tangible extension, and the consequent ambiguity of the term extension; which sometimes signifiescoloured, and at othersresistantexperience in sense.330.For an explanation of this difficulty, see sect. 144.331.“object”—“thing,”in the earlier editions.332.This is the issue of the analytical portion of theEssay.333.Cf. sect. 139-40.334.Here the question of externality, signifying independence of all percipient life, is again mixed up with that of the invisibility of distance outwards in the line of sight.335.Omitted in author's last edition.336.i.e. including muscular and locomotive experience as well as sense of contact. But what are thetangibiliathemselves? Are they also significant, likevisibilia, of a still ulterior reality? This is the problem of thePrinciples of Human Knowledge.337.In this section the conception of a natural Visual Language, makes its appearance, with its implication that Nature is (for us) virtually Spirit. Cf. sect. 140, 147—Principles, sect. 44—Dialogues of Hylas and Philonous—Alciphron, IV. 8, 11—andTheory of Vision Vindicated, passim.338.Sect. 52-87 treat of the invisibility of real, i.e. tactual, Magnitude. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 54-61.339.Sect. 8-15.340.Sect. 41, &c.341.See Molyneux'sTreatise on Dioptrics, B. I. prop. 28.342.See sect. 122-126.343.In short there is a point at which, with our limited sense, we cease to be percipient of colour, in seeing; and of resistance, in locomotion. Though Berkeley regards all visible extensions as sensible, and therefore dependent for their reality on being realised by sentient mind, he does not mean that mind or consciousness is extended. With him, extension, though it exists only in mind,—i.e. as an idea seen, in the case of visible extension, and as an idea touched, in the case of tangible extension,—is yet nopropertyof mind. Mind can exist without being percipient of extension, although extension cannot be realised without mind.344.But this is true, though less obviously, of tangible as well as of visible objects.345.Sect. 49.346.Cf. sect. 139, 140, &c.347.“situation”—not in the earlier editions.348.Sect. 55.349.Omitted in the author's last edition.350.Ordinary sight is virtually foresight. Cf. sect. 85.—See also Malebranche on the external senses, as given primarily for the urgent needs of embodied life, not to immediately convey scientific knowledge,Recherche, Liv. I. ch. 5, 6, 9, &c.351.Sect. 44.—See also sect. 55, and note.352.This supposes“settled”tangibilia, but not“settled”visibilia. Yet the sensible extension given in touch and locomotive experience is also relative—an object beingfeltas larger or smaller according to the state of the organism, and the other conditions of our embodied perception.353.What follows, to end of sect. 63, added in the author's last edition.354.“outward objects,”i.e. objects of which we are percipient in tactual experience, taken in thisEssayprovisionally as the real external objects. SeePrinciples, sect. 44.355.Cf. sect. 144. Note, in this and the three preceding sections, the stress laid on thearbitrarinessof the connexion between the signs which suggest magnitudes, or other modes of extension, and their significates. This is the foundation of theNew Theory; which thus resolvesphysicalcausality into a relation of signs to what they signify and predict—analogous to the relation between words and their accepted meanings.356.In sect. 67-78, Berkeley attempts to verify the foregoing account of the natural signs of Size, by applying it to solve a phenomenon, the cause of which had been long debated among men of science—the visible magnitude of heavenly bodies when seen in the horizon.357.Cf. sect. 10.358.Omitted in the author's last edition. Cf sect. 76, 77.—The explanation in question is attributed to Alhazen, and by Bacon to Ptolemy, while it is sanctioned by eminent scientific names before and since Berkeley.359.“Fourthly”in the second edition. Cf. what follows with sect. 74. Why“lesser”?360.When Berkeley, some years afterwards, visited Italy, he remarked that distant objects appeared to him much nearer than they really were—a phenomenon which he attributed to the comparative purity of the southern air.361.i.e. the original perception, apart from any synthetic operation of suggestion and inferential thought, founded on visual signs.362.In Riccioli'sAlmagest, II. lib. X. sect. 6. quest. 14, we have an account of many hypotheses then current, in explanation of the apparent magnitude of the horizontal moon.363.Gassendi's“Epistolæ quatuor de apparente magnitudine solis humilis et sublimis.”—Opera, tom. III pp. 420-477. Cf. Appendix to thisEssay, p. 110.364.SeeDioptrique, VI.365.Opera Latina, vol. I, p. 376, vol. II, pp. 26-62;English Works, vol. I. p. 462. (Molesworth's Edition.)366.The paper in the Transactions is by Molyneux.367.See Smith'sOptics, pp. 64-67, andRemarks, pp. 48, &c. At p. 55 Berkeley'sNew Theoryis referred to, and pronounced to be at variance with experience. Smith concludes by saying, that in“the second edition of Berkeley'sEssay, and also in a Vindication and Explanation of it (called theVisual Language), very lately published, the author has made some additions to his solution of the said phenomenon; but seeing it still involves and depends on the principle of faintness, I may leave the rest of it to the reader's consideration.”This, which appeared in 1738, is one of the very few early references to Berkeley'sNew Theory of Vision Vindicated.368.Sect. 2-51.369.This sentence is omitted in the author's last edition.370.What follows to the end of this section is not contained in the first edition.371.i.e. tangible.372.Cf. sect. 38; andTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 31.373.“Never”—“hardly,”in first edition.374.Cf. Appendix, p.208.—See Smith'sOptics, B. I. ch. v, andRemarks, p. 56, in which he“leaves it to be considered, whether the said phenomenon is not as clear an instance of the insufficiency of faintness”as of mathematical computation.375.A favourite doctrine with Berkeley, according to whose theory of visibles there can be no absolute visible magnitude, theminimumbeing the least that isperceivableby each seeing subject, and thus relative to his visual capacity. This section is thus criticised, in January, 1752, in a letter signed“Anti-Berkeley,”in theGent. Mag.(vol. XXII, p. 12):“Upon what his lordship asserts with respect to theminimum visibile, I would observe that it is certain that there are infinite numbers of animals which are imperceptible to the naked eye, and cannot be perceived but by the help of a microscope; consequently there are animals whose whole bodies are far less than theminimum visibileof a man. Doubtless these animals have eyes, and, if theirminimum visibilewere equal to that of a man, it would follow that they cannot perceive anything but what is much larger than their whole body; and therefore their own bodies must be invisible to them, because we know they are so to men, whoseminimum visibileis asserted by his lordship to be equal to theirs.”There is some misconception in this. Cf. Appendix toEssay, p. 209.376.Those two defects belong to human consciousness. See Locke'sEssay, II. 10, on the defects of human memory. It is this imperfection which makes reasoning needful—to assist finite intuition. Reasoning is the sign at once of our dignity and our weakness.377.Sect. 59.378.Sect. 80-82.379.Sect. 88-119 relate to the nature, invisibility, and arbitrary visual signs of Situation, or of the localities of tangible things. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 44-53.380.Cf. sect. 2, 114, 116, 118.381.This illustration is taken from Descartes. See Appendix.382.Sect. 10 and 19.383.Sect. 2-51.384.Omitted in author's last edition.385.This is Berkeley's universal solvent of the psychological difficulties involved in visual-perception.386.Cf. sect. 103, 106, 110, 128, &c. Berkeley treats this case hypothetically in theEssay, in defect of actual experiments upon the born-blind, since accumulated from Cheselden downwards. See however the Appendix, andTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 71.387.i.e. tangible things. Cf.Principles, sect. 44.388.The“prejudice,”to wit, which Berkeley would dissolve by his introspective analysis of vision. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 35.389.Thus forming individual concrete things out of what is perceived separately through different senses.390.This briefly is Berkeley's solution of“the knot about inverted images,”which long puzzled men of science.391.i.e. perceivemediately—visible objects,per se, having no tactual situation. Pure vision, he would say, has nothing to do with“high”and“low,”“great”and“inverted,”in the real or tactual meaning of those terms.392.i.e. tangible.393.e.g.“extension,”which, according to Berkeley, is an equivocal term, common (in its different meanings) tovisibiliaandtangibilia. Cf. sect. 139, 140.394.Cf. sect. 93, 106, 110, 128.395.i.e. real or tangible head.396.Cf. sect. 140, 143. In theGent. Mag.(vol. XXII. p. 12),“Anti-Berkeley”thus argues the case of one born blind.“This man,”he adds,“would, by being accustomed to feel one hand with the other, have perceived that the extremity of the hand was divided into fingers—that the extremities of these fingers were distinguished by certain hard, smooth surfaces, of a different texture from the rest of the fingers—and that each finger had certain joints or flexures. Now, if this man was restored to sight, and immediately viewed his hand before he touched it again, it is manifest that the divisions of the extremity of the hand into fingers would be visibly perceived. He would note too the small spaces at the extremity of each finger, which affected his sight differently from the rest of the fingers; upon moving his fingers he would see the joints. Though therefore, by means of this lately acquired sense of seeing, the object affected his mind in a new and different manner from what it did before, yet, as bytouchhe had acquired the knowledge of these several divisions, marks, and distinctions of the hand, and, as the new object ofsightappeared to be divided, marked, and distinguished in a similar manner, I think he would certainly conclude,before he touched his hand, that the thing which he now saw wasthe samewhich he had felt before and called his hand.”397.Locke,Essay, II. 8, 16. Aristotle regards number as a Common Sensible.—De Anima, II. 6, III. 1.398.“If the visible appearance of two shillings had been found connected from the beginning with the tangible idea of one shilling, that appearance would as naturally and readily have signified the unity of the (tangible) object as it now signifies its duplicity.”Reid,Inquiry, VI. 11.399.Here again note Berkeley's inconvenient reticence of his full theory of matter, as dependent on percipient life for its reality. Tangible things are meantime granted to be real“without mind.”Cf.Principles, sect. 43, 44.“Without the mind”—in contrast to sensuous phenomenon only.400.Cf. sect. 131.401.Sect. 2, 88, 116, 118.402.In short, weseeonlyquantities of colour—the real or tactual distance, size, shape, locality, up and down, right and left, &c., being gradually associated with the various visible modifications of colour.403.i.e. tangible.404.Sect. 41-44.405.i.e. tangible things.406.i.e. visible.407.Cf. sect. 41-44. The“eyes”—visible and tangible—are themselves objects of sense.408.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 21-25.409.“Visible ideas”—including sensations muscular and locomotive,feltin the organ of vision. Sect. 16, 27, 57.410.i.e. objects which, in this tentativeEssay, are granted, for argument's sake, to be external, or independent of percipient mind.411.i.e. to inquire whether there are, in this instance, Common Sensibles; and, in particular, whether anextensionof the same kind at least, if not numerically the same, is presented in each. The Kantian theory of ana prioriintuition of space, the common condition of tactual and visual experience, because implied in sense-experience as such, is not conceived by Berkeley. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 15.412.In the following reasoning against abstract, as distinguished from concrete or sense presented (visible or tangible) extension, Berkeley urges some of his favourite objections to“abstract ideas,”fully unfolded in hisPrinciples, Introduction, sect. 6-20.—See alsoAlciphron, VII. 5-8.—Defence of Free Thinking in Mathematics, sect. 45-48.413.Berkeley'sideasare concrete or particular—immediate data of sense or imagination.414.i.e. it cannot be individualized, either as a perceived or an imagined object.415.Sect. 105.416.“Endeavours”in first edition.417.i.e. a mental image of an abstraction, an impossible image, in which the extension and comprehension of the notion must be adequately pictured.418.“deservedly admired author,”in the first edition.419.“this celebrated author,”—“that great man”in second edition. In assailing Locke's“abstract idea,”he discharges the meaning which Locke intended by the term, and then demolishes his own figment.420.Omitted in the author's last edition.421.Omitted in last edition.422.Omitted in last edition.423.Omitted in last edition.424.SeePrinciples, passim.425.Omitted in author's last edition.426.He probably has Locke in his eye.427.On Berkeley's theory, space without relation to bodies (i.e. insensible or abstract space) would not be extended, as not having parts; inasmuch as parts can be assigned to it only with relation to bodies. Berkeley does not distinguish space from sensible extension. Cf. Reid'sWorks, p. 126, note—in which Sir W. Hamilton suggests that one may have ana prioriconception of pure space, andalsoana posterioriperception of finite, concrete space.428.Sect. 121. Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 15.429.i.e. there are no Common Sensibles: from which it follows that we can reason from the one sense to the other only by founding on the constant connexion of their respective phenomena, under a natural yet (for us) contingent law. Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 27, 28.430.Omitted in last edition.431.Cf. sect. 93, 103, 106, 110.432.Omitted in last edition.433.Cf. sect. 43, 103, &c. A plurality of co-existentminimaof coloured points constitutes Berkeley's visible extension; while a plurality of successively experiencedminimaof resistant points constitutes his tactual extension. Whether we can perceive visible extension without experience of muscular movement at least in the eye, he does not here say.434.Omitted in last edition.435.Real distance belongs originally, according to theEssay, to our tactual experience only—in the wide meaning of touch, which includes muscular and locomotive perceptions, as well as the simple perception of contact.436.Added in second edition.437.Omitted in last edition.438.See also Locke's“Correspondence”with Molyneux, in Locke'sWorks, vol. IX. p. 34.—Leibniz,Nouveaux Essais, Liv. II. ch. 9, who, so far granting the fact, disputes the heterogeneity.—Smith'sOptics.—Remarks, §§ 161-170.—Hamilton's Reid, p. 137, note, andLect. Metaph.II. p. 176.439.Omitted in last edition.440.Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 70.441.Cf. sect. 49, 146, &c. Here“same”includes“similar.”442.i.e. visible and tangible motions being absolutely heterogeneous, and the former,at man's point of view, only contingent signs of the latter, we should not, at first sight, be able to interpret the visual signs of tactual phenomena.443.Cf. sect. 122-125.444.Cf.Principles, sect. 111-116; alsoAnalyst, query 12. On Berkeley's system space in its three dimensions is unrealisable without experience of motion.445.Here the term“language of nature”makes its appearance, as applicable to the ideas or visual signs of tactual realities.446.Cf. sect. 16, 27, 97.447.Is“tangible”here used in its narrow meaning—excluding muscular and locomotive experience?448.i.e. as natural signs, divinely associated with their thus implied meanings.449.Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 35.450.Berkeley, in this section, enunciates the principal conclusion in theEssay, which conclusion indeed forms his new theory of Vision.451.A suggestion thus due to natural laws of association. The explanation of the fact that we apprehend, by those ideas or phenomena which are objects of sight, certain other ideas, which neither resemble them, nor efficiently cause them, nor are so caused by them, nor have any necessary connexion with them, comprehends, according to Berkeley, the whole Theory of Vision.“The imagination of every thinking person,”remarks Adam Smith,“will supply him with instances to prove that the ideas received by any one of the senses do readily excite such other ideas, either of the same sense or of any other, as have habitually been associated with them. So that if, on this account, we are to suppose, with a late ingenious writer, that the ideas of sight constitute a Visual Language, because they readily suggest the corresponding ideas of touch—as the terms of a language excite the ideas answering to them—I see not but we may, for the same reason, allow of a tangible, audible, gustatory, and olefactory language; though doubtless the Visual Language will be abundantly more copious than the rest.”Smith'sOptics.—Remarks, p. 29.—And into this conception of a universal sense symbolism, Berkeley's theory of Vision ultimately rises.452.Cf.Alciphron, Dialogue IV. sect. 11-15.453.Sect. 122-125.454.Sect. 127-138.455.Some modern metaphysicians would say, that neither tangible nor visible extension is the object geometry, but abstract extension; and others that space is a necessary implicate of sense-experience, rather than,per se, an object of any single sense. Cf. Kant's explanation of the origin of our mathematical knowledge,Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Elementarlehre, I.456.Cf. sect. 51-66, 144.457.This is a conjecture, not as to the probable ideas of one born blind, but as to the ideas of an“unbodied”intelligence, whoseonlysense was that of seeing. See Reid's speculation (Inquiry, VI. 9) on the“Geometry of Visibles,”and the mental experience of Idomenians, or imaginary beings supposed to have no ideas of the material world except those got by seeing.458.Cf. sect. 130, andNew Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 57. Does Berkeley, in this and the two preceding sections, mean to hint that the only proper object of sight isunextendedcolour; and that, apart from muscular movement in the eye or other locomotion,visibiliaresolve into unextended mathematical points? This question has not escaped more recent British psychologists, including Stewart, Brown, Mill, and Bain, who seem to hold that unextended colour is perceivable and imaginable.459.The bracketed sentence is not retained in the author's last edition, in which the first sentence of sect. 160 is the concluding one of sect. 159, and of theEssay.460.This passage is contained in theDioptricesof Descartes, VI. 13; see also VI. 11.461.The arbitrariness or contingency—as far as our knowledge carries us—of the connexion between the visual phenomena, as signs, on the one hand, and actual distance, as perceived through this means, on the other.462.Cf. sect. 80-83.463.The reference here seems to be to the case described in theTatler(No. 55) of August 16, 1709, in which William Jones, born blind, had received sight after a surgical operation, at the age of twenty, on the 29th of June preceding. A medical narrative of this case appeared, entitledA full and true account of a miraculous cure of a Young Man in Newington, who was born blind, and was in five minutes brought to perfect sight, by Mr. Roger Grant, oculist. London, 1709.464.Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 71, with the relative note.465.Omitted on the title-page in the second edition, but retained in the body of the work.466.Beardsley'sLife and Correspondence of Samuel Johnson, D.D., First President of King's College, New York, p. 72 (1874).467.Beardsley'sLife of Johnson, pp. 71, 72.468.Chandler'sLife of Johnson, Appendix, p. 161.469.Commonplace Book.470.Moreover, even if the outness or distance of thingswerevisible, it would not follow that either they or their distances could be real if unperceived. On the contrary, Berkeley implies that theyareperceivedvisually.471.It is also to be remembered that sensible things exist“in mind,”without being exclusivelymine, as creatures ofmy will. In one sense, that only is mine in which my will exerts itself. But, in another view, my involuntary states of feeling and imagination aremine, because their existence depends on my consciousness of them; and even sensible things are so farmine, because, though present in many minds in common, they are, for me, dependent onmypercipient mind.472.Thomas Herbert, eighth Earl of Pembroke and fifth Earl of Montgomery, was the correspondent and friend of Locke—who dedicated his famousEssayto him, as a work“having some little correspondence with some parts of that nobler and vast system of the sciences your lordship has made so new, exact, and instructive a draft of.”He represents a family renowned in English political and literary history. He was born in 1656; was a nobleman of Christ Church, Oxford, in 1672; succeeded to his titles in 1683; was sworn of the Privy Council in 1689; and made a Knight of the Garter in 1700. He filled some of the highest offices in the state, in the reigns of William and Mary, and of Anne. He was Lord Lieutenant of Ireland in 1707, having previously been one of the Commissioners by whom the union between England and Scotland was negotiated. He died in January 1733.473.Trinity College, Dublin.474.In hisCommonplace BookBerkeley seems to refer his speculations to his boyhood. The conception of the material world propounded in the following Treatise was in his view before the publication of theNew Theory of Vision, which was intended to prepare the way for it.475.Cf. Locke, in the“Epistle Dedicatory”of hisEssay. Notwithstanding the“novelty”of the New Principles, viz.negationof abstract or unperceived Matter, Space, Time, Substance, and Power; andaffirmationof Mind, as the Synthesis, Substance, and Cause of all—much in best preceding philosophy, ancient and modern, was a dim anticipation of it.476.Cf. sect. 6, 22, 24, &c., in illustration of the demonstrative claim of Berkeley's initial doctrine.477.Berkeley entreats his reader, here and throughout, to take pains to understand his meaning, and especially to avoid confounding the ordered ideas or phenomena, objectively presented to our senses, with capricious chimeras of imagination.478.“Philosophy is nothing but the true knowledge of things.”Locke.479.The purpose of those early essays of Berkeley was to reconcile philosophy with common sense, by employing reflection to makelatentcommon sense, or common reason, reveal itself in its genuine integrity. Cf. the closing sentences in theThird Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.480.Cf. Locke'sEssay, Introduction, sect. 4-7; Bk. II. ch. 23, § 12, &c. Locke (who is probably here in Berkeley's eye) attributes the perplexities of philosophy to our narrow faculties, which are meant to regulate our lives, not to remove all mysteries. See also Descartes,Principia, I. 26, 27, &c.; Malebranche,Recherche, III. 2.481.His most significant forerunners were Descartes in hisPrincipia, and Locke in hisEssay.482.Here“idea”and“notion”seem to be used convertibly. See sect. 142. Cf. with the argument againstabstract ideas, unfolded in the remainder of the Introduction,Principles, sect. 97-100, 118-132, 143;New Theory of Vision, sect. 122-125;Alciphron, Dial. vii. 5-7;Defence of Free Thinking in Mathematics, sect. 45-48. AlsoSiris, sect. 323, 335, &c., where he distinguishes Idea in a higher meaning from his sensuous ideas. As mentioned in my Preface, the third edition ofAlciphron, published in 1752, the year before Berkeley died, omits the three sections of the Seventh Dialogue which repeat the following argument against abstract ideas.483.As in Derodon'sLogica, Pt. II. c. 6, 7;Philosophia Contracta, I. i. §§ 7-11; and Gassendi,Leg. Instit., I. 8; also Cudworth,Eternal and Immutable Morality, Bk. IV.484.Omitted in second edition.485.We must remember that what Berkeley intends by anideais either a percept of sense, or a sensuous imagination; and his argument is that none ofthesecan be an abstraction. We can neither perceive nor imagine what is not concrete and part of a succession.486.“abstract notions”—here used convertibly with“abstract ideas.”Cf.Principles, sect. 89 and 142, on the special meaning ofnotion.487.Supposed by Berkeley to mean, that we can imagine, in abstraction from all phenomena presented in concrete experience, e.g. imagineexistence, in abstraction from all phenomena in which it manifests itself to us; ormatter, stripped of all the phenomena in which it is realised in sense.488.Omitted in second edition.489.Locke.490.Descartes, who regarded brutes as (sentient?) machines.491.“To this I cannot assent, being of opinion that a word,”&c.—in first edition.492.“an idea,”i.e. a concrete mental picture.493.So that“generality”in an idea is our“consideration”of a particular idea (e.g. a“particular motion”or a“particular extension”) notper se, but under general relations, which that particular idea exemplifies, and which, as he shews, may be signified by a corresponding word. All ideas (in Berkeley's confined meaning of“idea”) are particular. We rise above particular ideas by an intellectual apprehension of their relations; not by formingabstract pictures, which are contradictory absurdities.494.Locke is surely misconceived. He does not say, as Berkeley seems to suppose, that in forming“abstract ideas,”we are forming abstract mental images—pictures in the mind that are not individual pictures.495.Does Locke intend more than this, although he expresses his meaning in ambiguous words?496.It is a particular idea, but considered relatively—asignificantparticular idea, in other words. We realise our notions in examples, and these must be concrete.497.i.e.“ideas”in Locke's meaning of idea, under which he comprehends, not only the particular ideas of sense and imagination—Berkeley's“ideas”—but these considered relatively, and so seen intellectually, when Locke calls them abstract, general, or universal. Omniscience in its all-comprehensive intuition may not require, or even admit, such general ideas.498.Here and in what follows,“abstractnotion,”“universalnotion,”instead of abstractidea. Notion seems to be here a synonym for idea, and not taken in the special meaning which he afterwards attached to the term, when he contrasted it with idea.499.“notions,”again synonymous with ideas, which are all particular or concrete, in his meaning ofidea, when he uses it strictly.500.idea, i.e. individual mental picture.501.In all this he takes no account of the intellectual relations necessarily embodied in concrete knowledge, and without which experience could not cohere.502.“have in view,”i.e. actually realise in imagination.503.What follows, to the end of this section, was added in the second or 1734 edition.504.So Bacon in many passages of hisDe Augmentis ScientiariumandNovum Organum.505.“wide influence,”—“wide and extended sway”—in first edition.506.“idea,”i.e. individual datum of sense or of imagination.507.See Leibniz on Symbolical Knowledge (Opera Philosophica, pp. 79, 80, Erdmann), and Stewart in hisElements, vol. I. ch. 4, § 1, on our habit of using language without realising, in individual examples or ideas, the meanings of the common terms used.508.“doth”—“does,”here and elsewhere in first edition.509.“ideas,”i.e. representations in imagination ofanyof the individual objects to which the names are applicable. The sound or sight of a verbal sign may do duty for the concrete idea in which the notion signified by the word might be exemplified.510.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.511.Elsewhere he mentions Aristotle as“certainly a great admirer and promoter of the doctrine of abstraction,”and quotes his statement that there is hardly anything so incomprehensible to men as notions of the utmost universality; for they are the most remote from sense.Metaph., Bk. I. ch. 2.512.Added in second edition.513.Omitted in second edition.514.Omitted in second edition.515.Omitted in second edition.516.“my own ideas,”i.e. the concrete phenomena which I can realise as perceptions of sense, or in imagination.517.He probably refers to Locke.518.According to Locke,“that which has most contributed to hinder the due tracing of our ideas, and finding out their relations, and agreements or disagreements one with another, has been, I suppose, the ill use of words. It is impossible that men should ever truly seek, or certainly discover, the agreement or disagreement of ideas themselves, whilst their thoughts flutter about, or stick only in sounds of doubtful and uncertain significations. Mathematicians, abstracting their thoughts from names, and accustoming themselves to set before their minds the ideas themselves that they would consider, and not sounds instead of them, have avoided thereby a great part of that perplexity, puddering, and confusion which has so much hindered men's progress in other parts of knowledge.”Essay, Bk. IV. ch. 3, § 30. See also Bk. III. ch. 10, 11.519.General names involve in their signification intellectual relations among ideas or phenomena; but the relations,per se, are unimaginable.520.The rough draft of the Introduction, prepared two years before the publication of thePrinciples(see Appendix, vol. III), should be compared with the published version. He there tells that“there was a time when, being bantered and abused by words,”he“did not in the least doubt”that he was“able to abstract his ideas”; adding that“after a strict survey of my abilities, I not only discovered my own deficiency on this point, but also cannot conceive it possible that such a power should be even in the most perfect and exalted understanding.”What he thus pronounces“impossible,”is asensuousperception or imagination of an intellectual relation, as to which most thinkers would agree with him. But in so arguing, he seems apt to discard the intellectual relations themselves that are necessarily embodied in experience.David Hume refers thus to Berkeley's doctrine about“abstract ideas”:—“A great philosopher has asserted that all general ideas are nothing but particular ones annexed to a certain term, which gives them a more extensive signification. I look upon this to be one of the greatest and most valuable discoveries that has been made of late years in the republic of letters.”(Treatise of H. N.Pt. I, sect. 7.)521.This resembles Locke's account of the ideas with which human knowledge is concerned. They are all originally presented to the senses, or got by reflexion upon the passions and acts of the mind; and the materials contributed in this external and internal experience are, with the help of memory and imagination, elaborated by the human understanding in ways innumerable, true and false. See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II, ch. 1, §§ 1-5; ch. 10, 11, 12.522.The ideas or phenomena of which we are percipient in our five senses make their appearance, not isolated, but in individual masses, constituting the things, that occupy their respective places in perceived ambient space. It is asqualitiesofthingsthat the ideas or phenomena of sense arise in human experience.523.This is an advance upon the language of theCommonplace Book, in which“mind”is spoken of as only a“congeries of perceptions.”Here it is something“entirely distinct”from ideas or perceptions, in which they exist and are perceived, and on which they ultimately depend. Spirit, intelligent and active, presupposed with its implicates in ideas, thus becomes the basis of Berkeley's philosophy. Is this subjective idealism only? Locke appears in sect. 1, Descartes, if not Kant by anticipation, in sect. 2.524.This sentence expresses Berkeley's New Principle, which filled his thoughts in theCommonplace Book. Note“inamind,”not necessarily inmymind.525.That is to say, one has only to put concrete meaning into the termsexistenceandreality, in order to have“an intuitive knowledge”that matter depends for its real existence on percipient spirit.526.In other words, the things of sense become real, only in the concrete experience of living mind, which gives them the only reality we can conceive or have any sort of concern with. Extinguish Spirit and the material world necessarily ceases to be real.527.Thatesseispercipiis Berkeley's initial Principle, called“intuitive”or self-evident.528.Mark that it is the“natural or real existence”of the material world, in the absence of all realising Spirit, that Berkeley insists is impossible—meaningless.529.“our own”—yet not exclusivelymine. They depend for their reality uponapercipient, not onmyperception.530.“this tenet,”i.e. that the concrete material world could still be a reality after the annihilation of all realising spiritual life in the universe—divine or other.531.“existing unperceived,”i.e. existing without being realised in any living percipient experience—existing in a totally abstract existence, whatever that can mean.532.“notions”—a term elsewhere (see sect. 27, 89, 142) restricted, is here applied to the immediate data of the senses—the ideas of sense.533.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.534.In the first edition, instead of this sentence, we have the following:“To make this appear with all the light and evidence of an Axiom, it seems sufficient if I can but awaken the reflexion of the reader, that he may take an impartial view of his own meaning, and turn his thoughts upon the subject itself; free and disengaged from all embarras of words and prepossession in favour of received mistakes.”535.In other words, active percipient Spirit is at the root of all intelligible trustworthy experience.536.'proof'—“demonstration”in first edition; yet he calls it“intuitive.”537.“the ideas themselves,”i.e. the phenomena immediately presented in sense, and that are thus realised in and through the percipient experience of living mind, as their factor.538.As those say who assume that perception is ultimately only representative of the material reality, the very things themselves not making their appearance to us at all.539.He refers especially to Locke, whose account of Matter is accordingly charged with being incoherent.540.“inert.”See theDe Motu.541.“ideas existing in the mind,”i.e. phenomena of whichsomemind is percipient; which are realised in the sentient experience of a living spirit, human or other.542.What follows to the end of the section is omitted in the second edition.543.“the existence of Matter,”i.e. the existence of the material world, regarded as a something that does not need to be perceived in order to be real.544.Sometimes calledobjectivequalities, because they are supposed to be realised in an abstract objectivity, which Berkeley insists is meaningless.545.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II, ch. 8, §§ 13, 18; ch. 23, § 11; Bk. IV, ch. 3, § 24-26. Locke suggests this relation between the secondary and the primary qualities of matter only hypothetically.546.“in the mind, and nowhere else,”i.e. perceived or conceived, but in no other manner can they be real or concrete.547.“without the mind,”i.e. independently of all percipient experience.548.Extension is thus the distinguishing characteristic of the material world. Geometrical and physical solidity, as well as motion, imply extension.549.“number is the creature of the mind,”i.e. is dependent on being realised in percipient experience. This dependence is here illustrated by the relation of concrete number to the point of view of each mind; as the dependence of the other primary qualities was illustrated by their dependence on the organisation of the percipient. In this, the preceding, and the following sections, Berkeley argues the inconsistency of the abstract reality attributed to the primary qualities with their acknowledged dependence on the necessary conditions of sense perception.550.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 109.551.e.g. Locke,Essay, Bk. II, ch. 7, § 7; ch. 16, § 1.552.“without any alteration in any external object”—“without any external alteration”—in first edition.553.These arguments, founded on the mind-dependent nature ofallthe qualities of matter, are expanded in theFirst Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.554.“an outward object,”i.e. an object wholly abstract from living Mind.555.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.556.“reason,”i.e. reasoning. It is argued, in this and the next section, that a reality unrealised in percipient experience cannot be proved, either by our senses or by reasoning.557.Omitted in the second edition, and the sentence converted into a question.558.But the ideas of which we are cognizant in waking dreams, and dreams of sleep, differ in important characteristics from the external ideas of which we are percipient in sense. Cf. sect. 29-33.559.“external bodies,”i.e. bodies supposed to be real independently of all percipients in the universe.560.i.e. they cannot shew how their unintelligible hypothesis of Matter accounts for the experience we have, or expect to have; or which we believe other persons have, or to be about to have.561.“the production,”&c., i.e. the fact that we and others have percipient experience.562.Mind-dependent Matter he not only allows to exist, but maintains its reality to be intuitively evident.563.i.e. bodies existing in abstraction from living percipient spirit.564.“Matter,”i.e. abstract Matter, unrealised in sentient intelligence.565.The appeal here and elsewhere is to consciousness—directly in each person's experience, and indirectly in that of others.566.i.e. otherwise than in the form of an idea or actual appearance presented to our senses.567.This implies that the material world may be realised in imagination as well as in sensuous perception, but in a less degree of reality; for reality, he assumes, admits of degrees.568.“to conceive the existence of external bodies,”i.e. to conceive bodies that are not conceived—that are not ideas at all, but which exist in abstraction. To suppose what we conceive to be unconceived, is to suppose a contradiction.569.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.570.“The existence of things without mind,”or in the absence of all spiritual life and perception, is what Berkeley argues against, asmeaningless, if notcontradictory; not the existence of a material world, when this means the realised order of nature, regulated independently of individual will, and to which our actions must conform if we are to avoid physical pain.571.Here againnotionis undistinguished fromidea.572.This and the three following sections argue for the essential impotence of matter, and that, as far as we are concerned, so-called“natural causes”are onlysignswhich foretell the appearance of their so-called effects. The material world is presented to our senses as a procession of orderly, and therefore interpretable, yet in themselves powerless, ideas or phenomena: motion is always an effect, never an originating active cause.573.As Locke suggests.574.This tacitly presupposes the necessity in reason of the Principle of Causality, or the ultimate need for an efficient cause of every change. To determine the sort of Causation that constitutes and pervades the universe is the aim of his philosophy.575.In other words, the material world is not only real in and through percipient spirit, but the changing forms which its phenomena assume, in the natural evolution, are the issue of the perpetual activity of in-dwelling Spirit. The argument in this section requires a deeper criticism of its premisses.576.In other words, an agent cannot, as such, be perceived or imagined, though its effects can. The spiritual termagentis not meaningless; yet we have nosensuous ideaof its meaning.577.Omitted in second edition.578.This sentence is not contained in the first edition. It is remarkable for first introducing the termnotion, to signifyidealess meaning, as in the words soul, active power, &c. Here he says that“the operations of the mind”belong to notions, while, in sect. 1, he speaks of“ideasperceived by attending to the‘operations’of the mind.”579.“ideas,”i.e. fancies of imagination; as distinguished from the more real ideas or phenomena that present themselves objectively to our senses.580.With Berkeley the world of external ideas is distinguished from Spirit by its essential passivity. Active power is with him the essence of Mind, distinguishing me from the changing ideas of which I am percipient. We must not attribute free agency to phenomena presented to our senses.581.In this and the four following sections, Berkeley mentionsmarksby which the ideas or phenomena that present themselves to the senses may be distinguished from all other ideas, in consequence of which they may be termed“external,”while those of feeling and imagination are wholly subjective or individual.582.This mark—the superior strength and liveliness of the ideas or phenomena that are presented to the senses—was afterwards noted by Hume. SeeInquiry concerning Human Understanding, sect. II.583.Berkeley here and always insists on thearbitrarycharacter of“settled laws”of change in the world, as contrasted with“necessary connexions”discovered in mathematics. The material world is thus virtually an interpretable natural language, constituted in what, at our point of view, isarbitrarinessorcontingency.584.Under this conception of the universe,“second causes”aredivinely established signsof impending changes, and are only metaphorically called“causes.”585.So Schiller, inDon Carlos, Act III, where he represents sceptics as failing to see the God who veils Himself in everlasting laws. But in truth God is eternal law or order vitalised and moralised.586.“sensations,”with Berkeley, are not mere feelings, but in a sense external appearances.587.“morereality.”This implies that reality admits of degrees, and that the difference between the phenomena presented to the senses and those which are only imagined is a difference in degree of reality.588.In the preceding sections, two relations should be carefully distinguished—that of the material world to percipient mind, in which it becomesreal; and that between changes in the world and spiritual agency. These are Berkeley's two leading Principles. The first conducts to and vindicates the second—inadequately, however, apart from explication of their root in moral reason. The former gives a relationsui generis. The latter gives our only example of active causality—the natural order of phenomena being the outcome of the causal energy of intending Will.589.Sect. 34-84 contain Berkeley's answers to supposedobjectionsto the foregoing Principles concerning Matter and Spirit in their mutual relations.590.To be an“idea”is, with Berkeley, to be the imaginable object of a percipient spirit. But he does not define precisely the relation of ideas to mind.“Existence in mind”is existencein this relation. His question (which he determines in the negative) is, the possibility of concrete phenomena, naturally presented to sense,yet out of all relation to living mind.591.Omitted in second edition.592.i.e. of imagination. Cf. sect. 28-30.593.Cf. sect. 29.594.“more reality.”This again implies that reality admits of degrees. What is perceived in sense is more real than what is imagined, and eternal realities are more deeply real than the transitory things of sense.595.Cf. sect. 33.“Not fictions,”i.e. they are presentative, and therefore cannot misrepresent.596.With Berkeleysubstanceis either (a) active reason, i.e. spirit—substance proper, or (b) an aggregate of sense-phenomena, called a“sensible thing”—substance conventionally and superficially.597.And which, because realised in living perception, are calledideas—to remind us that reality is attained in and through percipient mind.598.“combined together,”i.e. in the form of“sensible things,”according to natural laws. Cf. sect. 33.599.“thinking things”—more appropriately calledpersons.600.Berkeley uses the word idea to mark the fact, that sensible things are real only as they manifest themselves in the form of passive objects, presented to sense-percipient mind; but he does not, as popularly supposed, regard“sensible things”as created and regulated by the activity of his own individual mind. They are perceived, but are neither created nor regulated, by the individual percipient, and are thuspractically externalto each person.601.Cf. sect. 87-91, against the scepticism which originates in alleged fallacy of sense.602.Omitted in second edition.603.It is always to be remembered that with Berkeley ideas or phenomena presented to sense arethemselvesthe real things, whilst ideas of imagination are representative (or misrepresentative).604.Here feelings of pleasure or pain are spoken of, without qualification, as in like relation to living mind as sensible things or ideas are.605.That the ideas of sense should be seen“at a distance of several miles”seems not inconsistent with their being dependent on a percipient, if ambient space isitself(as Berkeley asserts) dependent on percipient experience. Cf. sect. 67.606.In the preceding year.607.Essay, sect. 2.608.Ibid. sect. 11-15.609.Ibid. sect. 16-28.610.Ibid. sect. 51.611.Ibid. sect. 47-49, 121-141.612.Ibid. sect. 43.613.i.e. what we areimmediatelypercipient of in seeing.614.Touch is here and elsewhere taken in its wide meaning, and includes our muscular and locomotive experience, all which Berkeley included in the“tactual”meaning of distance.615.To explain the condition of sensible thingsduring the intervals of our perception of them, consistently with the belief of all sane persons regarding the material world, is a challenge which has been often addressed to the advocates of ideal Realism. According to Berkeley, there are no intervals in the existence of sensible things. They are permanently perceivable, under the laws of nature, though not always perceived by this, that or the other individual percipient. Moreover they always existreallyin the Divine Idea, andpotentially, in relation to finite minds, in the Divine Will.616.Berkeley allows to bodies unperceived by me potential, but (for me) not real existence. When I say a body exists thus conditionally, I mean that if, in the light, I open my eyes, I shall see it, and that if I move my hand, I must feel it.617.i.e. unperceived material substance.618.Berkeley remarks, in a letter to the American Samuel Johnson, that“those who have contended for a material world have yet acknowledged thatnatura naturans(to use the language of the Schoolmen) is God; and that the Divine conservation of things is equipollent to, and in fact the same thing with, a continued repeated creation;—in a word, that conservation and creation differ only as theterminus a quo. These are the common opinions of Schoolmen; and Durandus, who held the world to be a machine, like a clock made up and put in motion by God, but afterwards continued to go of itself, was therein particular, and had few followers. The very poets teach a doctrine not unlike the Schools—mens agitat molem(Virgil, Æneid, VI). The Stoics and Platonists are everywhere full of the same notion. I am not therefore singular in this point itself, so much as in my way of proving it.”Cf.Alciphron, Dial. IV. sect. 14;Vindication of New Theory of Vision, sect. 8, 17, &c.;Siris,passim, but especially in the latter part. See alsoCorrespondence between Clarke and Leibniz(1717). Is it not possible that the universe of things and persons is in continuous natural creation, unbeginning and unending?619.Cf. sect. 123-132.620.He distinguishes“idea”from“mode or attribute.”With Berkeley, the“substance”ofmatter(if the term is still to be applied to sensible things) is the naturally constituted aggregate of phenomena of which each particular thing consists. Now extension, and the other qualities of sensible things, are not, Berkeley argues,“in mind”either (a) according to the abstract relation of substance and attribute of which philosophers speak; nor (b) as one idea or phenomenon is related to another idea or phenomenon, in the natural aggregation of sense-phenomena which constitute, with him, thesubstanceof amaterialthing. Mind and its“ideas”are, on the contrary, related as percipient to perceived—in whatever“otherness”that altogethersui generisrelation implies.621.“Matter,”i.e. abstract material Substance, as distinguished from the concrete things that are realised in living perceptions.622.“take away natural causes,”i.e. empty the material world of all originative power, and refer the supposed powers of bodies to the constant and omnipresent agency of God.623.Some philosophers have treated the relation of Matter to Mind inperceptionas one of cause and effect. This, according to Berkeley, is an illegitimate analysis, which creates a fictitious duality. On his New Principles, philosophy is based on a recognition of the fact, that perception is neither the cause nor the effect of its object, but in a relation to it that is altogethersui generis.624.He refers to Descartes, and perhaps Geulinx and Malebranche, who, while they argued for materialsubstance, denied thecausal efficiencyof sensible things. Berkeley's new Principles are presented as the foundation in reason for this denial, and for the essential spirituality of all active power in the universe.625.On the principle,“Entia non sunt multiplicanda præter necessitatem.”626.“external things,”i.e. things in the abstract.627.That the unreflecting part of mankind should have a confused conception of what should be meant by theexternal realityof matter is not wonderful. It is the office of philosophy to improve their conception, making it deeper and truer, and this was Berkeley's preliminary task; as a mean for shewing the impotence of the things of sense, and conclusive evidence of omnipresent spiritual activity.628.Cf. sect. 4, 9, 15, 17, 22, 24.629.i.e. theirsense-ideas.—Though sense-ideas, i.e. the appearances presented to the senses, are independent of thewillof the individual percipient, it does not follow that they are independent ofall perception, so that they can be real in the absence of realising percipient experience. Cf. sect. 29-33.630.By shewing that what we are percipient of in sense must beidea, or that it is immediately known by us only as sensuous appearance.631.i.e.“imprinted”by unperceived Matter, which, on this dogma of a representative sense-perception, was assumed to exist behind the perceived ideas, and to be thecauseof their appearance. Cf.Third Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.632.Hence the difficulty men have in recognising that Divine Reason and Will, and Law in Nature, are coincident. But the advance of scientific discovery of the laws which express Divine Will in nature, instead of narrowing, extends our knowledge of God. Anddivineorabsolutely reasonable“arbitrariness”is not caprice.633.“ideas,”i.e. ideas ofsense. This“experience”implied an association of sensuous ideas, according to the divine or reasonable order of nature.634.Cf. sect. 25-33, and other passages in Berkeley's writings in which he insists upon thearbitrariness—divine or reasonable—of the natural laws and sense-symbolism.635.Cf. sect. 3, 4, 6, 22-24, 26, in which he proceeds upon the intuitive certainty of his two leading Principles, concerningRealityandCausation.636.In short, what is virtually the language of universal natural order is the divine way of revealing omnipresent Intelligence; nor can we conceive how this revelation could be made through a capricious or chaotic succession of changes.637.He here touches on moral purpose in miraculous phenomena, but without discussing their relation to the divine, or perfectly reasonable, order of the universe. Relatively to a fine knowledge of nature, they seem anomalous—exceptions from general rules, which nevertheless express, immediately and constantly, perfect active Reason.638.“ideas,”i.e. the phenomena presented to the senses.639.“imaginable”—in first edition.640.“the connexion of ideas,”i.e. the presence of law or reasonable uniformity in the coexistence and succession of the phenomena of sense; which makes them interpretable signs.641.According to Berkeley, it is by an abuse of language that the term“power”is applied to those ideas which are invariable antecedents of other ideas—the prior forms of their existence, as it were.642.Berkeley, in meeting this objection, thus implies Universal Natural Symbolism as the essential character of the sensible world, in its relation to man.643.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. IV, ch. 3, § 25-28, &c., in which he suggests that the secondary qualities of bodies may be the natural issue of the different relations and modifications of their primary qualities.644.With Berkeley,material substanceis merely the natural combination of sense-presented phenomena, which, under adivineorreasonable“arbitrariness,”constitute a concrete thing. Divine Will, or Active Reason, is the constantly sustaining cause of this combination or substantiation.645.i.e. that it is not realised in a living percipient experience.646.For“place”is realised only as perceived—percipient experience being its concrete existence. Living perception is, with Berkeley, the condition of the possibility of concrete locality.647.So in the Cartesian theory of occasional causes.648.So Geulinx and Malebranche.649.As known in Divine intelligence, they are accordinglyDivine Ideas. And, if this means that the sensible system is the expression of Divine Ideas, which are its ultimate archetype—that the Ideas of God are symbolised to our senses, and then interpreted (or misinterpreted) by human minds, this allies itself with Platonic Idealism.650.“It seems to me,”Hume says,“that this theory of the universal energy and operation of the Supreme Being istoo boldever to carry conviction with it to a mind sufficiently apprised of the weakness of human reason, and the narrow limits to which it is confined in all its operations.”But is it not virtually presupposed in the assumed trustworthiness of our experience of the universe?651.Accordingly we are led to ask, what the deepest support of their reality must be. Is it found in living Spirit, i.e. Active Reason, or in blind Matter?652.e.g. Descartes, Malebranche, Locke, &c.653.In short, if we mean by Matter, something unrealised in percipient experience of sense, what is called itsrealityis something unintelligible.654.And if sensible phenomena aresufficientlyexternalised, when regarded as regulated by Divine Reason.655.Twenty years after the publication of thePrinciples, in a letter to his American friend Johnson, Berkeley says:—“I have no objection against calling the Ideas in the mind of Godarchetypesof ours. But I object against those archetypes by philosophers supposed to be real things, and so to have an absolute rational existence distinct from their being perceived by any mind whatsoever; it being the opinion of all materialists that an ideal existence in the Divine Mind is one thing, and the real existence of material things another.”656.Berkeley's philosophy is not inconsistent with Divine Ideas which receive expression in the laws of nature, and of which human science is the imperfect interpretation. In this view, assertion of the existence of Matter is simply an expression of faith that the phenomenal universe into which we are born is a reasonable and interpretable universe; and that it would be fully interpreted, if our notions could be fully harmonised with the Divine Ideas which it expresses.657.Cf. sect. 3-24.658.So that superhuman persons, endowed with a million senses, would be no nearer this abstract Matter than man is, with his few senses.659.Matter and physical science isrelative, so far that we may suppose in other percipients than men, an indefinite number of additional senses, affording corresponding varieties of qualities in things, of course inconceivable by man. Or, we may suppose an intelligence destitute ofall oursenses, and so in a material world wholly different in its appearances from ours.660.The authority of Holy Scripture, added to our natural tendency to believe in external reality, are grounds on which Malebranche and Norris infer a material world. Berkeley's material world claims no logical proof of its reality. His is not to prove the reality of the world, but to shew what we should mean when we affirm its reality, and the basis of its explicability in science.661.i.e. existing unrealised in any intelligence—human or Divine.662.“external things,”i.e. things existing really, yet out of all relation to active living spirit.663.Simultaneous perception of the“same”(similar?)sense-ideas,by different persons, as distinguished from purely individual consciousness of feelings and fancies, is here taken as a test of thevirtually external realityof the former.Berkeley does not ask whether the change of the rod into a serpent, or of the water into wine, is the issue of divine agency and order, otherwise than as all natural evolution is divinely providential.664.Some of the Consequences of adoption of the New Principles, in their application to the physical sciences and mathematics, and then to psychology and theology, are unfolded in the remaining sections of thePrinciples.665.Berkeley disclaims the supposedrepresentativecharacter of the ideas given in sensuous perception, and recognises as the real object only what is ideally presented in consciousness.666.So Hume, Reid, and Hamilton, who all see in a wholly representative sense-perception, with its double object, the germ of total scepticism. Berkeley claims that, underhisinterpretation of what the reality of the material world means, immediate knowledge of mind-dependent matter is given in sense.667.“scepticism”—“sceptical cant”in the first edition.668.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.669.Berkeley's argument against afinally representativeperception so far resembles that afterwards employed by Reid and Hamilton. They differ as regards the dependence of the sensible object upon percipient spirit for its reality.670.Omitted in second edition.671.Omitted in second edition.672.But whilst unthinking things depend on being perceived, do not our spirits depend on ideas of some sort for their percipient life?673.The important passage within brackets was added in the second edition.674.“reason,”i.e. reasoning.675.“Notion,”in its stricter meaning, is thus confined by Berkeley to apprehension of theEgo, and intelligence ofrelations. The term“notion,”in this contrast withhis“idea,”becomes important in his vocabulary, although he sometimes uses it vaguely.676.Locke usesideain this wider signification.677.Inasmuch as they arerealin and through living percipient mind.678.i.e.unthinkingarchetypes.679.In this section Berkeley explains what he means byexternality. Men cannot act, cannot live, without assuming an external world—in some meaning of the term“external.”It is the business of the philosopher to explicate its true meaning.680.i.e. they are notsubstancesin the truest or deepest meaning of the word.681.“Ideas of the corporeal substances.”Berkeley might perhaps say—Divine Ideas which arethemselvesour world of sensible things in its ultimate form.682.On the scheme of ideal Realism,“creation”of matter is presenting to finite minds sense-ideas or phenomena, which are, as it were, letters of the alphabet, in that language of natural order which God employs for the expression ofHisIdeas to us.683.Theindependenteternity of Matter must be distinguished from an unbeginning and endlesscreationof sensible ideas or phenomena, in percipient spirits, according to divine natural law and order, with implied immanence of God.684.Because the question at issue with Atheism is, whether the universe of things and persons is finally substantiated and evolved in unthinking Matter or in the perfect Reason of God.685.Of which Berkeley doesnotpredicate anumericalidentity. Cf.Third Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.686.“matter,”i.e. matter abstracted from all percipient life and voluntary activity.687.“external”—not in Berkeley's meaning of externality. Cf. sect. 90, note 2.688.Si non rogas, intelligo.Berkeley writes long after this to Johnson thus:—“A succession of ideas (phenomena) I take toconstitutetime, and not to be only the sensible measure thereof, as Mr. Locke and others think. But in these matters every man is to think for himself, and speak as he finds. One of my earliest inquiries was abouttime; which led me into several paradoxes that I did not think it fit or necessary to publish, particularly into the notion that the resurrection follows the next moment after death. We are confounded and perplexed about time—supposing a succession in God; that we have an abstract idea of time; that time in one mind is to be measured by succession of ideas in another mind: not considering the true use of words, which as often terminate in the will as in the understanding, being employed to excite and direct action rather than to produce clear and distinct ideas.”Cf. Introduction, sect. 20.689.As theesseof unthinking things ispercipi, according to Berkeley, so theesseof persons ispercipere. The real existence of individual Mind thus depends on having ideas of some sort: the real existence of matter depends on a percipient.690.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.691.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 43.692.“objects of sense,”i.e. sensible things, practically external to each person. Cf. sect. 1, on the meaning ofthing, as distinct from the distinguishable ideas or phenomena that are naturally aggregated in the form of concrete things.693.Omitted in second edition.694.Omitted in second edition.695.Cf. Introduction, sect. 1-3. With Berkeley, the real essence of sensible things is given in perception—so far as our perceptions carry us.696.e.g. Locke'sEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 3.697.Berkeley advocates a Realism, which eliminates effective causation from the material world, concentrates it in Mind, and in physical research seeks among data of sense for their divinely maintained natural laws.698.In interpreting the data of sense, we are obliged to assume that everynewphenomenon must have previously existed in some equivalent form—but not necessarily in this or that particular form, for a knowledge of which we are indebted to inductive comparisons of experience.699.The preceding forms of new phenomena, being finally determined by Will, are, in that sense, arbitrary; but not capricious, for the Will is perfect Reason. God is the immanent cause of the natural order.700.He probably refers to Bacon.701.Omitted in second edition.702.What we are able to discover in the all-comprehensive order may be subordinate and provisional only. Nature in its deepest meaning explains itself in the Divine Omniscience.703.i.e. inductively.704.i.e. deductively.705.“seem to consider signs,”i.e. to be grammarians rather than philosophers: physical sciences deal with the grammar of the divine language of nature.706.“A man may be well read in the language of nature without understanding the grammar of it, or being able to say,”&c.—in first edition.707.“extend”—“stretch”—in first edition.708.Omitted in second edition.709.In the first edition, the section commences thus:“The best grammar of the kind we are speaking of will be easily acknowledged to be a treatise ofMechanics, demonstrated and applied to Nature, by a philosopher of a neighbouring nation, whom all the world admire. I shall not take upon me to make remarks on the performance of that extraordinary person: only some things he has advanced so directly opposite to the doctrine we have hitherto laid down, that we should be wanting in the regard due to the authority of so great a man did we not take some notice of them.”He refers, of course, to Newton. The first edition of Berkeley'sPrincipleswas published in Ireland—hence“neighbouring nation.”Newton'sPrincipiaappeared in 1687.710.“Motion,”in various aspects, is treated specially in theDe Motu. An imagination of trinal space presupposes locomotive experience—unimpeded, in contrast with—impeded locomotion. Cf. sect. 116.711.Omitted in second edition.712.Added in second edition.713.Omitted in second edition.714.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 13, §§ 7-10.715.“applied to”—“impressed on”—in first edition.716.“applied to”—“impressed on”—in first edition.717.“theforcecausing the change”—which“force,”according to Berkeley, can only be attributed metaphorically to the so-called impelling body; inasmuch asbodies, or the data of sense, can only be signs of their consequent events, not efficient causes of change.718.Added in second edition.719.What follows to the end of this section is omitted in the second edition.720.“seems impossible”—“is above my capacity”—in first edition.721.In short, empty Spaceisthe sensuous idea of unresisted motion. This is implied in theNew Theory of Vision. He minimises Space, treating it as a datum of sense.722.He probably refers to Samuel Clarke'sDemonstration of the Being and Attributes of God, which appeared in 1706, and a treatiseDe Spatio Reali, published in the same year.723.Sect. 118-132 are accordingly concerned with the New Principles in their application to Mathematics. The foundation of the mathematical sciences engaged much of Berkeley's thought in early life and in his later years. See hisAnalyst.724.Numerical relations arerealisedonly in concrete experience.725.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 107, &c.726.Ibid. sect. 122-125, 149-160.727.An infinitely divided extension, being unperceived, must be unreal—if its existence is made real only in and through actual perception, or at least imagination. The only possible extension is, accordingly, sensible extension, which could not be infinitely divided without the supposed parts ceasing to be perceived or real.728.“converted Gentile”—“pagan convert”—in first edition.729.Cf. Locke'sEssay, Bk. I, ch. 3, § 25.730.“will perhaps in virtue thereof be brought to admit,”&c.—“will not stick to affirm,”&c.—in first edition.731.Omitted in second edition. See theAnalyst.732.“we must mean”—“we mean (if we mean anything)”—in first edition.733.Omitted in the second edition.734.Does this refer to the intended“Part II”of thePrinciples?735.“men of great abilities and obstinate application,”&c.—“men of the greatest abilities and most obstinate application,”&c.—in first edition.736.What follows to the end of this section is omitted in the second edition.737.“absolute,”i.e. abstract, independent, irrelative existence—as something of which there can be no sensuous perception or conception.738.Matter unrealised in perception—not the material world that is realised in percipient experience of sense.739.Omitted in second edition.740.Sect. 135-156 treat of consequences of the New Principles, in their application to sciences concerned with our notions ofSpiritorMind; as distinguished from sciences of ideas in external Nature, and their mathematical relations. Individual mind, with Berkeley, needs data of sense in order to its realisation in consciousness; while it is dependent on God, in a relation which he does not define distinctly.741.e.g. Locke suggests this.742.Is this analogy applicable?743.Omitted in second edition, as he had previously learned to distinguishnotionfromidea. Cf. sect. 89, 142.744.Ibid. In the omitted passage it will be seen that he makesideaandnotionsynonymous.745.Is the reality of mind as dependent on having ideas (of some sort) as ideas are on mind; although mind is more deeply and truly real than its ideas are?746.Introduced in second edition.747.We knowother finite personsthrough sense-presented phenomena, but not as themselves phenomena. Cf. sect. 145. It is a mediate knowledge that we have of other persons. The question about the individuality of finite egos, as distinguished from God, Berkeley has not touched.748.These sentences are omitted in the second edition.749.“the soul,”i.e. the individual Ego.750.Cf. sect. 2; 25-27.751.This is Berkeley's application of his new conception of the reality of matter, to the final human question of the self-conscious existence of the individual human Ego, after physical death. Philosophers and theologians were accustomed in his generation to ground their argument for a future life on the metaphysical assumption of the physical indivisibility of our self-conscious spirit, and on our contingent connexion with the body.“Our bodies,”says Bishop Butler,“are no moreourselves, orpart of ourselves, than any other matter around us.”This train of thought is foreign to us at the present day, when men of science remind us that self-conscious life is found only in correlation with corporeal organisation, whatever may be the abstract possibility. Hope of continued life after physical death seems to depend on ethical considerations more than on metaphysical arguments, and on what is suggested by faith in the final outcome of personal life in adivinelyconstituted universe.752.Mind and the ideas presented to the senses are at opposite poles of existence. But he does not say that, thus opposed, they are each independent of the other.753.What follows was introduced in the second edition, in whichnotionis contrasted withidea.754.Here is a germ of Kantism. But Berkeley has not analysed that activity of mind which constitutesrelation, nor systematically unfolded the relations involved in the rational constitution of experience. There is more disposition to this inSiris.755.As with Locke, for example.756.Note this condemnation of the tendency to substantiate“powers of mind.”757.Omitted in second edition. Berkeley was after all reluctant to“depart from received modes of speech,”notwithstanding their often misleading associations.758.Omitted in second edition.759.This is one of the notable sections in thePrinciples, as it suggests therationaleof Berkeley's rejection of Panegoism or Solipsism. Is this consistent with his conception of the reality of the material world? It is objected (e.g. by Reid) that ideal realism dissolves our faith in the existence of other persons. The difficulty is to shew how appearances presented to my senses, which are sensuous and subjective, can be media of communication between persons. The question carries us back to the theistic presupposition in the trustworthiness of experience—which is adapted to deceive if I am the only person existing. With Berkeley a chief function of ideas of sense is to signify other persons to each person. SeeAlciphron, Dial. IV;New Theory of Vision Vindicated, andSiris.760.“repugnant”—for it would involve thought in incoherence, by paralysis of its indispensable causal presupposition.761.Is not God the indispensable presupposition of trustworthy experience, rather than an empirical inference?762.This suggests an explanation of the objective reality and significance ofideas of sense; through which they become media of social intercourse in the fundamentally divine universe. God so regulates the sense-given ideas of which human beings are individually percipient, as that,while numerically different, as in each mind, those ideas are nevertheless a sufficient medium for social intercourse, if the Power universally at work is morally trustworthy. Unless our God-given experience is deceiving, Solipsism is not a necessary result of the fact that no one but myself can be percipient of my sensuous experience.763.Omitted in second edition.764.Malebranche, as understood by Berkeley. SeeRecherche, Liv. III. p. ii. ch. 6, &c.765.For all finite personssomehowlive, and move, and have their being“in God.”The existence ofeternalliving Mind, and thepresentexistence of other men, are bothinferences, resting on the same foundation, according to Berkeley.766.The theistic trust in which our experience is rooted remaining latent, or being unintelligent.767.Cf. sect. 25-28, 51-53, 60-66. His conception of Divine causation in Nature, as the constant omnipresent agency in all natural law, is the deepest part of his philosophy. It is pursued in theDe Motu.768.Is not the unbeginning and unending natural evolution, an articulate revelation of Eternal Spirit or Active Reason at the heart of the whole?769.Omitted in second edition.770.So Pascal in thePensées.771.Divine reason ever active in Nature is the necessary correlate to reason in man; inasmuch as otherwise the changing universe in which we live would be unfit to be reasoned about or acted in.772.The existence ofmoralevil, or what ought not to exist, isthedifficulty which besets faith in the fundamental divinity or goodness of the universe. Yet that faith is presupposed in interpretation of nature, which proceeds on thepostulateof universal order; and this implies the moral trustworthiness of the world which we begin to realise when we begin to be conscious. That we are living and having our being in omnipotent goodness is thus not an inference, but the implied basis of all real inferences. I have expanded this thought in myPhilosophy of Theism. We cannotproveGod, for we must assume God, as the basis of all proof. Faith even in the uniformity of nature is virtually faith in omnipotent goodness immanent in the universe.773.So Leibniz in hisTheodicée, which was published in the same year as Berkeley'sPrinciples.774.The divine presupposition, latent in all human reasoning and experience, is hid from the unreflecting, in whom the higher life is dormant, and the ideal in the universe is accordingly undiscerned. Unless the universe is assumed to be physically and morally trustworthy, i.e. unless God is presupposed, even natural science has no adequate foundation.775.Our necessarily incomplete knowledge of the Universe in which we find ourselves is apt to disturb the fundamental faith, that the phenomena presented to us are significant of God. Yet wetacitly assumethat they are thus significant when we interpret real experience, physical or moral.776.Omitted in second edition.777.For the following extracts from previously unpublished correspondence of Berkeley and Sir John Percival, I am indebted to the kindness of his descendant, the late Lord Egmont.778.What Berkeley seeks to shew is, not that the world of the senses is unreal, but in what its reality consists. Is it inexplicable chaos, or explicable expression of ever active Intelligence, more or less interpreted in natural science?779.Leibniz:De modo distinguendi Phenomena Realia ab Imaginariis(1707).780.For some information relative to Gua de Malves, see Querard'sLa France Littéraire,tom. iii. p. 494.781.The following is the translator's Prefatory Note, on the objects of theDialogues,and in explanation of the three illustrative vignettes:—“L'Auteur expose dans le premier Dialogue le sentiment du Vulgaire et celui des Philosophes, sur les qualités secondaires et premieres, la nature et l'existence des corps; et il prétend prouver en même tems l'insuffisance de l'un et de l'autre. La Vignette qu'on voit à la téte du Dialogue, fait allusion à cet objet. Elle représente un Philosophe dans son cabinet, lequel est distrait de son travail par un enfant qu'il appercoit se voyant lui-méme dans un miroir, en tendant les mains pour embrasser sa propre image. Le Philosophe rit de l'erreur où il croit que tombe l'enfant; tandis qu'on lui applique à lui-même ces mots tirés d'Horace:Quid rides?....de teFabula narratur.“Le second Dialogue est employé à exposer le sentiment de l'Auteur sur le même sujet, sçavoir, que les choses corporelles ont une existence réelle dans les esprits qui les apperçoivent; mais qu'elles ne sçauroient exister hors de tous les esprits à la fois, même de l'esprit infini de Dieu; et que par conséquent la Matière, prise suivant l'acception ordinaire du mot, non seulement n'existe point, mais seroit même absolument impossible. On a taché de représenter aux yeux ce sentiment dans la Vignette du Dialogue. Le mot grec νοῦς qui signifieâme, désigne l'àme: les rayons qui en partent marquent l'attention que l'âme donne à des idées ou objets; les tableaux qu'on a placés aux seuls endroits où les rayons aboutissent, et dont les sujets sont tirés de la description des beautés de la nature, qui se trouve dans le livre, représentent les idées ou objets que l'âme considère, pas le secours des facultes qu'elle a reçues de Dieu; et l'action de l'Étre suprème sur l'âme est figurée par un trait, qui, partant d'un triangle, symbole de la Divinité, et perçant les nuages dont le triangle est environné. s'étend jusqu'à l'âme pour la vivifier; enfin, on a fait en sorte de rendre le même sentiment par ces mots:Quæ noscere cumque Deus det,Esse puta.“L'objet du troisième Dialogue est de répondre aux difficultés auxquelles le sentiment qu'on a établi dans les Dialogues précédens, peut être sujet, de l'éclaircir en cette sorte de plus, d'en développer toutes les heureuses conséquences, enfin de faire voir, qu'étant bien entendu, il revient aux notions les plus communes. Et comme l'Auteur exprime à la fin du livre cette dernière pensée, en comparant ce qu'il vient de dire, à l'eau que les deux Interlocuteurs sont supposés voir jaillir d'un jet, et qu'il remarque que la même force de la gravité fait élever jusqu'à une certaine hauteur et retomber ensuite dans le bassin d'où elle étoit d'abord partie; on a pris cet emblême pour le sujet de la Vignette de ce Dialogue; on a représenté en conséquence dans cette dernière Vignette les deux Interlocuteurs, se promenant dans le lieu où l'Auteur les suppose, et s'entretenant là-dessus, et pour donner au Lecteur l'explication de l'emblême, on a mis au bas le vers suivant:Urget aquas vis sursum, eadem flectitque deorsum.”782.Collier never came fairly in sight of the philosophical public of last century. He is referred to in Germany by Bilfinger, in hisDilucidationes Philosophicæ(1746), and also in theAda Eruditorum, Suppl. VI. 244, &c., and in England by Corry in hisReflections on Liberty and Necessity(1761), as well as in theRemarkson the Reflections, andAnswersto the Remarks, pp. 7, 8 (1763), where he is described as“a weak reasoner, and a very dull writer also.”Collier was dragged from his obscurity by Dr. Reid, in hisEssays on the Intellectual Powers, Essay II. ch. 10. He was a subject of correspondence between Sir James Mackintosh, then at Bombay, and Dr. Parr, and an object of curiosity to Dugald Stewart. A beautiful reprint of theClavis(of the original edition of which only seven copies were then known to exist) appeared in Edinburgh in 1836; and in the following year it was included in a collection ofMetaphysical Tracts by English Philosophers of the Eighteenth Century, prepared for the press by Dr. Parr.783.William, fourth Lord Berkeley of Stratton, born about 1663, succeeded his brother in 1697, and died in 1741 at Bruton in Somersetshire. The Berkeleys of Stratton were descended from a younger son of Maurice, Lord Berkeley of Berkeley Castle, who died in 1326. His descendant, Sir John Berkeley of Bruton, a zealous Royalist, was created first Lord Berkeley of Stratton in 1658, and in 1669 became Lord Lieutenant of Ireland, an office which he held till 1672, when he was succeeded by the Earl of Essex (see Burke'sExtinct Peerages). It is said that Bishop Berkeley's father was related to him. The Bishop himself was introduced by Dean Swift, in 1713, to the Lord Berkeley of Stratton, to whom theDialoguesare dedicated, as“a cousin of his Lordship.”The title of Berkeley of Stratton became extinct on the death of the fifth Lord in 1773.784.This interesting Preface is omitted in his last edition of theDialogues.785.The Second Part of thePrincipleswas never published, and only in part written. See Editor's Preface to thePrinciples.786.Principles, Introduction, sect. 1.787.Berkeley's philosophy is professedly a“revolt”from abstract ideas to an enlightened sense of concrete realities. In these DialoguesPhilonouspersonates the revolt, and represents Berkeley.Hylasvindicates the uncritical conception of independent Matter.788.Berkeley's zeal against Matter in the abstract, and all abstract ideas of concrete things, is therefore not necessarily directed against“universal intellectual notions”—“the principles and theorems of sciences.”789.Here“reason”means reasoning or inference. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 42, including the distinction between“suggestion”and“inference.”790.“figure”as well as colour, is here included among the original data of sight.791.“without the mind,”i.e. unrealised by any percipient mind.792.Cf.Principles, sect. 14.793.Cf.Principles, sect. 14, 15.794.“Sensible qualities,”i.e. the significant appearances presented in sense.795.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 80-86.796.Descartes and Locke for example.797.On Primary and Secondary Qualities of Matter, and their mutual relations, cf.Principles, sect. 9-15. See also Descartes,Meditations, III,Principia, I. sect. 69; Malebranche,Recherche, Liv. VI. Pt. II. sect. 2; Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 8.798.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 80.799.What follows, within brackets, is not contained in the first and second editions.800.Percipient mind is, in short, the indispensable realising factor ofallthe qualities of sensible things.801.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 122-126;Principles, sect. 123, &c.;Siris, sect. 270, &c.802.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 15.803.Is“notion”here a synonym for idea?804.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 16.805.“Size or figure, or sensible quality”—“size, color &c.,”in the first and second editions.806.In Berkeley's later and more exact terminology, the data or implicates of pure intellect are callednotions, in contrast to hisideas, which are concrete or individual sensuous presentations.807.They need living percipient mind to make them real.808.So Reid'sInquiry, ch. ii, sect. 8, 9;Essays on the Intellectual Powers, II. ch. 16. Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 8, &c.809.i.e. figured or extended visible colour. Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 43, &c.810.Cf.Principles, sect. 25, 26.811.After maintaining, in the preceding part of this Dialogue, the inevitable dependence of all the qualities of Matter upon percipient Spirit, the argument now proceeds to dispose of the supposition that Matter may still be an unmanifested or unqualifiedsubstratum, independent of living percipient Spirit.812.[See theEssay towards a New Theory of Vision, and itsVindication.] Note by theAuthorin the 1734 edition.813.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 2.814.Cf. Ibid., sect. 43.815.“an idea,”i.e. a phenomenon present to our senses.816.This was Reid's fundamental question in his criticism of Berkeley.817.Cf.Principles, sect. 8.818.Cf.Principles, sect. 25, 26.819.In other words, the percipient activity of a living spirit is the necessary condition of the real existence of all ideas or phenomena immediately present to our senses.820.An“explanation”afterwards elaborately developed by Hartley, in hisObservations on Man(1749). Berkeley has probably Hobbes in view.821.The brain with the human body in which it is included constitutes a part of the material world, and must equally with the rest of the material world depend for its realisation upon percipient Spirit as the realising factor.822.Cf.Principles, sect. 23.823.“in stones and minerals”—in first and second editions.824.Cf.Principles, sect. 29-33; also sect. 90.—Thepermanenceof a thing, during intervals in which it may be unperceived and unimagined by human beings, is here assumed, as a natural conviction.825.In other words, men are apt to treat the omniscience of God as an inference from the dogmatic assumption that God exists, instead of seeing that our cosmic experience necessarily presupposes omnipotent and omniscient Intelligence at its root.826.Cf.Principles, sect. 90. A permanent material world is grounded on Divine Mind, because it cannot but depend on Mind, while its reality is only partially and at intervals sustained by finite minds.827.“necessarily inferred from”—rather necessarily presupposed in.828.The present reality of Something implies the eternal existence of living Mind, if Somethingmustexist eternally, and if real or concrete existence involves living Mind. Berkeley's conception of material nature presupposes a theistic basis.829.He refers of course to Malebranche and his Divine Vision.830.But Malebranche usesideain a higher meaning than Berkeley does—akin to the Platonic, and in contrast to the sensuous phenomena which Berkeley calls ideas.831.The passage within brackets first appeared in the third edition.832.Cf.Principles, sect. 25-33.833.Cf. Ibid., sect. 3-24.834.Icanrepresent to myself another mind perceiving and conceiving things; because I have an example of this my own conscious life. Icannotrepresent to myself sensible things existing totally unperceived and unimagined; because I cannot, without a contradiction, have an example of this in my own experience.835.“reason,”i.e. by reasoning.836.Berkeley'smaterial substanceis a natural or divinely ordered aggregate of sensible qualities or phenomena.837.Inasmuch as, according to Berkeley, it must be a living Spirit, and it would be an abuse of language to call this Matter.838.Cf.Principles, sect. 25, 26.839.It is here argued that asvolitionis the onlyoriginativecause implied in our experience, and which consequently alone puts true meaning into the term Cause, to apply that term to what is not volition is to make it meaningless, or at least to misapply it.840.While thus arguing against the need for independent matter, as an instrument needed by God, Berkeley fails to explain how dependent matter can be a medium of intercourse between persons. It must be more than a subjective dream, however well ordered, if it is available for this purpose. Unless the visible and audible ideas or phenomena presented to me are actually seen and heard by other men, how can they be instrumental in intercommunication?841.Cf.Principles, sect. 68-79.842.Cf.Principles, sect. 20.843.Cf.Principles, sect. 80, 81.844.i.e. all Spirits and their dependent ideas or phenomena.845.This, according to Hume (who takes for granted that Berkeley's reasonings can produce no conviction), is the natural effect of Berkeley's philosophy.—“Most of the writings of that very ingenious author (Berkeley) form the best lessons of scepticism which are to be found either among the ancient or modern philosophers, Bayle not excepted.... That all his arguments, though otherwise intended, are, in reality, merely sceptical, appear from this—that they admit of no answer, and produce no conviction. Their only effect is to cause that momentary amazement and irresolution and confusion, which is the result of scepticism.”(Hume'sEssays, vol. II. Note N, p. 554.)846.Omitted in last edition.847.“Tell me, Hylas,”—“So Hylas”—in first and second editions.848.Variously callednoumena,“things-in-themselves,”absolute substances, &c.—which Berkeley's philosophy banishes, on the ground of their unintelligibility, and thus annihilates all farther questions concerning them. Questions about existence are thus confined within the concrete or realising experiences of living spirits.849.Berkeley claims that his doctrine supersedes scepticism, and excludes the possibility of fallacy in sense, in excluding an ultimately representative perception of Matter. He also assumes the reasonableness of faith in the reality and constancy of natural law. When we see an orange, the visual sense guarantees only colour. The other phenomena, which we associate with this colour—the other“qualities”of the orange—are, when we onlyseethe orange, matter of faith. We believe them to be realisable.850.He accepts the common belief on which interpretation of sense symbols proceeds—that sensible phenomena are evolved in rational order, under laws that are independent of, and in that respect external to, the individual percipient.851.Mediately as well as immediately.852.We can hardly be said to have animmediatesense-perception of an individual“thing”—meaning by“thing”a congeries of sense-ideas or phenomena, presented to different senses. We immediately perceive some of them, and believe in the others, which those suggest. See the last three notes.853.He probably refers to Descartes, whoarguesfor the trustworthiness of our faculties from the veracity of God; thus apparently arguing in a circle, seeing that the existence of God is manifested to us only through our suspected faculties. But is not confidence in the trustworthiness of the Universal Power at the heart of the universe, the fundamentalpresuppositionof all human experience, and God thus the basis and end of philosophy and of experience?854.As Locke does. SeeEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 11.855.Cf.Principles of Human Knowledge, sect. 45-48.856.And to be thus external to individual minds.857.It is here that Berkeley differs, for example, from Hume and Comte and J.S. Mill; who accept sense-given phenomena, and assume the constancy of their orderly reappearances,as a matter of fact, while they confess total ignorance of thecauseof natural order. (Thus ignorant, why do they assume reason or order in nature?) The ground of sensible things, which Berkeley refers to Divine Power, Mill expresses by the term“permanent possibilityof sensation.”(See hisExamination of Hamilton, ch. 11.) Our belief in the continued existence of a sensible thingin our absencemerely means, with him, our conviction, derived from custom, that we should perceive it under inexplicable conditions which determine its appearance.858.Cf.Principles, sect. 25, 26.859.Cf. Ibid., sect. 2, 27, 135-142.860.Inasmuch as I am conscious ofmyself, I can gather, through the sense symbolism, the real existence of other minds, external to my own. For I cannot, of course, enter into the very consciousness of another person.861.“reason,”i.e. reasoning or necessary inference—founded here on our sense of personal dependence; not merely on our faith in sense symbolism and the interpretability of the sensible world. Our belief in the existence of finite minds, external to our own, is, with Berkeley, an application of this faith.862.“Matter,”i.e. Matter as abstract substance. Cf.Principles, sect. 135-138.863.Does this imply that with Berkeley,self, as distinguished from thephenomenaof which the material world consists, is not a necessary presuppostion of experience? He says in many places—I amconsciousof“my own being,”and that my mind is myself. Cf.Principles, sect, 2.864.Cf.Principles, sect. 8.865.Cf. Ibid., sect. 20866.This important passage, printed within brackets, is not found in the first and second editions of theDialogues. It is, by anticipation, Berkeley's answer to Hume's application of the objections to the reality of abstract or unperceived Matter, to the reality of the Ego or Self, of which we are aware through memory, as identical amid the changes of its successive states.867.See note 4 on preceding page.868.Cf.Principles, sect. 142.869.Cf. Ibid., sect. 2. Does he assume that he exists when he is not conscious of ideas—sensible or other? Or, does he deny that he is ever unconscious?870.That is of matter supposed to exist independently of any mind. Berkeley speaks here of aconsciousnessof matter. Does he mean consciousness of belief in abstract material Substance?871.Cf.Principles, sect. 54-57.872.Which he does not doubt.873.This sentence expresses the whole question between Berkeley and his antagonists.874.Cf.Principles, sect. 29-41.875.The words within brackets are omitted in the third edition.876.The index pointing to the originative causes in the universe is thus the ethical judgment, which fastens upon the free voluntary agency ofpersons, as absolutely responsible causes, not merely caused causes.877.That only ideas or phenomena are presented to our senses may be assented to by those who nevertheless maintain that intelligent sensuous experience implies more than the sensuous or empirical data.878.Cf.Principles, sect. 49.879.Cf.Principles, sect. 58.880.“without the mind,”i.e. without the mind of each percipient person.881.This is the gist of the whole question. According to the Materialists, sense-presented phenomena are due to unpresented, unperceived, abstract Matter; according to Berkeley, to living Spirit; according to Hume and Agnostics, their origin is unknowable, yet (incoherently) they claim that wecaninterpret them—in physical science.882.A similar objection is urged by Erdmann, in his criticism of Berkeley in theGrundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie.883.Cf.Principles, sect. 50;Siris, sect. 319.884.Cf.Principles, sect. 58.885.“order”—“series,”in first and second editions.886.“Matter,”i.e. when the reality of“matter”is supposed to signify what Berkeley argues cannot be; because really meaningless.887.“the connexion of ideas,”i.e. the physical coexistences and sequences, maintained in constant order by Power external to the individual, and which are disclosed in the natural sciences.888.Cf.Principles, sect. 38. Berkeley is not for making thingssubjective, but for recognising ideas or phenomena presented to the senses asobjective.889.They are not mere illusory appearances but are the very things themselves making their appearance, as far as our limited senses allow them to be realised for us.890.i.e. abstract Matter.891.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 49; andNew Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 9, 10, 15, &c.892.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 84-86.893.“the connexion of ideas,”i.e. the order providentially maintained in nature.894.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 23-25.895.Cf.Principles, sect. 8-10, 86, 87.896.This difficulty is thus pressed by Reid:—“The ideas in my mind cannot be the same with the ideas in any other mind; therefore, if the objects I perceive be only ideas, it is impossible that two or more such minds can perceive the same thing. Thus there is one unconfutable consequence of Berkeley's system, which he seems not to have attended to, and from which it will be found difficult, if at all possible, to guard it. The consequence I mean is this—that, although it leaves us sufficient evidence of a Supreme Mind, it seems to take away all the evidence we have of other intelligent beings like ourselves. What I call a father, or a brother, or a friend, is only a parcel of ideas in my own mind ; they cannot possibly have that relation to another mind which they have to mine, any more than the pain felt by me can be theindividual painfelt by another. I am thus left alone as the only creature of God in the universe”(Hamilton'sReid, pp. 284-285). Implied Solipsism or Panegoism is thus charged against Berkeley, unless his conception of the material world is further guarded.897.Reid and Hamilton argue in like manner against a fundamentally representative sense-perception.898.Cf.Principles, sect. 6.899.Cf. Ibid., sect. 87-90.900.Cf. Ibid., sect. 18.901.Cf.Principles, sect. 24.902.“unknown,”i.e. unrealised in percipient life.903.Cf.Principles, sect. 28-33.904.See also Collier'sClavis Universalis, p. 6:“Two or more persons who are present at a concert of music may indeed in some measure be said to hear thesamenotes; yet the sound which the one hears isnot the very samewith the sound which another hears,because the souls or persons are supposed to be different.”905.Berkeley seems to hold that inthingsthere is no identity other than perfect similarity—only inpersons. And even as to personal identity he is obscure. Cf.Siris, sect. 347, &c.906.But the question is, whether the very ideas or phenomena that are perceived by mecanbe also perceived by other persons; and if not, how I can discover that“other persons”exist, or that any finite person except myself is cognizant of the ideal cosmos—if the sort ofsamenessthat Berkeley advocates is all that can be predicated of concrete ideas; which are thus onlysimilar, or generically the same. Unless the ideas arenumericallythe same, can different persons make signs to one another through them?907.Omitted in author's last edition.908.This seems to imply that intercourse between finite persons is maintained through ideas or phenomena presented to the senses, under a tacit faith in divinely guaranteed correspondence between the phenomena of which I am conscious, and the phenomena of which my neighbour is conscious; so that they arepractically“the same.”If we are living in a fundamentally divine, and therefore absolutely trustworthy, universe, the phenomena presented to my senses, which I attribute to the agency of another person, are so attributed rightly. For if not, the so-called cosmos is adapted to mislead me.909.This explanation is often overlooked by Berkeley's critics.910.Cf.Principles, sect. 82-84.911.i.e. if you take the termideain its wholly subjective and popular meaning.912.i.e. if you take the termideain its objective meaning.913.“philosophic,”i.e.pseudo-philosophic, against which he argues.914.Had this their relative existence—this realisation of the material world through finite percipient and volitional life—any beginning? May not God have been eternally presenting phenomena to the senses of percipient beings in cosmical order, if not on this planet yet elsewhere, perhaps under other conditions? Has there been any beginning in the succession of finite persons?915.In the first and second editions only.916.Is“creation”by us distinguishable from continuous evolution, unbeginning and unending, in divinely constituted order; and is there a distinction between creation or evolution ofthingsand creation or evolution ofpersons?917.Cf.Siris, sect. 347-349.918.“Matter,”i.e. Matter in this pseudo-philosophical meaning of the word.919.Thus Origen in the early Church. That“Matter”is co-eternal with God would mean that God is eternally making things real in the percipient experience of persons.920.Cf.Principles, sect. 85-156, in which the religious and scientific advantages of the new conception of matter and the material cosmos are illustrated, when it is rightly understood and applied.921.“substance and accident”—“subjects and adjuncts,”—in the first and the second edition.922.Cf.Principles, sect. 28-42. InSiris, sect. 294-297, 300-318, 335, 359-365, we have glimpses of thought more allied to Platonism, if not to Hegelianism.923.“Matter,”i.e. matter unrealised in any mind, finite or Divine.924.These two propositions are a summary of Berkeley's conception of the material world. With him, theimmediateobjects of sense, realise inperception, are independent of thewillof the percipient, and are thus external to his proper personality. Berkeley's“material world”of enlightened Common Sense, resulting from two factors, Divine and human, is independent of each finite mind; but not independent of all living Mind.925.“voces male intellectæ.”Cf.Principles of Human Knowledge,“Introduction,”sect. 6, 23-25, on the abuse of language, especially by abstraction.926.“veterum philosophorum.”The history of ancient speculations about motion, from the paradoxes of Zeno downwards, is, in some sort, a history of ancient metaphysics. It involves Space, Time, and the material world, with the ultimate causal relation of Nature to Spirit.927.“hujus ævi philosophos.”As in Bacon on motion, and in the questions raised by Newton, Borelli, Leibniz, and others, discussed in the following sections.928.Sect. 3-42 are concerned with the principle of Causality, exemplified in the motion, or change of place and state, that is continually going on in the material world, and which was supposed by some to explain all the phenomena of the universe.929.“vis.”The assumption thatactive poweris an immediate datum of sense is the example here offered of the abase of abstract words. He proceeds to dissolve the assumption by shewing that it is meaningless.930.“principio”—the ultimate explanation or originating cause. Cf. sect. 36. Metaphors, or indeed empty words, are accepted for explanations, it is argued, whenbodilypower or force, in any form, e.g. gravitation, is taken as the real cause of motion. To call these“occult causes”is to say nothing that is intelligible. The perceived sensible effects and their customary sequences are all we know. Physicists are still deluded by words and metaphors.931.Cf. sect. 53, wheresense,imagination, andintelligenceare distinguished.932.Cf.Principles, Introd. 16, 20, 21; alsoAlciphron, Dial. VII. sect. 8, 17.933.[La Materia altro non è che un vaso di Circe incantato, il quale serve per ricettacolo della forza et de' momenti dell' impeto. La forzae l'impeti sono astratti tanto sottili, sono quintessenze tanto spiritose, che in altre ampolle non si possono racchiudere, fuor che nell' intima corpulenza de' solidi naturali, VideLezioni Accademiche.]—Author.Torricelli (1608-47), the eminent Italian physicist, and professor of mathematics at Florence, who invented the barometer.934.Borelli (1608-79), Italian professor of mathematics at Pisa, and then of medicine at Florence; see hisDe Vi Percussionis, cap. XXIV. prop. 88, and cap. XXVII.935.“per effectum,”i.e. by its sensible effects—real power or active force not being a datum of the senses, but found in the spiritual efficacy, of which we have an example in our personal agency.936.“vim mortuam.”The only power we can find is the living power of Mind. Reason is perpetually active in the universe, imperceptible through the senses, and revealed tothemonly in its sensible effects.“Power,”e.g.“gravitation,”in things,per se, is distinguished from perceived“motion”only through illusion due to misleading abstraction. There is nophysicalpower, intermediate between spiritual agency, on the one hand, and the sensible changes we see, on the other. Cf. sect. 11.937.“meditatione subigenda sunt.”Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 35, 70.938.“distingui.”It is here argued that so-called power within the things of sense is not distinguishable from the sensibly perceived sequences. To the meaningless supposition that it is, he attributes the frivolous verbal controversies among the learned mentioned in the following section. The province of natural philosophy, according to Berkeley, is to inquire what the rules are under which sensible effects are uniformly manifested. Cf.Siris, sect. 236, 247, 249.939.Principia Math.Def. III.940.De Vi Percussionis, cap. I.941.“utiles.”Such words as“force,”“power,”“gravity,”“attraction,”are held to be convenient in physical reasonings about thephenomenaof motion, but worthless as philosophical expressions of thecauseof motion, which transcends sense and mechanical science. Cf.Siris, sect. 234, 235.942.Cf. sect. 67.943.“candem.”So in recent discussions on the conservation of force.944.[Borellus.]—Author.SeeDe Vi Percussionis, cap. XXIII.945.[Leibnitius.]—Author.946.On Berkeley's reasoning all terms which involve the assumption that real causality is something presentable to the senses are a cover for meaninglessness. Only through self-conscious experience of personal activity does real meaning enter into the portion of language which deals with active causation. This is argued in detail in sect. 21-35.947.Our concrete experience is assumed to be confined to (a)bodies, i.e. the data of the senses, and (b)mindorspirit—sentient, intelligent, active—revealed by internal consciousness. Cf.Principles, sect. 1, 2, in which experience is resolved intoideasand theactive intelligencewhich they presuppose. Here the word idea disappears, but, in accordance with its signification,“bodies”is still regarded as aggregates of external phenomena, the passive subjects of changes of place and state: the idealisation of the material world is tacitly implied, but not obtruded.948.“nihilque,”&c. Cf.Principles of Human Knowledge, e.g. sect. 26, 65, 66. where the essential passivity of theideaspresented to the senses, i.e. the material world, is maintained as a cardinal principle—on the positive ground of our percipient experience of sensible things. To speak of the cause of motion assomething sensible, he argues (sect. 24), is merely to shew that we know nothing about it. Cf. sect. 28, 29, infra.949.The phenomena that can be presented to the senses are taken as the measure of what can be attributed to the material world; and as the senses presentonlyconditioned change of place in bodies, we must look for the active cause in the invisible world which internal consciousness presents to us.950.“genus rerum cogitantium.”Cf.Principles, sect. 2.951.“experientia didicimus.”Can the merely empirical data even of internal consciousness reveal this causal connexion between volition and bodily motions, without the venture of theistic faith?952.“a primo et universali Principio”i.e. God, or the Universal Spirit, in whom the universe of bodies and spirits finds explanation; in a way which Berkeley does not attempt to unfold articulately and exhaustively in philosophical system.953.Phys.θ. 4. 255 a 5-7.954.Princip. Math.Def. III.955.“resistentia.”Our muscularsensationof resistance is apt to be accepted empirically as itselfactive power in the concrete, entering very much, as has been said, into the often inaccurate idea of power which is formed. See Editor's Preface.956.“nec incommode.”Cf. sect. 17, and note.957.“hypothesis mathematica.”Cf. sect. 17, 35, 36-41, 66, 67; alsoSiris, sect. 250-251.958.“nihil.”This section sums up Berkeley's objections to creditingmatterwith real power; the senses being taken as the test of what is contained in matter. It may be compared with David Hume, Thomas Brown, and J.S. Mill on Causation. Berkeley differs from them in recognising active power in spirit, while with them he resolves causation among bodies into invariable sequence.959.Can the data presented to us reveal more than sequence, in the relation between our volitions and the corresponding movements of our bodies? Is not the difference found in the moral presupposition, whichsupernaturalisesman in his voluntary or morally responsible activity? This obliges us to seeourselvesas absolutely original causes of all bodily and mental states for which we can be morally approved or blamed.960.“novumque genus.”Cf. sect. 21. We have here Berkeley's antithesis of mind and matter—spirits and external phenomena presented to the senses—persons in contrast to passive ideas.961.De Anima, I. ii. 13, 22, 24.962.“Cartesius.”The antithesis of extended things and thinking things pervades Descartes; but not, as with Berkeley, on the foundation of the new conception of what is truly meant by matter or sensible things. See e.g.Principia, P. I. §§ 63, 64.963.“alii.”Does he refer to Locke, who suggests the possibility of matter thinking?964.See Aristotle,De Anima, I. ii. 5, 13; Diogenes Laertius, Lib. VI. i. 6.965.Nat. Ausc.VIII. 15; alsoDe Anima, III, x. 7.966.Hardly any passage in theTimæusexactly corresponds to this. The following is, perhaps, the most pertinent:—Κίνησιν γὰρ ἀπένειμεν αὐτῷ τὴν τοῦ σώματος οἰκείαν, τῶν ἑπτὰ τὴν περὶ νοῦν καὶ φρόνησιν μάλιστα οὖσαν (p. 34 a). Aristotle quotes theTimæusin the same connexion,De Anima, I. iii. ii.967.“philosophi Cartesiani.”Secundum Cartesium causa generalis omnium motuum et quietum est Deus.—Derodon,Physica, I. ix. 30.968.Principia Mathematica—Scholium Generale.969.“naturam naturantem esse Deum”—as we might say, God considered as imminent cause in the universe. See St. Thomas Aquinas,Opera, vol. XXII. Quest. 6, p. 27.970.“juxta certam et constantem rationem.”While all changes in Nature are determined by Will, it is not capricious but rational Will. The so-called arbitrariness of the Language of Nature is relative to us, and from our point of view. In itself, the universe of reality expresses Perfect Reason.971.“permaneret.”Cf. sect. 51.972.“spectat potius ad philosophiam primam.”The drift of theDe Motuis to distinguish the physical sequences of molecular motion, which the physical sciences articulate, from the Power with which metaphysics and theology are concerned, and which we approach through consciousness.973.“regulas.”Cf.Siris, sect. 231-235.974.Having, in the preceding sections, contrasted perceived motions and their immanent originating Power—matter and mind—physics and metaphysics—he proceeds in this and the seven following sections to explain more fully what ha means byprincipiumand also the two meanings (metaphysical and mechanical) ofsolutio. Byprincipium, in philosophy, he understands universally efficient supersensible Power. In natural philosophy the term is applied to the orderly sequences manifested to our senses, not to the active cause of the order.975.“ratiocinio ... redditæ universales.”Relations of the data of sense to universalising reason are here recognised.976.“natura motus.”Sect. 43-66 treat of the nature of theeffect—i.e. perceptible motion, as distinguished from its true causal origin (principium) in mind or spirit. The origin of motion belongs to metaphysics; its nature, as dependent on percipient experience, belongs to physics. Is motion independent of a plurality of bodies; or does it involve bodies in relation to other bodies, so that absolute motion is meaningless? Cf.Principles, sect. 111-116.977.“idea illa tenuissima et subtilissima.”The difficulty as to definition of motion is attributed to abstractions, and the inclination of the scholastic mind to prefer these to concrete experience.978.Motion is thus defined by Aristotle:—Διὸ ἡ κίνησις ἐντελέχεια τοῦ κινητοῦ, ᾗ κινητόν. Nat. Ausc. III. ii; see also i. and iii. Cf. Derodon,Physica, I. ix.979.Newton.980.Cf. sect. 3-42.981.Descartes,Principia, P. II. § 25; also Borellus,De Vi Percussionis, p. 1.982.“res faciles difficillimas.”Cf.Principles,“Introduction,”sect. 1.983.Καὶ διὰ τοῦτο δὴ χαλεπὸν αὐτὴν λαβεῖν τί ἐστίν.Nat. Ausc.III. ii.984.e.g. Zeno, in his noted argument against the possibility of motion, referred to as a signal example of fallacy.985.“de infinite, &c.”Cf.Principles, sect. 130-132, and theAnalystpassim, for Berkeley's treatment of infinitesimals.986.“confundere.”Cf. sect. 3-42 for illustrations of this confusion.987.The modern conception of the“conservation of force.”988.Aristotle states the question inNat. Ausc.VIII. cap. i, and solves it in cap. iv.989.“mutatio loci”is the effect, i.e. motion perceived by sense;“vitale principium”the real cause, i.e. vital rational agency.990.“moventis et moti,”i.e. as concauses.991.“motum localem.”Sect. 52-65 discuss the reality of absolute or empty space, in contrast with concrete space realised in perception of the local relations of bodies. The meaninglessness of absolute space and motion is argued. Cf.Principles, sect. 116, 117. See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 13, 15, 17; alsoPapers which passed between Mr. Leibnitz and Dr. Clarke in 1715-16, pp. 55-59; 73-81; 97-103, &c. Leibniz calls absolute space“an ideal of some modern Englishman.”992.Newton'sPrincipia, Def. Sch. III. See also Derodon,Physica, P. I. cap. vi. § 1.993.Cf. Locke on a vacuum, and the“possibility of space existing without matter,”Essay, Bk. II. ch. 13.994.Note the account here given ofimaginationandintellect, as distinguished fromsense, which may be compared with αἴσθησις, φαντασία, and νοῦς in Aristotelian psychology.995.“attributorum divinorum particeps.”See Samuel Clarke, in hisDemonstration, and in thePapers between Clarke and Leibnitz.996.“nostrum,”sc. corpus. When we imagine space emptied of bodies, we are apt to forget that our own bodies are part of the material world.997.[Vide quæ contra spatium absolutum disseruntur in libroDe Principiis Cognitionis Humanæ, idiomate anglicano decem abhine annis edito.]—Author.He refers to sect. 116 of thePrinciples.998.He treats absolute space as nothing, and relative space as dependent on Perception and Will.999.Phys.α. 5. 188a. 22, 23.1000.See Locke,Essay, Bk. II. ch. 13, §§ 7-10.1001.Sect. 67-72 treat of the supposed ejection of motion from the striking body into the body struck. Is this only metaphorical? Is the motion received by the latter to be supposed identical with, or equivalent to, that given forth by the former?1002.Principia, Def. IV.1003.Lezioni Accademiche.1004.De Vi Percussionis, cap. IX.1005.Newton's third law of motion.1006.Berkeley sees in motion only a link in the chain which connects the sensible and intelligible worlds—a conception unfolded in hisSiris, more than twenty years later.1007.“provincia sua.”TheDe Motu, so far as it treats of motion perceptible to the senses, is assigned to physics; in contrast to theology or metaphysics, alone concerned with active causation.
Footnotes1.Philosophy of Theism: The Gifford Lectures delivered before the University of Edinburgh in 1894-96. (Second Edition, 1899.)2.Essay on Vision, sect. 147, 148.3.Principles, sect. 6.4.Preface to theThree Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous.5.By Anthony Collins.6.See vol. III, Appendix B.7.Murdoch Martin, a native of Skye, author of aVoyage to St. Kilda(1698), and aDescription of the Western Islands of Scotland(1703).8.See Stewart'sWorks(ed. Hamilton), vol. I. p. 161. There is a version of this story by DeQuincey, in his quaint essay onMurder considered as one of the Fine Arts.9.Sir John became Lord Percival in that year.10.A place more than once visited by Berkeley.11.Bakewell'sMemoirs of the Court of Augustus, vol. II. p. 177.12.A letter in Berkeley'sLife and Letters, p. 93, which led me to a different opinion, I have now reason to believe was not written by him, nor was it written in 1721. The research of Dr. Lorenz, confirmed by internal evidence, shews that it was written in October, 1684, before Berkeley the philosopher was born, and when the Duke of Ormond was Lord Lieutenant of Ireland. The writer was probably the Hon. and Rev. George Berkeley, a Prebendary of Westminster in 1687, who died in 1694. The wife of the“pious Robert Nelson”was a daughter of Earl Berkeley, and this“George”was her younger brother.13.Percival MSS.14.For the letter, see Editor's Preface to theProposal for a College in Bermuda, vol. IV. pp. 343-44.15.Afterwards Sir John James.16.Smibert the artist, who made a picture of Berkeley in 1725, and afterwards in America of the family party then at Gravesend.17.Historical Register, vol. XIII, p. 289 (1728).18.New England Weekly Courier, Feb. 3, 1729.19.For valuable information about Rhode Island, reproduced inBerkeley's Life and Correspondenceand here, I am indebted to Colonel Higginson, to whom I desire to make this tardy but grateful acknowledgement.20.James, Dalton, and Smibert.21.Whitehall, having fallen into decay, has been lately restored by the pious efforts of Mrs. Livingston Mason, in concert with the Rev. Dr. E. E. Hale, and others. This good work was completed in the summer of 1900; and the house is now as nearly as possible in the state in which Berkeley left it.22.See vol. III, Appendix C.23.Three Men of Letters, by Moses Coit Tyler (New York, 1895). He records some of the American academical and other institutions that are directly or indirectly, due to Berkeley.24.The thought implied in this paragraph is pursued in myPhilosophy of Theism, in which the ethical perfection of the Universal Mind is taken as the fundamental postulate in all human experience. If the Universal Mind is not ethically perfect, the universe (including our spiritual constitution) is radically untrustworthy.25.Life and Letters of Berkeley, p. 222.26.The third Earl of Shaftesbury, the pupil of Locke, and author of theCharacteristics. In addition to the well-known biography by Dr. Fowler, the present eminent Vice-Chancellor of Oxford, Shaftesbury has been interpreted in two other lately published works—aLifeby Benjamin Rand, Ph.D. (1900), and an edition of theCharacteristics, with an Introduction and Notes, by John M. Robertson (1900).27.The title of this book is—Things Divine and Supernatural conceived by Analogy with Things Natural and Human, by the Author ofThe Procedure, Extent and Limits of the Human Understanding. TheDivine Analogyappeared in 1733, and theProcedurein 1728.28.Spinoza argues that what iscalled“understanding”and“will”in God, has no more in common with human understanding and will than the dog-star in the heavens has with the animal we call a dog. See Spinoza'sEthica, I. 17,Scholium.29.The question of the knowableness of God, or Omnipotent Moral Perfection in the concrete, enters into recent philosophical and theological discussion in Britain. Calderwood, in hisPhilosophy of the Infinite(1854), was one of the earliest, and not the least acute, of Hamilton's critics in this matter. The subject is lucidly treated by Professor Andrew Seth (Pringle-Pattison) in hisLectures on Theism(1897) and in a supplement to Calderwood'sLife(1900). So also Huxley'sDavid Humeand Professor Iverach'sIs God Knowable?30.Stewart'sWorks. vol. I. pp. 350-1.31.Berkeley MSS. possessed by Archdeacon Rose.32.Pope's poetic tribute to Berkeley belongs to this period—“Even in a bishop I can spy desert;Secker is decent; Rundle has a heart:Manners with candour are to Benson given,To Berkeley—every virtue under heaven.”Epilogue to the Satires.Also his satirical tribute to the critics of Berkeley—“Truth's sacred fort th' exploded laugh shall win;And Coxcombs vanquish Berkeley with a grin.”Essay on Satire,Part II.33.Berkeley'sLife and Letters, p. 210.34.Bacon'sNovuin Organum. Distributio Operis.35.Section 141.36.See“Editor's Preface to Alciphron.”37.Compare Essay II in theGuardianwith this.38.Taylor, in later life, conformed to the Anglican Church.39.See Berkeley'sLife and Letters, chap. viii.40.The Primacy.41.This seems to have been his eldest son, Henry.42.His son George was already settled at Christ Church. Henry, the eldest son, born in Rhode Island, was then“abroad in the south of France for his health,”as one of his brother George's letters tells us, found among the Johnson MSS.43.See Appendix D. Reid, like Berkeley, held that“matter cannot be the cause of anything,”but this not as a consequence of the new conception of the world presented to the senses, through which alone Berkeley openshisway to its powerlessness; although Reid supposes that in his youth he followed Berkeley in this too. SeeThomas Reid(1898), in“Famous Scots Series,”where I have enlarged on this.44.Johnson MSS.45.That Berkeley was buried in Oxford is mentioned in his son's letter to Johnson, in which he says :“His remains are interred in the Cathedral of Christ Church, and next week a monument to his memory will be erected with an inscription by Dr. Markham, a Student of this College.”As the son was present at, and superintended the arrangements for his father's funeral, it can be no stretch of credulity to believe that he knew where his father was buried. It may be added that Berkeley himself had provided in his Will“that my body be buried in the churchyard of the parish in which I die.”The Will, dated July 31, 1752, is givenin extensoin myLife and Lettersof Berkeley, p. 345. We have also the record of burial in the Register of Christ Church Cathedral, which shews that“on January ye 20th1753, ye Right Reverend John (sic) Berkley, LdBishop of Cloyne, was buryed”there. This disposes of the statement on p. 17 of Diprose'sAccount of the Parish of Saint Clement Danes(1868), that Berkeley was buried in that church.I may add that a beautiful memorial of Berkeley has lately been placed in the Cathedral of Cloyne, by subscriptions in this country and largely in America.46.“General ideas,”i.e.abstractgeneral ideas, distinguished, in Berkeley's nominalism, fromconcretegeneral ideas, or from general names, which are signs of any one of an indefinite number of individual objects. Cf.Principles,Introduction, sect. 16.47.Introduction to thePrinciples of Human Knowledge.48.“co-existing ideas,”i.e. phenomena presented in uniform order to the senses.49.Newton postulates a world of matter and motion, governed mechanically by laws within itself: Berkeley finds himself charged with New Principles, demanded by reason, with which Newton's postulate is inconsistent.50.He attempts this in many parts of thePrinciplesandDialogues. He recognises the difficulty of reconciling his New Principles with theidentityandpermanenceof sensible things.51.He contemplated thus early applications of his New Principles to Mathematics, afterwards made in his book ofPrinciples, sect. 118-32.52.What Berkeley callsideasare either perceptible by the senses or imagined: either way they are concrete:abstract ideasare empty words.53.i.e. the existence of bodies and qualities independently of—in abstraction from—all percipient mind. While the spiritual theism of Descartes is acceptable, he rejects his mechanical conception of the material world.54.But a“house”or a“church”includes more thanvisibleideas, so that we cannot, strictly speaking, be said to see it. We see immediately only visible signs of its invisible qualities.55.This is added in the margin.56.The total impotence of Matter, and the omnipotence of Mind or Spirit in Nature, is thus early becoming the dominant thought with Berkeley.57.This refers to an objection to the New Principles that is apparently reinforced by recent discoveries in geology. But if these contradict the Principles, so does the existence of a table while I am only seeing it.58.Existence, in short, can be realised only in the form of living percipient mind.59.Berkeley hardly distinguishes uncontingent mathematicalrelations, to which the sensible ideas or phenomena in which the relations are concretely manifested must conform.60.M. T. = matter tangible; M. V. = matter visible; M. . = matter sensible. The distinctions n question were made prominent in theEssay on Vision. See sect. 1, 121-45.61.Which the common supposition regarding primary qualities seems to contradict.62.[That need not have been blotted out—'tis good sense, if we do but determine wtwe mean bythingandidea.]—Author, on blank page of the MS.63.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. III. ch. 4, § 8, where he criticises attempts to define motion, as involving apetitio.64.George Cheyne, the physician (known afterwards as author of theEnglish Malady), published in 1705 a work on Fluxions, which procured him admission to the Royal Society. He was born in 1670.65.This reminds us of Hume, and inclines towards the empirical notion of Causation, as merely constancy in sequence—not even continuous metamorphosis.66.This is Berkeley's objection to abstract, i.e. unperceived, quantities and infinitesimals—important in the sequel.67.The“lines and figures”of pure mathematics, that is to say; which he rejects as meaningless, in his horror unrealisable abstractions.68.Things really exist, that is to say, in degrees, e.g. in a lesser degree, when they are imagined than when they are actually perceived by our senses; but, in this wide meaning of existence, they may in both cases be said to exist.69.Added on blank page of the MS.70.In Berkeley's limitation of the termideato what is presented objectively in sense, or represented concretely in imagination. Accordingly“an infinite idea”would be an idea which transcends ideation—an express contradiction.71.Does thehumanspirit depend onsensibleideas as much as they depend on spirit? Other orders of spiritual beings may be percipient of other sorts of phenomena than those presented in those few senses to which man is confined, although self-conscious activity abstracted fromallsorts of presented phenomena seems impossible. But a self-conscious spirit is not necessarily dependent onourmaterial world oroursense experience.72.[This I do not altogether approve of.]—Author, on margin.73.He afterwards guarded the difference, by contrastingnotionandidea, confining the latter to phenomena presented objectively to our senses, or represented in sensuous imagination, and applying the former to intellectual apprehension of“operations of the mind,”and of“relations”among ideas.74.SeePrinciples, sect. 89.75.Is thought, then, independent of language? Can we realise thought worthy of the name without use of words? This is Berkeley's excessive juvenile reaction against verbal abstractions.76.Every general notion isideally realisablein one or other of its possible concrete or individual applications.77.This is the germ of Berkeley's notion of the objectivity of the material world to individual percipients and so of the rise of individual self-consciousness.78.Added by Berkeley on blank page of the MS.79.Cf. p.420, note 2. Bishop Sprat'sHistory of the Royal Societyappeared in 1667.80.Much need; for what he means byideahas not been attended to by his critics.81.What“Second Book”is this? Does he refer to the“Second Part”of thePrinciples, which never appeared? God is the culmination of his philosophy, inSiris.82.This is Berkeley's material substance. Individual material substances are for him, steady aggregates of sense-given phenomena, having the efficient and final cause of their aggregation in eternally active Mind—active mind, human and Divine, being essential to their realisation for man.83.Cf. Introduction to thePrinciples, especially sect. 18-25.84.Stillingfleet charges Locke with“discarding substance out of the reasonable part of the world.”85.The philosophers supposed the real things to exist behind our ideas, in concealment: Berkeley was now beginning to think that the objective ideas or phenomena presented to the senses, the existence of which needs no proof, werethemselvesthe significant and interpretable realities of physical science.86.If the material world can berealonly in and through a percipient intelligence, as the realising factor.87.Cf.Principles, sect. 13, 119-122, which deny the possibility of an idea or mental picture corresponding to abstract number.88.“Præcedaneous,”i.e. precedent.89.Who refunds human as well as natural causation into Divine agency.90.In which Locke treats“Of the Reality of Knowledge,”including questions apt to lead Berkeley to inquire, Whether we could in reason suppose reality in the absence of all realising mind.91.Locke's“abstract idea”is misconceived and caricatured by Berkeley in his impetuosity.92.This and other passages refer to the scepticism, that is founded on the impossibility of our comparing our ideas of things with unperceived real things; so that we can never escape from the circle of subjectivity. Berkeley intended to refute this scepticism.93.Probably Samuel Madden, who afterwards edited theQuerist.94.This“First Book”seems to be“Part I”of the projectedPrinciples—the only Part ever published. Here he inclines to“perception or thought in general,”in the language of Descartes; but in the end he approximates to Locke's“sensation and reflection.”SeePrinciples, sect. 1, and notes.95.Does he mean, like Hume afterwards, that ideas or phenomena constitute the ego, so that I am only the transitory conscious state of each moment?96.“Consciousness”—a term rarely used by Berkeley or his contemporaries.97.This too, if strictly interpreted, looks like an anticipation of Hume's reduction of the ego into successive“impressions”—“nothing but a bundle or collection of different perceptions, which succeed one another with inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and movement.”See Hume'sTreatise, Part IV. sect. 6.98.What“Third Book”is here projected? Was a“Third Part”of thePrinciplesthen in embryo?99.This is scarcely done in the“Introduction”to thePrinciples.100.Berkeley, as we find in theCommonplace Book, is fond of conjecturing how a man all alone in the world, freed from the abstractions of language, would apprehend the realities of existence, which he must then face directly, without the use or abuse of verbal symbols.101.This“N. B.”is expanded in the Introduction to thePrinciples.102.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 4.103.What is immediately realised in our percipient experience must be presumed or trusted in as real, if we have any hold of reality, or the moral right to postulate that our universe is fundamentally trustworthy.104.But he distinguishes, in thePrinciplesand elsewhere, between an idea of sense and a percipient ego.105.They reappear inSiris.106.In one of Berkeley's letters to Johnson, a quarter of a century after theCommonplace Book, when he was in America, he observes that“the mechanical philosophers pretend to demonstrate that matter is proportional to gravity. But their argument concludes nothing, and is a mere circle”—as he proceeds to show.107.In thePrinciples, sect. 1-33, he seeks to fulfil the expository part of this intention; in sect. 33-84, also in theDialogues between Hylas and Philonous, he is“particular in answering objections.”108.If Matter is arbitrarily credited with omnipotence.109.On freedom as implied in a moral and responsible agent, cf.Siris, sect. 257 and note.110.Is not this one way of expressing the Universal Providence and constant uniting agency of God in the material world?111.Hereideaseems to be used in its wider signification, includingnotion.112.“infinitely greater”—Does infinity admit of imaginable degrees?113.'embrangled'—perplexed—involved in disputes.114.SeePrinciples, Introduction, sect. 24.115.“homonymy,”i.e. equivocation.116.Voluntary or responsible activity is not an idea or datum of sense, nor can it be realised in sensuous imagination. He uses“thing”in the wide meaning which comprehends persons.117.Voluntary or responsible activity is not an idea or datum of sense, nor can it be realised in sensuous imagination. He uses“thing”in the wide meaning which comprehends persons.118.Is this consistent with other entries?119.Essay, Bk. II. ch. i. sect. 9-19.120.This is one way of meeting the difficulty of supposed interruptions of conscious or percipient activity.121.This seems to imply that voluntary action is mysteriously self-originated.122.“perception.”He does not include the percipient.123.“without,”i.e. unrealised by any percipient.124.This would makeideathe term only for what is imagined, as distinguished from what is perceived in sense.125.In a strict use of words, onlypersonsexercise will—notthings.126.As we must do in imagination, which (unlike sense) is representative; for the mental images represent original data of sense-perception.127.Does he not allow that we havemeaning, if notideas, when we use the terms virtue and vice and moral action?128.As Locke says we are.129.“Existenceandunityare ideas that are suggested to the understanding by every object without and every idea within. When ideas are in our minds, we consider thattheyexist.”Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 7. sect. 7.130.i.e. of Existence in the abstract—unperceived and unperceiving—realised neither in percipient life nor in moral action.131.This suggests that God knows sensible things without being sentient of any.132.Cf.Principles, Introd., sect. 1-5.133.Cf. Preface toPrinciples; also toDialogues.134.i.e. that ethics was a science of phenomena or ideas.135.i.e. of theindependentexistence of Matter.136.'bodies'—i.e. sensible things—not unrealised Matter.137.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 13.138.Locke died in October, 1704.139.“without the mind,”i.e. abstracted from all active percipient life.140.e.g. secondary qualities of sensible things, in which pleasure and pain are prominent.141.e.g. primary qualities, in which pleasure and pain are latent.142.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 13. § 21, ch. 17. § 4; also Bk. IV. ch. 3. § 6; also his controversy with Bishop Stillingfleet regarding the possibility of Matter thinking. With Berkeley real space is a finite creature, dependent for realisation on living percipient Spirit.143.But what of the origination of the volition itself?144.Essay, Bk. I. ch. iv. § 18. See also Locke'sLettersto Stillingfleet.145.It is, according to Berkeley, the steady union or co-existence of a group of sense-phenomena.146.Essay, Bk. II. ch. i. § 10—where he argues for interruptions of consciousness.“Men think not always.”147.In other words, the material world is wholly impotent: all activity in the universe is spiritual.148.On the order of its four books and the structure of Locke'sEssay, see the Prolegomena in my edition of theEssay, pp. liv-lviii.149.i.e. independent imperceptible Matter.150.What of the earliest geological periods, asks Ueberweg? But is there greater difficulty in such instances than in explaining the existence of a table or a house, while one is merely seeing, without touching?151.Locke explains“substance”as“an uncertain supposition of we know not what.”Essay, Bk. I. ch. 4. § 18.152.Locke makes certainty consist in the agreement of“our ideas with the reality of things.”SeeEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 4. § 18. Here the sceptical difficulty arises, which Berkeley meets under his Principle. If we have no perception of reality, we cannot compare our ideas with it, and so cannot have any criterion of reality.153.[This seems wrong. Certainty, real certainty, is of sensible ideas. I may be certain without affirmation or negation.—Author.] This needs further explanation.154.This entry and the preceding tends to resolve all judgments which are not what Kant calls analytical into contingent.155.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 1, §§ 3-7, and ch. 3. §§ 7-21. The stress Berkeley lays on“co-existence”is significant.156.i.e. we must not doubt the reality of the immediate data of sense but accept it, as“the mob”do.157.But is imagination different from actual perception only indegreeof reality?158.Cf.Principles, sect. 13, 120; also Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 7. sect. 7.159.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 1.160.Berkeley's aim evidently is to deliver men from empty abstractions, by a return to more reasonably interpreted common-sense.161.The sort ofexternalworld that is intelligible to us is that of whichanother personis percipient, and which isobjectiveto me, in a percipient experience foreign to mine.162.Cf. Berkeley'sArithmeticaandMiscellanea Mathematica, published while he was making his entries in thisCommonplace Book.163.Minima sensibilia?164.Pleasures,quâpleasures, are natural causes of correlative desires, as pains or uneasinesses are of correlative aversions. This is implied in the very nature of pleasure and pain.165.Here we have his explanation ofidea.166.Absent things.167.Here, as elsewhere, he resolves geometry, as strictly demonstrable, into a reasoned system of analytical or verbal propositions.168.Compare this with note 3, p. 34; also with the contrast between Sense and Reason, inSiris. Is the statement consistent with implied assumptions even in thePrinciples, apart from which they could not cohere?169.To have anideaof God—as Berkeley uses idea—would imply that God is an immediately perceptible, or at least an imaginable object.170.Cf.Principles, sect. 89.171.Ch. 11. § 5.172.Why add—“or perception”?173.Here we have Berkeley's favourite thought of the divine arbitrariness of the constitution of Nature, and of its laws of change.174.This suggests the puzzle, that the cause of every volition must be a preceding volition, and so onad infinitum.175.Recherche, I. 19.176.i.e. of his own individual mind.177.i.e. toapercipient mind, but not necessarily tomine; for natural laws are independent of individual will, although the individual participates in perception of the ordered changes.178.Cf. theArithmetica.179.i.e. which are not phenomena. This recognition of originative Will even then distinguished Berkeley.180.Is this Part II of thePrinciples, which was lost in Italy?181.The thought of articulaterelationsto which real existence must conform, was not then at least in Berkeley's mind. Hence the empiricism and sensationalism into which he occasionally seems to rush in theCommonplace Book, in his repulsion from empty abstractions.182.This is the essence of Berkeley's philosophy—“a blind agent is a contradiction.”183.This is the basis of Berkeley's reasoning for the necessarilyunrepresentativecharacter of the ideas or phenomena that are presented to our senses.Theyare the originals.184.Berkeley's horror of abstract or unperceived space and atoms is partly explained by dogmas in natural philosophy that are now antiquated.185.Ralph [?] Raphson, author ofDemonstratio de Deo(1710), and also ofDe Spatio Reali, seu ente Infinito: conamen mathematico-metaphysicum(1697), to which Berkeley refers in one of his letters to Johnson. See also Green'sPrinciples of Natural Philosophy(1712). The immanence of omnipotent goodness in the material world was unconsciously Berkeley's presupposition. In God we have our being.186.Note here Berkeley's version of the causal principle, which is really the central presupposition of his whole philosophy—viz. every event in the material world must be the issue of acting Will.187.So Locke on an ideally perfect memory.Essay, Bk. II. ch. x. § 9.188.John Sergeant was the author ofSolid Philosophy asserted against the Fancies of the Ideists(London, 1697); also ofthe Method to Science(1696). He was a deserter from the Church of England to the Church of Rome, and wrote several pieces in defence of Roman theology—some of them in controversy with Tillotson.189.Spirit and Matter are mutually dependent; but Spirit is the realising factor and real agent in the universe.190.See Descartes,Meditations, III; Spinoza,Epist.II, ad Oldenburgium.191.Cf.Principles, sect. 2.192.Is“inclusion”here virtually a synonym for verbal definition?193.SeePrinciples, sect. 2. The universe of Berkeley consists of Active Spirits that perceive and produce motion in impotent ideas or phenomena, realised in the percipient experience of persons. All supposed powers in Matter are refunded into Spirit.194.When self-conscious agents are included among“things.”We can have no sensuous image, i.e. idea, ofspirit, although he maintains we can use the word intelligently.195.Berkeley insists that we should individualise our thinking—“ipsis consuescere rebus,”as Bacon says,—to escape the dangers of artificial signs. This is the drift of his assault on abstract ideas, and his repulsion from what is not concrete. He would even dispense with words in his meditations in case of being sophisticated by abstractions.196.Nature or the phenomenal world in short is the revelation of perfectly reasonable Will.197.Gerard De Vries, the Cartesian.198.Are the things of sense only modes in which percipient persons exist?199.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 9. § 8.200.Time being relative to the capacity of the percipient.201.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 9. § 8.202.To perceive what is not an idea (as Berkeley uses idea) is to perceive what is not realised, and therefore not real.203.So things have apotentialobjective existence in the Divine Will.204.With Berkeley, change is time, and time, abstracted from all changes, is meaningless.205.Could he know, by seeing only, even that hehada body?206.“the ideas attending these impressions,”i.e. the ideas that are correlatives of the (by us unperceived) organic impressions.207.The Italian physical and metaphysical philosopher Fardella (1650-1718) maintained, by reasonings akin to those of Malebranche, that the existence of the material world could not be scientifically proved, and could only be maintained by faith in authoritative revelation. See hisUniversæ Philosophiæ Systema(1690), and especially hisLogica(1696).208.Locke'sEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 11.209.What does he mean by“unknown substratum”?210.He gets rid of the infinite in quantity, because it is incapable of concrete manifestation to the senses. When a phenomenon given in sense reaches theminimum sensibile, it reaches what is for us the margin of realisable existence: it cannot be infinitely little and still a phenomenon: insensible phenomena of sense involve a contradiction. And so too of the infinitely large.211.In short he would idealise the visible world but not the tangible world. In thePrinciples, Berkeley idealises both.212.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 149-59, where he concludes that“neither abstract nor visible extension makes the object of geometry.”213.By the adult, who has learned to interpret its visual signs.214.Inasmuch as no physical consequencesfollowthe volition; which however is still self-originated.215.“A succession of ideas I take toconstitutetime, and not to be only the sensible measure thereof, as Mr. Locke and others think.”(Berkeley's letter to Johnson.)216.Cf.Essay, Bk. II. ch. 16, sect. 8.217.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 67-77.218.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 88-120.219.This is of the essence of Berkeley's philosophy.220.But in moral freedom originates in the agent, instead of being“consecutive”to his voluntary acts or found only in their consequences.221.“Strigose”(strigosus)—meagre.222.As he afterwards expresses it, we have intelligiblenotions, but notideas—sensuous pictures—of the states or acts of our minds.223.[“Omnes reales rerum proprietates continentur in Deo.”What means Le Clerc &c. by this? Log. I. ch. 8.]—Author, on margin.224.“Si non rogas intelligo.”225.This way of winning others to his own opinions is very characteristic of Berkeley. See p.92and note.226.SeeThird Dialogue, onsamenessin things andsamenessin persons, which it puzzles him to reconcile with his New Principles.227.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 52-61.228.Cf.Principles, sect. 101-134.229.“distance”—on opposite page in the MS. Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 140.230.Direct perception of phenomena is adequate to the perceived phenomena; indirect or scientific perception is inadequate, leaving room for faith and trust.231.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 107-8.232.The Divine Ideas of Malebranche and the sensuous ideas of Berkeley differ.233.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 71.234.Cf. Malebranche,Recherche, Bk. I. c. 6. That and the following chapters seem to have been in Berkeley's mind.235.He here assumes that extension (visible) is implied in the visible idea we call colour.236.This strikingly illustrates Berkeley's use of“idea,”and what he intends when he argues against“abstract”ideas.237.An interesting autobiographical fact. From childhood he was indisposed to take things on trust.238.Essay on Vision, sect. 88-119.239.“thoughts,”i.e. ideas of sense?240.This, in a crude way, is the distinction of δύναμις and ἐνέργεια. It helps to explain Berkeley's meaning, when he occasionally speaks of the ideas or phenomena that appear in the sense experience of different persons as if they were absolutely independent entities.241.To be“in an unperceiving thing,”i.e. to be real, yet unperceived. Whatever is perceived is, because realised only through a percipient act, anidea—in Berkeley's use of the word.242.This as to the“Platonic strain”is not in the tone ofSiris.243.John Keill (1671-1721), an eminent mathematician, educated at the University of Edinburgh; in 1710 Savilian Professor of Astronomy at Oxford, and the first to teach the Newtonian philosophy in that University. In 1708 he was engaged in a controversy in support of Newton's claims to the discovery of the method of fluxions.244.This suggests a negative argument for Kant's antinomies, and for Hamilton's law of the conditioned.245.Newton became Sir Isaac on April 16, 1705. Was this written before that date?246.These may beconsideredseparately, but notpicturedas such.247.In as far as they have not been sensibly realised in finite percipient mind.248.[Or rather that invisible length does exist.]—Author, on margin.249.Bonaventura Cavalieri (1598-1647), the Italian mathematician. HisGeometry of Indivisibles(1635) prepared the way for the Calculus.250.[By“the excuse”is meant the finiteness of our mind—making it possible for contradictions to appear true to us.]—Author, on margin.251.He allows elsewhere that words with meanings not realisable in imagination, i.e. in the form of idea, may discharge a useful office. SeePrinciples, Introduction, sect. 20.252.We do not perceive unperceived matter, but only matter realised in living perception—the percipient act being the factor of its reality.253.The secondary qualities of things.254.Because, while dependent on percipient sense, they are independent ofmypersonal will, being determined to appear under natural law, by Divine agency.255.Keill'sIntroductio ad veram Physicam(Oxon. 1702)—Lectio 5—a curious work, dedicated to the Earl of Pembroke.256.[Extension without breadth—i. e. insensible, intangible length—is not conceivable. 'Tis a mistake we are led into by the doctrine of abstraction.]—Author, on margin of MS.257.Here“Sir Isaac.”Hence written after April, 1705.258.Essay, Bk. IV. ch. iv. sect. 18; ch. v. sect. 3, &c.259.He appliesthingto self-conscious persons as well as to passive objects of sense.260.Scaligerana Secunda, p. 270.261.[These arguments must be proposed shorter and more separate in the Treatise.]—Author, on margin.262.“Idea”here used in its wider meaning—for“operations of mind,”as well as for sense presented phenomena that are independent of individual will. Cf.Principles, sect. 1.263.“sensations,”i.e. objective phenomena presented in sense.264.SeePrinciples, sect. 1.265.SeePrinciples, sect. 2.266.An“unperceiving thing”cannot be the factor of material reality.267.[To the utmost accuracy, wanting nothing of perfection.Theirsolutions of problems, themselves must own to fall infinitely short of perfection.]—Author, on margin.268.Jean de Billy and René de Billy, French mathematicians—the former author ofNova Geometriæ Clavisand other mathematical works.269.According to Baronius, in the fifth volume of his“Annals,”Ficinus appeared after death to Michael Mercatus—agreeably to a promise he made when he was alive—to assure him of the life of the human spirit after the death of the body.270.So far as we are factors of their reality, in sense and in science, or can be any practical way concerned with them.271.Cf.Principles, sect. 101-34.272.“something,”i.e.abstractsomething.273.Lord Pembroke (?)—to whom thePrincipleswere dedicated, and to whom Locke dedicated hisEssay.274.This is an interesting example of a feature that is conspicuous in Berkeley—the art of“humoring an opponent in his own way of thinking,”which it seems was an early habit. It is thus that he insinuates his New Principles in theEssay on Vision, and so prepares to unfold and defend them in the book ofPrinciplesand the threeDialogues—straining language to reconcile them with ordinary modes of speech.275.In Diderot'sLettre sur les aveugles, à l'usage de ceux qui voient, where Berkeley, Molyneux, Condillac, and others are mentioned. Cf. also Appendix, pp. 111, 112; andTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 71, with the note, in which some recorded experiments are alluded to.276.De Anima, II. 6, III. 1, &c. Aristotle assigns a pre-eminent intellectual value to the sense of sight. See, for instance, hisMetaphysics, I. 1.277.Sir A. Grant, (Ethics of Aristotle, vol. II. p. 172) remarks, as to the doctrine that the Common Sensibles are apprehended concomitantly by the senses, that:“this is surely the true view; we see in the apprehension of number, figure, and the like, not an operation of sense, but the mind putting its own forms and categories, i.e. itself, on the external object. It would follow then that the senses cannot really be separated from the mind; the senses and the mind each contribute an element to every knowledge. Aristotle's doctrine of κοινὴ αἴσθησις would go far, if carried out, to modify his doctrine of the simple and innate character of the senses, e.g. sight (cf.Eth.II. 1, 4), and would prevent its collision with Berkeley'sTheory of Vision.”—See also Sir W. Hamilton,Reid's Works, pp. 828-830.Dugald Stewart (Collected Works, vol. I. p. 341, note) quotes Aristotle'sEthics, II. 1, as evidence that Berkeley's doctrine,“with respect to the acquired perceptions of sight, was quite unknown to the best metaphysicians of antiquity.”278.A work resembling Berkeley's in its title, but in little else, appeared more than twenty years before theEssay—theNova Visionis Theoriaof Dr. Briggs, published in 1685.279.SeeTreatise on the Eye, vol. II. pp. 299, &c.280.See Reid'sInquiry, ch. v. §§ 3, 5, 6, 7; ch. vi. § 24, andEssays on the Intellectual Powers, II. ch. 10 and 19.281.While Sir W. Hamilton (Lectures on Metaphysics, lxxviii) acknowledges the scientific validity of Berkeley's conclusions, as to the way we judge of distances, he complains, in the same lecture, that“the whole question is thrown into doubt by the analogy of the lower animals,”i.e. by their probablevisual instinctof distances; and elsewhere (Reid'sWorks, p. 137, note) he seems to hesitate about Locke's Solution of Molyneux's Problem, at least in its application to Cheselden's case. Cf. Leibniz,Nouveaux Essais, Liv. II. ch. 9, in connexion with this last.282.An almost solitary exception in Britain to this unusual uniformity on a subtle question in psychology is found in Samuel Bailey'sReview of Berkeley's Theory of Vision, designed to show the unsoundness of that celebrated Speculation, which appeared in 1842. It was the subject of two interesting rejoinders—a well-weighed criticism, in theWestminster Review, by J.S. Mill, since republished in hisDiscussions; and an ingenious Essay by Professor Ferrier, inBlackwood's Magazine, republished in hisPhilosophical Remains. The controversy ended on that occasion with Bailey'sLetter to a Philosopher in reply to some recent attempts to vindicate Berkeley's Theory of Vision, and in further elucidation of its unsoundness, and a reply to it by each of his critics. It was revived in 1864 by Mr. Abbott of Trinity College, Dublin, whose essay onSight and Touchis“an attempt to disprove the received (or Berkeleian) Theory of Vision.”283.Afterwards (in 1733) Earl of Egmont. Born about 1683, he succeeded to the baronetcy in 1691, and, after sitting for a few years in the Irish House of Commons, was in 1715 created Baron Percival, in the Irish peerage. In 1732 he obtained a charter to colonise the province of Georgia in North America. His name appears in the list of subscribers to Berkeley's Bermuda Scheme in 1726. He died in 1748. He corresponded frequently with Berkeley from 1709 onwards.284.Similar terms are applied to the sense of seeing by writers with whom Berkeley was familiar. Thus Locke (Essay, II. ix. 9) refers to sight as“the most comprehensive of all our senses.”Descartes opens hisDioptriqueby designating it as“le plus universal et le plus noble de nos sens;”and he alludes to it elsewhere (Princip.IV. 195) as“le plus subtil de tous les sens.”Malebranche begins his analysis of sight (Recherche, I. 6) by describing it as“le premier, le plus noble, et le plus étendu de tous les sens.”The high place assigned to this sense by Aristotle has been already alluded to. Its office, as the chief organ through which a conception of the material universe as placed in ambient space is given to us, is recognised by a multitude of psychologists and metaphysicians.285.On Berkeley's originality in his Theory of Vision see the Editor's Preface.286.In the first edition alone this sentence followed:—“In treating of all which, it seems to me, the writers of Optics have proceeded on wrong principles.”287.Sect. 2-51 explain the way in which we learn in seeing to judge of Distance or Outness, and of objects as existing remote from our organism, viz. by their association with what we see, and with certain muscular and other sensations in the eye which accompany vision. Sect. 2 assumes, as granted, the invisibility of distance in the line of sight. Cf. sect. 11 and 88—First Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous—Alciphron, IV. 8—Theory of Vision Vindicated and Explained, sect. 62-69.288.i.e. outness, or distance outward from the point of vision—distance in the line of sight—the third dimension of space. Visible distance is visible space or interval between two points (see sect. 112). We can be sensibly percipient of it only whenbothpoints are seen.289.This section is adduced by some of Berkeley's critics as if it were the evidence discovered by him for hisTheory, instead of being, as it is, a passing reference to the scientific ground of the already acknowledged invisibility of outness, or distance in the line of sight. See, for example, Bailey'sReview of Berkeley's Theory of Vision, pp. 38-43, also hisTheory of Reasoning, p. 179 and pp. 200-7—Mill'sDiscussions, vol. II. p. 95—Abbott'sSight and Touch, p. 10, where this sentence is presented as“the sole positive argument advanced by Berkeley.”The invisibility of outness is not Berkeley's discovery, but the way we learn to interpret its visual signs, and what these are.290.i.e. aerial and linear perspective are acknowledged signs of remote distances. But the question, in this and the thirty-six following sections, concerns the visibility ofneardistances only—a few yards in front of us. It was“agreed by all”that beyond this limit distances are suggested by our experience of their signs.291.Cf. this and the four following sections with the quotations in the Editor's Preface, from Molyneux'sTreatise of Dioptrics.292.In the author's last edition we have this annotation:“See what Des Cartes and others have written upon the subject.”293.In the first edition this section opens thus:“I have here set down the common current accounts that are given of our perceiving near distances by sight, which, though they are unquestionably received for true by mathematicians, and accordingly made use of by them in determining the apparent places of objects, do nevertheless,”&c.294.Omitted in the author's last edition.295.i.e. although immediately invisible, it is mediately seen. Mark, here and elsewhere, the ambiguity of the termperception, which now signifies the act of being conscious of sensuous phenomena, and again the act of inferring phenomena of which we are at the time insentient; while it is also applied to the object perceived instead of to the percipient act; and sometimes to imagination, and the higher acts of intelligence.296.“Some men”—“mathematicians,”in first edition.297.i.e. themediateperception.298.“any man”—“all the mathematicians in the world,”in first edition.299.Omitted in the author's last edition.300.Omitted in the author's last edition.301.Sect. 3, 9.302.Observe the first introduction by Berkeley of the termsuggestion, used by him to express a leading factor in his account of the visible world, and again in his more comprehensive account of our knowledge of the material universe in thePrinciples. It had been employed occasionally, among others, by Hobbes and Locke. There are three ways in which the objects we have an immediate perception of in sight may be supposed to conduct us to what we do not immediately perceive: (1) Instinct, or what Reid calls“original suggestion”(Inquiry, ch. VI. sect. 20-24); (2) Custom; (3) Reasoning from accepted premisses. Berkeley's“suggestion”corresponds to the second. (Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 42.)303.In theTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 66, it is added that this“sensation”belongs properly to the sense of touch. Cf. also sect. 145 of thisEssay.304.Here“natural”=“necessary”: elsewhere=divinely arbitrary connexion.305.That ourmediatevision of outness and of objects as thus external, is due to media which have a contingent or arbitrary, instead of a necessary, connexion with the distances which they enable us to see, or of which they are the signs, is a cardinal part of his argument.306.Sect. 2.307.Here, as generally in theEssay, the appeal is to our inward experience, not to phenomena observed by our senses in the organism.308.See sect. 35 for the difference between confused and faint vision. Cf. sect. 32-38 with this section. AlsoTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 68.309.See sect. 6.310.These sections presuppose previous contiguity as an associative law of mental phenomena.311.See Reid'sInquiry, ch. vi. sect. 22.312.Sect. 16-27.—For the signs of remote distances, see sect. 3.313.These are muscular sensations felt in the organ, and degrees of confusion in a visible idea. Berkeley's“arbitrary”signs of distance, near and remote, are either (a) invisible states of the visual organ, or (b) visible appearances.314.In Molyneux'sTreatise of Dioptrics, Pt. I. prop. 31, sect. 9, Barrow's difficulty is stated. Cf. sect. 40 below.315.Christopher Scheiner, a German astronomer, and opponent of the Copernican system, born 1575, died 1650.316.Andrea Tacquet, a mathematician, born at Antwerp in 1611, and referred to by Molyneux as“the ingenious Jesuit.”He published a number of scientific treatises, most of which appeared after his death, in a collected form, at Antwerp in 1669.317.In what follows Berkeley tries to explain by his visual theory seeming contradictions which puzzled the mathematicians.318.This is offered as a verification of the theory that near distances are suggested, according to the order of nature, by non-resembling visual signs, contingently connected with real distance.319.Cf. sect. 78; alsoNew Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 31.320.Berkeley here passes from his proof of visual“suggestion”of all outward distances—i.e. intervals between extremes in the line of sight—by means of arbitrary signs, and considers the nature of visible externality. See note in Hamilton'sReid, p. 177, on the distinction between perception of the external world and perception of distance through the eye.321.See Descartes,Dioptrique, VI—Malebranche,Recherche, Liv. I. ch. 9, 3—Reid'sInquiry, VI. 11.322.Berkeley here begins to found, on the experienced connexion between extension and colour, and between visible and tangible extension, a proof thatoutnessis invisible. From Aristotle onwards it has been assumed that colour is the only phenomenon of which we are immediately percipient in seeing. Visible extension, visible figure, and visible motion are accordingly taken to be dependent on the sensation of colour.323.In connexion with this and the next illustration, Berkeley seems to argue that we are not only unable to see distance in the line of sight, but also that we do not see a distant object in itsreal visiblemagnitude. But elsewhere he affirms that onlytangiblemagnitude is entitled to be calledreal. Cf. sect. 55, 59, 61.324.The sceptical objections to the trustworthiness of the senses, proposed by the Eleatics and others, referred to by Descartes in hisMeditations, and by Malebranche in the First Book of hisRecherche, may have suggested the illustrations in this section. Cf. also Hume's EssayOn the Academical or Sceptical Philosophy. The sceptical difficulty is founded on the assumption that the object seen at different distances is thesame visible object: it is really different, and so the difficulty vanishes.325.Here Berkeley expressly introduces“touch”—a term which with him includes, not merely organic sense of contact, but also muscular and locomotive sense-experience. After this he begins to unfold the antithesis of visual and tactual phenomena, whose subsequent synthesis it is the aim of theNew Theoryto explain. Cf.Principles of Human Knowledge, sect. 43—Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 22 and 25. Note here Berkeley's reticence of his idealization of Matter—tangible as well as visible. Cf.Principles, sect. 44.326.This connexion of our knowledge of distance with our locomotive experience points to a theory which ultimately resolves space into experience of unimpeded locomotion.327.Locke (Essay, Introduction, § 8) takesideavaguely as“the term which serves best to stand whatsoever is the object of the understanding when a man thinks.”Oversight of what Berkeley intends the term idea has made his whole conception of nature and the material universe a riddle to many, of which afterwards.328.The expressive term“outness,”favoured by Berkeley, is here first used.329.“We get the idea of Space,”says Locke,“both by our sight and touch”(Essay, II. 13. § 2). Locke did not contemplate Berkeley's antithesis of visible and tangible extension, and the consequent ambiguity of the term extension; which sometimes signifiescoloured, and at othersresistantexperience in sense.330.For an explanation of this difficulty, see sect. 144.331.“object”—“thing,”in the earlier editions.332.This is the issue of the analytical portion of theEssay.333.Cf. sect. 139-40.334.Here the question of externality, signifying independence of all percipient life, is again mixed up with that of the invisibility of distance outwards in the line of sight.335.Omitted in author's last edition.336.i.e. including muscular and locomotive experience as well as sense of contact. But what are thetangibiliathemselves? Are they also significant, likevisibilia, of a still ulterior reality? This is the problem of thePrinciples of Human Knowledge.337.In this section the conception of a natural Visual Language, makes its appearance, with its implication that Nature is (for us) virtually Spirit. Cf. sect. 140, 147—Principles, sect. 44—Dialogues of Hylas and Philonous—Alciphron, IV. 8, 11—andTheory of Vision Vindicated, passim.338.Sect. 52-87 treat of the invisibility of real, i.e. tactual, Magnitude. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 54-61.339.Sect. 8-15.340.Sect. 41, &c.341.See Molyneux'sTreatise on Dioptrics, B. I. prop. 28.342.See sect. 122-126.343.In short there is a point at which, with our limited sense, we cease to be percipient of colour, in seeing; and of resistance, in locomotion. Though Berkeley regards all visible extensions as sensible, and therefore dependent for their reality on being realised by sentient mind, he does not mean that mind or consciousness is extended. With him, extension, though it exists only in mind,—i.e. as an idea seen, in the case of visible extension, and as an idea touched, in the case of tangible extension,—is yet nopropertyof mind. Mind can exist without being percipient of extension, although extension cannot be realised without mind.344.But this is true, though less obviously, of tangible as well as of visible objects.345.Sect. 49.346.Cf. sect. 139, 140, &c.347.“situation”—not in the earlier editions.348.Sect. 55.349.Omitted in the author's last edition.350.Ordinary sight is virtually foresight. Cf. sect. 85.—See also Malebranche on the external senses, as given primarily for the urgent needs of embodied life, not to immediately convey scientific knowledge,Recherche, Liv. I. ch. 5, 6, 9, &c.351.Sect. 44.—See also sect. 55, and note.352.This supposes“settled”tangibilia, but not“settled”visibilia. Yet the sensible extension given in touch and locomotive experience is also relative—an object beingfeltas larger or smaller according to the state of the organism, and the other conditions of our embodied perception.353.What follows, to end of sect. 63, added in the author's last edition.354.“outward objects,”i.e. objects of which we are percipient in tactual experience, taken in thisEssayprovisionally as the real external objects. SeePrinciples, sect. 44.355.Cf. sect. 144. Note, in this and the three preceding sections, the stress laid on thearbitrarinessof the connexion between the signs which suggest magnitudes, or other modes of extension, and their significates. This is the foundation of theNew Theory; which thus resolvesphysicalcausality into a relation of signs to what they signify and predict—analogous to the relation between words and their accepted meanings.356.In sect. 67-78, Berkeley attempts to verify the foregoing account of the natural signs of Size, by applying it to solve a phenomenon, the cause of which had been long debated among men of science—the visible magnitude of heavenly bodies when seen in the horizon.357.Cf. sect. 10.358.Omitted in the author's last edition. Cf sect. 76, 77.—The explanation in question is attributed to Alhazen, and by Bacon to Ptolemy, while it is sanctioned by eminent scientific names before and since Berkeley.359.“Fourthly”in the second edition. Cf. what follows with sect. 74. Why“lesser”?360.When Berkeley, some years afterwards, visited Italy, he remarked that distant objects appeared to him much nearer than they really were—a phenomenon which he attributed to the comparative purity of the southern air.361.i.e. the original perception, apart from any synthetic operation of suggestion and inferential thought, founded on visual signs.362.In Riccioli'sAlmagest, II. lib. X. sect. 6. quest. 14, we have an account of many hypotheses then current, in explanation of the apparent magnitude of the horizontal moon.363.Gassendi's“Epistolæ quatuor de apparente magnitudine solis humilis et sublimis.”—Opera, tom. III pp. 420-477. Cf. Appendix to thisEssay, p. 110.364.SeeDioptrique, VI.365.Opera Latina, vol. I, p. 376, vol. II, pp. 26-62;English Works, vol. I. p. 462. (Molesworth's Edition.)366.The paper in the Transactions is by Molyneux.367.See Smith'sOptics, pp. 64-67, andRemarks, pp. 48, &c. At p. 55 Berkeley'sNew Theoryis referred to, and pronounced to be at variance with experience. Smith concludes by saying, that in“the second edition of Berkeley'sEssay, and also in a Vindication and Explanation of it (called theVisual Language), very lately published, the author has made some additions to his solution of the said phenomenon; but seeing it still involves and depends on the principle of faintness, I may leave the rest of it to the reader's consideration.”This, which appeared in 1738, is one of the very few early references to Berkeley'sNew Theory of Vision Vindicated.368.Sect. 2-51.369.This sentence is omitted in the author's last edition.370.What follows to the end of this section is not contained in the first edition.371.i.e. tangible.372.Cf. sect. 38; andTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 31.373.“Never”—“hardly,”in first edition.374.Cf. Appendix, p.208.—See Smith'sOptics, B. I. ch. v, andRemarks, p. 56, in which he“leaves it to be considered, whether the said phenomenon is not as clear an instance of the insufficiency of faintness”as of mathematical computation.375.A favourite doctrine with Berkeley, according to whose theory of visibles there can be no absolute visible magnitude, theminimumbeing the least that isperceivableby each seeing subject, and thus relative to his visual capacity. This section is thus criticised, in January, 1752, in a letter signed“Anti-Berkeley,”in theGent. Mag.(vol. XXII, p. 12):“Upon what his lordship asserts with respect to theminimum visibile, I would observe that it is certain that there are infinite numbers of animals which are imperceptible to the naked eye, and cannot be perceived but by the help of a microscope; consequently there are animals whose whole bodies are far less than theminimum visibileof a man. Doubtless these animals have eyes, and, if theirminimum visibilewere equal to that of a man, it would follow that they cannot perceive anything but what is much larger than their whole body; and therefore their own bodies must be invisible to them, because we know they are so to men, whoseminimum visibileis asserted by his lordship to be equal to theirs.”There is some misconception in this. Cf. Appendix toEssay, p. 209.376.Those two defects belong to human consciousness. See Locke'sEssay, II. 10, on the defects of human memory. It is this imperfection which makes reasoning needful—to assist finite intuition. Reasoning is the sign at once of our dignity and our weakness.377.Sect. 59.378.Sect. 80-82.379.Sect. 88-119 relate to the nature, invisibility, and arbitrary visual signs of Situation, or of the localities of tangible things. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 44-53.380.Cf. sect. 2, 114, 116, 118.381.This illustration is taken from Descartes. See Appendix.382.Sect. 10 and 19.383.Sect. 2-51.384.Omitted in author's last edition.385.This is Berkeley's universal solvent of the psychological difficulties involved in visual-perception.386.Cf. sect. 103, 106, 110, 128, &c. Berkeley treats this case hypothetically in theEssay, in defect of actual experiments upon the born-blind, since accumulated from Cheselden downwards. See however the Appendix, andTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 71.387.i.e. tangible things. Cf.Principles, sect. 44.388.The“prejudice,”to wit, which Berkeley would dissolve by his introspective analysis of vision. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 35.389.Thus forming individual concrete things out of what is perceived separately through different senses.390.This briefly is Berkeley's solution of“the knot about inverted images,”which long puzzled men of science.391.i.e. perceivemediately—visible objects,per se, having no tactual situation. Pure vision, he would say, has nothing to do with“high”and“low,”“great”and“inverted,”in the real or tactual meaning of those terms.392.i.e. tangible.393.e.g.“extension,”which, according to Berkeley, is an equivocal term, common (in its different meanings) tovisibiliaandtangibilia. Cf. sect. 139, 140.394.Cf. sect. 93, 106, 110, 128.395.i.e. real or tangible head.396.Cf. sect. 140, 143. In theGent. Mag.(vol. XXII. p. 12),“Anti-Berkeley”thus argues the case of one born blind.“This man,”he adds,“would, by being accustomed to feel one hand with the other, have perceived that the extremity of the hand was divided into fingers—that the extremities of these fingers were distinguished by certain hard, smooth surfaces, of a different texture from the rest of the fingers—and that each finger had certain joints or flexures. Now, if this man was restored to sight, and immediately viewed his hand before he touched it again, it is manifest that the divisions of the extremity of the hand into fingers would be visibly perceived. He would note too the small spaces at the extremity of each finger, which affected his sight differently from the rest of the fingers; upon moving his fingers he would see the joints. Though therefore, by means of this lately acquired sense of seeing, the object affected his mind in a new and different manner from what it did before, yet, as bytouchhe had acquired the knowledge of these several divisions, marks, and distinctions of the hand, and, as the new object ofsightappeared to be divided, marked, and distinguished in a similar manner, I think he would certainly conclude,before he touched his hand, that the thing which he now saw wasthe samewhich he had felt before and called his hand.”397.Locke,Essay, II. 8, 16. Aristotle regards number as a Common Sensible.—De Anima, II. 6, III. 1.398.“If the visible appearance of two shillings had been found connected from the beginning with the tangible idea of one shilling, that appearance would as naturally and readily have signified the unity of the (tangible) object as it now signifies its duplicity.”Reid,Inquiry, VI. 11.399.Here again note Berkeley's inconvenient reticence of his full theory of matter, as dependent on percipient life for its reality. Tangible things are meantime granted to be real“without mind.”Cf.Principles, sect. 43, 44.“Without the mind”—in contrast to sensuous phenomenon only.400.Cf. sect. 131.401.Sect. 2, 88, 116, 118.402.In short, weseeonlyquantities of colour—the real or tactual distance, size, shape, locality, up and down, right and left, &c., being gradually associated with the various visible modifications of colour.403.i.e. tangible.404.Sect. 41-44.405.i.e. tangible things.406.i.e. visible.407.Cf. sect. 41-44. The“eyes”—visible and tangible—are themselves objects of sense.408.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 21-25.409.“Visible ideas”—including sensations muscular and locomotive,feltin the organ of vision. Sect. 16, 27, 57.410.i.e. objects which, in this tentativeEssay, are granted, for argument's sake, to be external, or independent of percipient mind.411.i.e. to inquire whether there are, in this instance, Common Sensibles; and, in particular, whether anextensionof the same kind at least, if not numerically the same, is presented in each. The Kantian theory of ana prioriintuition of space, the common condition of tactual and visual experience, because implied in sense-experience as such, is not conceived by Berkeley. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 15.412.In the following reasoning against abstract, as distinguished from concrete or sense presented (visible or tangible) extension, Berkeley urges some of his favourite objections to“abstract ideas,”fully unfolded in hisPrinciples, Introduction, sect. 6-20.—See alsoAlciphron, VII. 5-8.—Defence of Free Thinking in Mathematics, sect. 45-48.413.Berkeley'sideasare concrete or particular—immediate data of sense or imagination.414.i.e. it cannot be individualized, either as a perceived or an imagined object.415.Sect. 105.416.“Endeavours”in first edition.417.i.e. a mental image of an abstraction, an impossible image, in which the extension and comprehension of the notion must be adequately pictured.418.“deservedly admired author,”in the first edition.419.“this celebrated author,”—“that great man”in second edition. In assailing Locke's“abstract idea,”he discharges the meaning which Locke intended by the term, and then demolishes his own figment.420.Omitted in the author's last edition.421.Omitted in last edition.422.Omitted in last edition.423.Omitted in last edition.424.SeePrinciples, passim.425.Omitted in author's last edition.426.He probably has Locke in his eye.427.On Berkeley's theory, space without relation to bodies (i.e. insensible or abstract space) would not be extended, as not having parts; inasmuch as parts can be assigned to it only with relation to bodies. Berkeley does not distinguish space from sensible extension. Cf. Reid'sWorks, p. 126, note—in which Sir W. Hamilton suggests that one may have ana prioriconception of pure space, andalsoana posterioriperception of finite, concrete space.428.Sect. 121. Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 15.429.i.e. there are no Common Sensibles: from which it follows that we can reason from the one sense to the other only by founding on the constant connexion of their respective phenomena, under a natural yet (for us) contingent law. Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 27, 28.430.Omitted in last edition.431.Cf. sect. 93, 103, 106, 110.432.Omitted in last edition.433.Cf. sect. 43, 103, &c. A plurality of co-existentminimaof coloured points constitutes Berkeley's visible extension; while a plurality of successively experiencedminimaof resistant points constitutes his tactual extension. Whether we can perceive visible extension without experience of muscular movement at least in the eye, he does not here say.434.Omitted in last edition.435.Real distance belongs originally, according to theEssay, to our tactual experience only—in the wide meaning of touch, which includes muscular and locomotive perceptions, as well as the simple perception of contact.436.Added in second edition.437.Omitted in last edition.438.See also Locke's“Correspondence”with Molyneux, in Locke'sWorks, vol. IX. p. 34.—Leibniz,Nouveaux Essais, Liv. II. ch. 9, who, so far granting the fact, disputes the heterogeneity.—Smith'sOptics.—Remarks, §§ 161-170.—Hamilton's Reid, p. 137, note, andLect. Metaph.II. p. 176.439.Omitted in last edition.440.Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 70.441.Cf. sect. 49, 146, &c. Here“same”includes“similar.”442.i.e. visible and tangible motions being absolutely heterogeneous, and the former,at man's point of view, only contingent signs of the latter, we should not, at first sight, be able to interpret the visual signs of tactual phenomena.443.Cf. sect. 122-125.444.Cf.Principles, sect. 111-116; alsoAnalyst, query 12. On Berkeley's system space in its three dimensions is unrealisable without experience of motion.445.Here the term“language of nature”makes its appearance, as applicable to the ideas or visual signs of tactual realities.446.Cf. sect. 16, 27, 97.447.Is“tangible”here used in its narrow meaning—excluding muscular and locomotive experience?448.i.e. as natural signs, divinely associated with their thus implied meanings.449.Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 35.450.Berkeley, in this section, enunciates the principal conclusion in theEssay, which conclusion indeed forms his new theory of Vision.451.A suggestion thus due to natural laws of association. The explanation of the fact that we apprehend, by those ideas or phenomena which are objects of sight, certain other ideas, which neither resemble them, nor efficiently cause them, nor are so caused by them, nor have any necessary connexion with them, comprehends, according to Berkeley, the whole Theory of Vision.“The imagination of every thinking person,”remarks Adam Smith,“will supply him with instances to prove that the ideas received by any one of the senses do readily excite such other ideas, either of the same sense or of any other, as have habitually been associated with them. So that if, on this account, we are to suppose, with a late ingenious writer, that the ideas of sight constitute a Visual Language, because they readily suggest the corresponding ideas of touch—as the terms of a language excite the ideas answering to them—I see not but we may, for the same reason, allow of a tangible, audible, gustatory, and olefactory language; though doubtless the Visual Language will be abundantly more copious than the rest.”Smith'sOptics.—Remarks, p. 29.—And into this conception of a universal sense symbolism, Berkeley's theory of Vision ultimately rises.452.Cf.Alciphron, Dialogue IV. sect. 11-15.453.Sect. 122-125.454.Sect. 127-138.455.Some modern metaphysicians would say, that neither tangible nor visible extension is the object geometry, but abstract extension; and others that space is a necessary implicate of sense-experience, rather than,per se, an object of any single sense. Cf. Kant's explanation of the origin of our mathematical knowledge,Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Elementarlehre, I.456.Cf. sect. 51-66, 144.457.This is a conjecture, not as to the probable ideas of one born blind, but as to the ideas of an“unbodied”intelligence, whoseonlysense was that of seeing. See Reid's speculation (Inquiry, VI. 9) on the“Geometry of Visibles,”and the mental experience of Idomenians, or imaginary beings supposed to have no ideas of the material world except those got by seeing.458.Cf. sect. 130, andNew Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 57. Does Berkeley, in this and the two preceding sections, mean to hint that the only proper object of sight isunextendedcolour; and that, apart from muscular movement in the eye or other locomotion,visibiliaresolve into unextended mathematical points? This question has not escaped more recent British psychologists, including Stewart, Brown, Mill, and Bain, who seem to hold that unextended colour is perceivable and imaginable.459.The bracketed sentence is not retained in the author's last edition, in which the first sentence of sect. 160 is the concluding one of sect. 159, and of theEssay.460.This passage is contained in theDioptricesof Descartes, VI. 13; see also VI. 11.461.The arbitrariness or contingency—as far as our knowledge carries us—of the connexion between the visual phenomena, as signs, on the one hand, and actual distance, as perceived through this means, on the other.462.Cf. sect. 80-83.463.The reference here seems to be to the case described in theTatler(No. 55) of August 16, 1709, in which William Jones, born blind, had received sight after a surgical operation, at the age of twenty, on the 29th of June preceding. A medical narrative of this case appeared, entitledA full and true account of a miraculous cure of a Young Man in Newington, who was born blind, and was in five minutes brought to perfect sight, by Mr. Roger Grant, oculist. London, 1709.464.Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 71, with the relative note.465.Omitted on the title-page in the second edition, but retained in the body of the work.466.Beardsley'sLife and Correspondence of Samuel Johnson, D.D., First President of King's College, New York, p. 72 (1874).467.Beardsley'sLife of Johnson, pp. 71, 72.468.Chandler'sLife of Johnson, Appendix, p. 161.469.Commonplace Book.470.Moreover, even if the outness or distance of thingswerevisible, it would not follow that either they or their distances could be real if unperceived. On the contrary, Berkeley implies that theyareperceivedvisually.471.It is also to be remembered that sensible things exist“in mind,”without being exclusivelymine, as creatures ofmy will. In one sense, that only is mine in which my will exerts itself. But, in another view, my involuntary states of feeling and imagination aremine, because their existence depends on my consciousness of them; and even sensible things are so farmine, because, though present in many minds in common, they are, for me, dependent onmypercipient mind.472.Thomas Herbert, eighth Earl of Pembroke and fifth Earl of Montgomery, was the correspondent and friend of Locke—who dedicated his famousEssayto him, as a work“having some little correspondence with some parts of that nobler and vast system of the sciences your lordship has made so new, exact, and instructive a draft of.”He represents a family renowned in English political and literary history. He was born in 1656; was a nobleman of Christ Church, Oxford, in 1672; succeeded to his titles in 1683; was sworn of the Privy Council in 1689; and made a Knight of the Garter in 1700. He filled some of the highest offices in the state, in the reigns of William and Mary, and of Anne. He was Lord Lieutenant of Ireland in 1707, having previously been one of the Commissioners by whom the union between England and Scotland was negotiated. He died in January 1733.473.Trinity College, Dublin.474.In hisCommonplace BookBerkeley seems to refer his speculations to his boyhood. The conception of the material world propounded in the following Treatise was in his view before the publication of theNew Theory of Vision, which was intended to prepare the way for it.475.Cf. Locke, in the“Epistle Dedicatory”of hisEssay. Notwithstanding the“novelty”of the New Principles, viz.negationof abstract or unperceived Matter, Space, Time, Substance, and Power; andaffirmationof Mind, as the Synthesis, Substance, and Cause of all—much in best preceding philosophy, ancient and modern, was a dim anticipation of it.476.Cf. sect. 6, 22, 24, &c., in illustration of the demonstrative claim of Berkeley's initial doctrine.477.Berkeley entreats his reader, here and throughout, to take pains to understand his meaning, and especially to avoid confounding the ordered ideas or phenomena, objectively presented to our senses, with capricious chimeras of imagination.478.“Philosophy is nothing but the true knowledge of things.”Locke.479.The purpose of those early essays of Berkeley was to reconcile philosophy with common sense, by employing reflection to makelatentcommon sense, or common reason, reveal itself in its genuine integrity. Cf. the closing sentences in theThird Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.480.Cf. Locke'sEssay, Introduction, sect. 4-7; Bk. II. ch. 23, § 12, &c. Locke (who is probably here in Berkeley's eye) attributes the perplexities of philosophy to our narrow faculties, which are meant to regulate our lives, not to remove all mysteries. See also Descartes,Principia, I. 26, 27, &c.; Malebranche,Recherche, III. 2.481.His most significant forerunners were Descartes in hisPrincipia, and Locke in hisEssay.482.Here“idea”and“notion”seem to be used convertibly. See sect. 142. Cf. with the argument againstabstract ideas, unfolded in the remainder of the Introduction,Principles, sect. 97-100, 118-132, 143;New Theory of Vision, sect. 122-125;Alciphron, Dial. vii. 5-7;Defence of Free Thinking in Mathematics, sect. 45-48. AlsoSiris, sect. 323, 335, &c., where he distinguishes Idea in a higher meaning from his sensuous ideas. As mentioned in my Preface, the third edition ofAlciphron, published in 1752, the year before Berkeley died, omits the three sections of the Seventh Dialogue which repeat the following argument against abstract ideas.483.As in Derodon'sLogica, Pt. II. c. 6, 7;Philosophia Contracta, I. i. §§ 7-11; and Gassendi,Leg. Instit., I. 8; also Cudworth,Eternal and Immutable Morality, Bk. IV.484.Omitted in second edition.485.We must remember that what Berkeley intends by anideais either a percept of sense, or a sensuous imagination; and his argument is that none ofthesecan be an abstraction. We can neither perceive nor imagine what is not concrete and part of a succession.486.“abstract notions”—here used convertibly with“abstract ideas.”Cf.Principles, sect. 89 and 142, on the special meaning ofnotion.487.Supposed by Berkeley to mean, that we can imagine, in abstraction from all phenomena presented in concrete experience, e.g. imagineexistence, in abstraction from all phenomena in which it manifests itself to us; ormatter, stripped of all the phenomena in which it is realised in sense.488.Omitted in second edition.489.Locke.490.Descartes, who regarded brutes as (sentient?) machines.491.“To this I cannot assent, being of opinion that a word,”&c.—in first edition.492.“an idea,”i.e. a concrete mental picture.493.So that“generality”in an idea is our“consideration”of a particular idea (e.g. a“particular motion”or a“particular extension”) notper se, but under general relations, which that particular idea exemplifies, and which, as he shews, may be signified by a corresponding word. All ideas (in Berkeley's confined meaning of“idea”) are particular. We rise above particular ideas by an intellectual apprehension of their relations; not by formingabstract pictures, which are contradictory absurdities.494.Locke is surely misconceived. He does not say, as Berkeley seems to suppose, that in forming“abstract ideas,”we are forming abstract mental images—pictures in the mind that are not individual pictures.495.Does Locke intend more than this, although he expresses his meaning in ambiguous words?496.It is a particular idea, but considered relatively—asignificantparticular idea, in other words. We realise our notions in examples, and these must be concrete.497.i.e.“ideas”in Locke's meaning of idea, under which he comprehends, not only the particular ideas of sense and imagination—Berkeley's“ideas”—but these considered relatively, and so seen intellectually, when Locke calls them abstract, general, or universal. Omniscience in its all-comprehensive intuition may not require, or even admit, such general ideas.498.Here and in what follows,“abstractnotion,”“universalnotion,”instead of abstractidea. Notion seems to be here a synonym for idea, and not taken in the special meaning which he afterwards attached to the term, when he contrasted it with idea.499.“notions,”again synonymous with ideas, which are all particular or concrete, in his meaning ofidea, when he uses it strictly.500.idea, i.e. individual mental picture.501.In all this he takes no account of the intellectual relations necessarily embodied in concrete knowledge, and without which experience could not cohere.502.“have in view,”i.e. actually realise in imagination.503.What follows, to the end of this section, was added in the second or 1734 edition.504.So Bacon in many passages of hisDe Augmentis ScientiariumandNovum Organum.505.“wide influence,”—“wide and extended sway”—in first edition.506.“idea,”i.e. individual datum of sense or of imagination.507.See Leibniz on Symbolical Knowledge (Opera Philosophica, pp. 79, 80, Erdmann), and Stewart in hisElements, vol. I. ch. 4, § 1, on our habit of using language without realising, in individual examples or ideas, the meanings of the common terms used.508.“doth”—“does,”here and elsewhere in first edition.509.“ideas,”i.e. representations in imagination ofanyof the individual objects to which the names are applicable. The sound or sight of a verbal sign may do duty for the concrete idea in which the notion signified by the word might be exemplified.510.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.511.Elsewhere he mentions Aristotle as“certainly a great admirer and promoter of the doctrine of abstraction,”and quotes his statement that there is hardly anything so incomprehensible to men as notions of the utmost universality; for they are the most remote from sense.Metaph., Bk. I. ch. 2.512.Added in second edition.513.Omitted in second edition.514.Omitted in second edition.515.Omitted in second edition.516.“my own ideas,”i.e. the concrete phenomena which I can realise as perceptions of sense, or in imagination.517.He probably refers to Locke.518.According to Locke,“that which has most contributed to hinder the due tracing of our ideas, and finding out their relations, and agreements or disagreements one with another, has been, I suppose, the ill use of words. It is impossible that men should ever truly seek, or certainly discover, the agreement or disagreement of ideas themselves, whilst their thoughts flutter about, or stick only in sounds of doubtful and uncertain significations. Mathematicians, abstracting their thoughts from names, and accustoming themselves to set before their minds the ideas themselves that they would consider, and not sounds instead of them, have avoided thereby a great part of that perplexity, puddering, and confusion which has so much hindered men's progress in other parts of knowledge.”Essay, Bk. IV. ch. 3, § 30. See also Bk. III. ch. 10, 11.519.General names involve in their signification intellectual relations among ideas or phenomena; but the relations,per se, are unimaginable.520.The rough draft of the Introduction, prepared two years before the publication of thePrinciples(see Appendix, vol. III), should be compared with the published version. He there tells that“there was a time when, being bantered and abused by words,”he“did not in the least doubt”that he was“able to abstract his ideas”; adding that“after a strict survey of my abilities, I not only discovered my own deficiency on this point, but also cannot conceive it possible that such a power should be even in the most perfect and exalted understanding.”What he thus pronounces“impossible,”is asensuousperception or imagination of an intellectual relation, as to which most thinkers would agree with him. But in so arguing, he seems apt to discard the intellectual relations themselves that are necessarily embodied in experience.David Hume refers thus to Berkeley's doctrine about“abstract ideas”:—“A great philosopher has asserted that all general ideas are nothing but particular ones annexed to a certain term, which gives them a more extensive signification. I look upon this to be one of the greatest and most valuable discoveries that has been made of late years in the republic of letters.”(Treatise of H. N.Pt. I, sect. 7.)521.This resembles Locke's account of the ideas with which human knowledge is concerned. They are all originally presented to the senses, or got by reflexion upon the passions and acts of the mind; and the materials contributed in this external and internal experience are, with the help of memory and imagination, elaborated by the human understanding in ways innumerable, true and false. See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II, ch. 1, §§ 1-5; ch. 10, 11, 12.522.The ideas or phenomena of which we are percipient in our five senses make their appearance, not isolated, but in individual masses, constituting the things, that occupy their respective places in perceived ambient space. It is asqualitiesofthingsthat the ideas or phenomena of sense arise in human experience.523.This is an advance upon the language of theCommonplace Book, in which“mind”is spoken of as only a“congeries of perceptions.”Here it is something“entirely distinct”from ideas or perceptions, in which they exist and are perceived, and on which they ultimately depend. Spirit, intelligent and active, presupposed with its implicates in ideas, thus becomes the basis of Berkeley's philosophy. Is this subjective idealism only? Locke appears in sect. 1, Descartes, if not Kant by anticipation, in sect. 2.524.This sentence expresses Berkeley's New Principle, which filled his thoughts in theCommonplace Book. Note“inamind,”not necessarily inmymind.525.That is to say, one has only to put concrete meaning into the termsexistenceandreality, in order to have“an intuitive knowledge”that matter depends for its real existence on percipient spirit.526.In other words, the things of sense become real, only in the concrete experience of living mind, which gives them the only reality we can conceive or have any sort of concern with. Extinguish Spirit and the material world necessarily ceases to be real.527.Thatesseispercipiis Berkeley's initial Principle, called“intuitive”or self-evident.528.Mark that it is the“natural or real existence”of the material world, in the absence of all realising Spirit, that Berkeley insists is impossible—meaningless.529.“our own”—yet not exclusivelymine. They depend for their reality uponapercipient, not onmyperception.530.“this tenet,”i.e. that the concrete material world could still be a reality after the annihilation of all realising spiritual life in the universe—divine or other.531.“existing unperceived,”i.e. existing without being realised in any living percipient experience—existing in a totally abstract existence, whatever that can mean.532.“notions”—a term elsewhere (see sect. 27, 89, 142) restricted, is here applied to the immediate data of the senses—the ideas of sense.533.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.534.In the first edition, instead of this sentence, we have the following:“To make this appear with all the light and evidence of an Axiom, it seems sufficient if I can but awaken the reflexion of the reader, that he may take an impartial view of his own meaning, and turn his thoughts upon the subject itself; free and disengaged from all embarras of words and prepossession in favour of received mistakes.”535.In other words, active percipient Spirit is at the root of all intelligible trustworthy experience.536.'proof'—“demonstration”in first edition; yet he calls it“intuitive.”537.“the ideas themselves,”i.e. the phenomena immediately presented in sense, and that are thus realised in and through the percipient experience of living mind, as their factor.538.As those say who assume that perception is ultimately only representative of the material reality, the very things themselves not making their appearance to us at all.539.He refers especially to Locke, whose account of Matter is accordingly charged with being incoherent.540.“inert.”See theDe Motu.541.“ideas existing in the mind,”i.e. phenomena of whichsomemind is percipient; which are realised in the sentient experience of a living spirit, human or other.542.What follows to the end of the section is omitted in the second edition.543.“the existence of Matter,”i.e. the existence of the material world, regarded as a something that does not need to be perceived in order to be real.544.Sometimes calledobjectivequalities, because they are supposed to be realised in an abstract objectivity, which Berkeley insists is meaningless.545.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II, ch. 8, §§ 13, 18; ch. 23, § 11; Bk. IV, ch. 3, § 24-26. Locke suggests this relation between the secondary and the primary qualities of matter only hypothetically.546.“in the mind, and nowhere else,”i.e. perceived or conceived, but in no other manner can they be real or concrete.547.“without the mind,”i.e. independently of all percipient experience.548.Extension is thus the distinguishing characteristic of the material world. Geometrical and physical solidity, as well as motion, imply extension.549.“number is the creature of the mind,”i.e. is dependent on being realised in percipient experience. This dependence is here illustrated by the relation of concrete number to the point of view of each mind; as the dependence of the other primary qualities was illustrated by their dependence on the organisation of the percipient. In this, the preceding, and the following sections, Berkeley argues the inconsistency of the abstract reality attributed to the primary qualities with their acknowledged dependence on the necessary conditions of sense perception.550.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 109.551.e.g. Locke,Essay, Bk. II, ch. 7, § 7; ch. 16, § 1.552.“without any alteration in any external object”—“without any external alteration”—in first edition.553.These arguments, founded on the mind-dependent nature ofallthe qualities of matter, are expanded in theFirst Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.554.“an outward object,”i.e. an object wholly abstract from living Mind.555.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.556.“reason,”i.e. reasoning. It is argued, in this and the next section, that a reality unrealised in percipient experience cannot be proved, either by our senses or by reasoning.557.Omitted in the second edition, and the sentence converted into a question.558.But the ideas of which we are cognizant in waking dreams, and dreams of sleep, differ in important characteristics from the external ideas of which we are percipient in sense. Cf. sect. 29-33.559.“external bodies,”i.e. bodies supposed to be real independently of all percipients in the universe.560.i.e. they cannot shew how their unintelligible hypothesis of Matter accounts for the experience we have, or expect to have; or which we believe other persons have, or to be about to have.561.“the production,”&c., i.e. the fact that we and others have percipient experience.562.Mind-dependent Matter he not only allows to exist, but maintains its reality to be intuitively evident.563.i.e. bodies existing in abstraction from living percipient spirit.564.“Matter,”i.e. abstract Matter, unrealised in sentient intelligence.565.The appeal here and elsewhere is to consciousness—directly in each person's experience, and indirectly in that of others.566.i.e. otherwise than in the form of an idea or actual appearance presented to our senses.567.This implies that the material world may be realised in imagination as well as in sensuous perception, but in a less degree of reality; for reality, he assumes, admits of degrees.568.“to conceive the existence of external bodies,”i.e. to conceive bodies that are not conceived—that are not ideas at all, but which exist in abstraction. To suppose what we conceive to be unconceived, is to suppose a contradiction.569.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.570.“The existence of things without mind,”or in the absence of all spiritual life and perception, is what Berkeley argues against, asmeaningless, if notcontradictory; not the existence of a material world, when this means the realised order of nature, regulated independently of individual will, and to which our actions must conform if we are to avoid physical pain.571.Here againnotionis undistinguished fromidea.572.This and the three following sections argue for the essential impotence of matter, and that, as far as we are concerned, so-called“natural causes”are onlysignswhich foretell the appearance of their so-called effects. The material world is presented to our senses as a procession of orderly, and therefore interpretable, yet in themselves powerless, ideas or phenomena: motion is always an effect, never an originating active cause.573.As Locke suggests.574.This tacitly presupposes the necessity in reason of the Principle of Causality, or the ultimate need for an efficient cause of every change. To determine the sort of Causation that constitutes and pervades the universe is the aim of his philosophy.575.In other words, the material world is not only real in and through percipient spirit, but the changing forms which its phenomena assume, in the natural evolution, are the issue of the perpetual activity of in-dwelling Spirit. The argument in this section requires a deeper criticism of its premisses.576.In other words, an agent cannot, as such, be perceived or imagined, though its effects can. The spiritual termagentis not meaningless; yet we have nosensuous ideaof its meaning.577.Omitted in second edition.578.This sentence is not contained in the first edition. It is remarkable for first introducing the termnotion, to signifyidealess meaning, as in the words soul, active power, &c. Here he says that“the operations of the mind”belong to notions, while, in sect. 1, he speaks of“ideasperceived by attending to the‘operations’of the mind.”579.“ideas,”i.e. fancies of imagination; as distinguished from the more real ideas or phenomena that present themselves objectively to our senses.580.With Berkeley the world of external ideas is distinguished from Spirit by its essential passivity. Active power is with him the essence of Mind, distinguishing me from the changing ideas of which I am percipient. We must not attribute free agency to phenomena presented to our senses.581.In this and the four following sections, Berkeley mentionsmarksby which the ideas or phenomena that present themselves to the senses may be distinguished from all other ideas, in consequence of which they may be termed“external,”while those of feeling and imagination are wholly subjective or individual.582.This mark—the superior strength and liveliness of the ideas or phenomena that are presented to the senses—was afterwards noted by Hume. SeeInquiry concerning Human Understanding, sect. II.583.Berkeley here and always insists on thearbitrarycharacter of“settled laws”of change in the world, as contrasted with“necessary connexions”discovered in mathematics. The material world is thus virtually an interpretable natural language, constituted in what, at our point of view, isarbitrarinessorcontingency.584.Under this conception of the universe,“second causes”aredivinely established signsof impending changes, and are only metaphorically called“causes.”585.So Schiller, inDon Carlos, Act III, where he represents sceptics as failing to see the God who veils Himself in everlasting laws. But in truth God is eternal law or order vitalised and moralised.586.“sensations,”with Berkeley, are not mere feelings, but in a sense external appearances.587.“morereality.”This implies that reality admits of degrees, and that the difference between the phenomena presented to the senses and those which are only imagined is a difference in degree of reality.588.In the preceding sections, two relations should be carefully distinguished—that of the material world to percipient mind, in which it becomesreal; and that between changes in the world and spiritual agency. These are Berkeley's two leading Principles. The first conducts to and vindicates the second—inadequately, however, apart from explication of their root in moral reason. The former gives a relationsui generis. The latter gives our only example of active causality—the natural order of phenomena being the outcome of the causal energy of intending Will.589.Sect. 34-84 contain Berkeley's answers to supposedobjectionsto the foregoing Principles concerning Matter and Spirit in their mutual relations.590.To be an“idea”is, with Berkeley, to be the imaginable object of a percipient spirit. But he does not define precisely the relation of ideas to mind.“Existence in mind”is existencein this relation. His question (which he determines in the negative) is, the possibility of concrete phenomena, naturally presented to sense,yet out of all relation to living mind.591.Omitted in second edition.592.i.e. of imagination. Cf. sect. 28-30.593.Cf. sect. 29.594.“more reality.”This again implies that reality admits of degrees. What is perceived in sense is more real than what is imagined, and eternal realities are more deeply real than the transitory things of sense.595.Cf. sect. 33.“Not fictions,”i.e. they are presentative, and therefore cannot misrepresent.596.With Berkeleysubstanceis either (a) active reason, i.e. spirit—substance proper, or (b) an aggregate of sense-phenomena, called a“sensible thing”—substance conventionally and superficially.597.And which, because realised in living perception, are calledideas—to remind us that reality is attained in and through percipient mind.598.“combined together,”i.e. in the form of“sensible things,”according to natural laws. Cf. sect. 33.599.“thinking things”—more appropriately calledpersons.600.Berkeley uses the word idea to mark the fact, that sensible things are real only as they manifest themselves in the form of passive objects, presented to sense-percipient mind; but he does not, as popularly supposed, regard“sensible things”as created and regulated by the activity of his own individual mind. They are perceived, but are neither created nor regulated, by the individual percipient, and are thuspractically externalto each person.601.Cf. sect. 87-91, against the scepticism which originates in alleged fallacy of sense.602.Omitted in second edition.603.It is always to be remembered that with Berkeley ideas or phenomena presented to sense arethemselvesthe real things, whilst ideas of imagination are representative (or misrepresentative).604.Here feelings of pleasure or pain are spoken of, without qualification, as in like relation to living mind as sensible things or ideas are.605.That the ideas of sense should be seen“at a distance of several miles”seems not inconsistent with their being dependent on a percipient, if ambient space isitself(as Berkeley asserts) dependent on percipient experience. Cf. sect. 67.606.In the preceding year.607.Essay, sect. 2.608.Ibid. sect. 11-15.609.Ibid. sect. 16-28.610.Ibid. sect. 51.611.Ibid. sect. 47-49, 121-141.612.Ibid. sect. 43.613.i.e. what we areimmediatelypercipient of in seeing.614.Touch is here and elsewhere taken in its wide meaning, and includes our muscular and locomotive experience, all which Berkeley included in the“tactual”meaning of distance.615.To explain the condition of sensible thingsduring the intervals of our perception of them, consistently with the belief of all sane persons regarding the material world, is a challenge which has been often addressed to the advocates of ideal Realism. According to Berkeley, there are no intervals in the existence of sensible things. They are permanently perceivable, under the laws of nature, though not always perceived by this, that or the other individual percipient. Moreover they always existreallyin the Divine Idea, andpotentially, in relation to finite minds, in the Divine Will.616.Berkeley allows to bodies unperceived by me potential, but (for me) not real existence. When I say a body exists thus conditionally, I mean that if, in the light, I open my eyes, I shall see it, and that if I move my hand, I must feel it.617.i.e. unperceived material substance.618.Berkeley remarks, in a letter to the American Samuel Johnson, that“those who have contended for a material world have yet acknowledged thatnatura naturans(to use the language of the Schoolmen) is God; and that the Divine conservation of things is equipollent to, and in fact the same thing with, a continued repeated creation;—in a word, that conservation and creation differ only as theterminus a quo. These are the common opinions of Schoolmen; and Durandus, who held the world to be a machine, like a clock made up and put in motion by God, but afterwards continued to go of itself, was therein particular, and had few followers. The very poets teach a doctrine not unlike the Schools—mens agitat molem(Virgil, Æneid, VI). The Stoics and Platonists are everywhere full of the same notion. I am not therefore singular in this point itself, so much as in my way of proving it.”Cf.Alciphron, Dial. IV. sect. 14;Vindication of New Theory of Vision, sect. 8, 17, &c.;Siris,passim, but especially in the latter part. See alsoCorrespondence between Clarke and Leibniz(1717). Is it not possible that the universe of things and persons is in continuous natural creation, unbeginning and unending?619.Cf. sect. 123-132.620.He distinguishes“idea”from“mode or attribute.”With Berkeley, the“substance”ofmatter(if the term is still to be applied to sensible things) is the naturally constituted aggregate of phenomena of which each particular thing consists. Now extension, and the other qualities of sensible things, are not, Berkeley argues,“in mind”either (a) according to the abstract relation of substance and attribute of which philosophers speak; nor (b) as one idea or phenomenon is related to another idea or phenomenon, in the natural aggregation of sense-phenomena which constitute, with him, thesubstanceof amaterialthing. Mind and its“ideas”are, on the contrary, related as percipient to perceived—in whatever“otherness”that altogethersui generisrelation implies.621.“Matter,”i.e. abstract material Substance, as distinguished from the concrete things that are realised in living perceptions.622.“take away natural causes,”i.e. empty the material world of all originative power, and refer the supposed powers of bodies to the constant and omnipresent agency of God.623.Some philosophers have treated the relation of Matter to Mind inperceptionas one of cause and effect. This, according to Berkeley, is an illegitimate analysis, which creates a fictitious duality. On his New Principles, philosophy is based on a recognition of the fact, that perception is neither the cause nor the effect of its object, but in a relation to it that is altogethersui generis.624.He refers to Descartes, and perhaps Geulinx and Malebranche, who, while they argued for materialsubstance, denied thecausal efficiencyof sensible things. Berkeley's new Principles are presented as the foundation in reason for this denial, and for the essential spirituality of all active power in the universe.625.On the principle,“Entia non sunt multiplicanda præter necessitatem.”626.“external things,”i.e. things in the abstract.627.That the unreflecting part of mankind should have a confused conception of what should be meant by theexternal realityof matter is not wonderful. It is the office of philosophy to improve their conception, making it deeper and truer, and this was Berkeley's preliminary task; as a mean for shewing the impotence of the things of sense, and conclusive evidence of omnipresent spiritual activity.628.Cf. sect. 4, 9, 15, 17, 22, 24.629.i.e. theirsense-ideas.—Though sense-ideas, i.e. the appearances presented to the senses, are independent of thewillof the individual percipient, it does not follow that they are independent ofall perception, so that they can be real in the absence of realising percipient experience. Cf. sect. 29-33.630.By shewing that what we are percipient of in sense must beidea, or that it is immediately known by us only as sensuous appearance.631.i.e.“imprinted”by unperceived Matter, which, on this dogma of a representative sense-perception, was assumed to exist behind the perceived ideas, and to be thecauseof their appearance. Cf.Third Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.632.Hence the difficulty men have in recognising that Divine Reason and Will, and Law in Nature, are coincident. But the advance of scientific discovery of the laws which express Divine Will in nature, instead of narrowing, extends our knowledge of God. Anddivineorabsolutely reasonable“arbitrariness”is not caprice.633.“ideas,”i.e. ideas ofsense. This“experience”implied an association of sensuous ideas, according to the divine or reasonable order of nature.634.Cf. sect. 25-33, and other passages in Berkeley's writings in which he insists upon thearbitrariness—divine or reasonable—of the natural laws and sense-symbolism.635.Cf. sect. 3, 4, 6, 22-24, 26, in which he proceeds upon the intuitive certainty of his two leading Principles, concerningRealityandCausation.636.In short, what is virtually the language of universal natural order is the divine way of revealing omnipresent Intelligence; nor can we conceive how this revelation could be made through a capricious or chaotic succession of changes.637.He here touches on moral purpose in miraculous phenomena, but without discussing their relation to the divine, or perfectly reasonable, order of the universe. Relatively to a fine knowledge of nature, they seem anomalous—exceptions from general rules, which nevertheless express, immediately and constantly, perfect active Reason.638.“ideas,”i.e. the phenomena presented to the senses.639.“imaginable”—in first edition.640.“the connexion of ideas,”i.e. the presence of law or reasonable uniformity in the coexistence and succession of the phenomena of sense; which makes them interpretable signs.641.According to Berkeley, it is by an abuse of language that the term“power”is applied to those ideas which are invariable antecedents of other ideas—the prior forms of their existence, as it were.642.Berkeley, in meeting this objection, thus implies Universal Natural Symbolism as the essential character of the sensible world, in its relation to man.643.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. IV, ch. 3, § 25-28, &c., in which he suggests that the secondary qualities of bodies may be the natural issue of the different relations and modifications of their primary qualities.644.With Berkeley,material substanceis merely the natural combination of sense-presented phenomena, which, under adivineorreasonable“arbitrariness,”constitute a concrete thing. Divine Will, or Active Reason, is the constantly sustaining cause of this combination or substantiation.645.i.e. that it is not realised in a living percipient experience.646.For“place”is realised only as perceived—percipient experience being its concrete existence. Living perception is, with Berkeley, the condition of the possibility of concrete locality.647.So in the Cartesian theory of occasional causes.648.So Geulinx and Malebranche.649.As known in Divine intelligence, they are accordinglyDivine Ideas. And, if this means that the sensible system is the expression of Divine Ideas, which are its ultimate archetype—that the Ideas of God are symbolised to our senses, and then interpreted (or misinterpreted) by human minds, this allies itself with Platonic Idealism.650.“It seems to me,”Hume says,“that this theory of the universal energy and operation of the Supreme Being istoo boldever to carry conviction with it to a mind sufficiently apprised of the weakness of human reason, and the narrow limits to which it is confined in all its operations.”But is it not virtually presupposed in the assumed trustworthiness of our experience of the universe?651.Accordingly we are led to ask, what the deepest support of their reality must be. Is it found in living Spirit, i.e. Active Reason, or in blind Matter?652.e.g. Descartes, Malebranche, Locke, &c.653.In short, if we mean by Matter, something unrealised in percipient experience of sense, what is called itsrealityis something unintelligible.654.And if sensible phenomena aresufficientlyexternalised, when regarded as regulated by Divine Reason.655.Twenty years after the publication of thePrinciples, in a letter to his American friend Johnson, Berkeley says:—“I have no objection against calling the Ideas in the mind of Godarchetypesof ours. But I object against those archetypes by philosophers supposed to be real things, and so to have an absolute rational existence distinct from their being perceived by any mind whatsoever; it being the opinion of all materialists that an ideal existence in the Divine Mind is one thing, and the real existence of material things another.”656.Berkeley's philosophy is not inconsistent with Divine Ideas which receive expression in the laws of nature, and of which human science is the imperfect interpretation. In this view, assertion of the existence of Matter is simply an expression of faith that the phenomenal universe into which we are born is a reasonable and interpretable universe; and that it would be fully interpreted, if our notions could be fully harmonised with the Divine Ideas which it expresses.657.Cf. sect. 3-24.658.So that superhuman persons, endowed with a million senses, would be no nearer this abstract Matter than man is, with his few senses.659.Matter and physical science isrelative, so far that we may suppose in other percipients than men, an indefinite number of additional senses, affording corresponding varieties of qualities in things, of course inconceivable by man. Or, we may suppose an intelligence destitute ofall oursenses, and so in a material world wholly different in its appearances from ours.660.The authority of Holy Scripture, added to our natural tendency to believe in external reality, are grounds on which Malebranche and Norris infer a material world. Berkeley's material world claims no logical proof of its reality. His is not to prove the reality of the world, but to shew what we should mean when we affirm its reality, and the basis of its explicability in science.661.i.e. existing unrealised in any intelligence—human or Divine.662.“external things,”i.e. things existing really, yet out of all relation to active living spirit.663.Simultaneous perception of the“same”(similar?)sense-ideas,by different persons, as distinguished from purely individual consciousness of feelings and fancies, is here taken as a test of thevirtually external realityof the former.Berkeley does not ask whether the change of the rod into a serpent, or of the water into wine, is the issue of divine agency and order, otherwise than as all natural evolution is divinely providential.664.Some of the Consequences of adoption of the New Principles, in their application to the physical sciences and mathematics, and then to psychology and theology, are unfolded in the remaining sections of thePrinciples.665.Berkeley disclaims the supposedrepresentativecharacter of the ideas given in sensuous perception, and recognises as the real object only what is ideally presented in consciousness.666.So Hume, Reid, and Hamilton, who all see in a wholly representative sense-perception, with its double object, the germ of total scepticism. Berkeley claims that, underhisinterpretation of what the reality of the material world means, immediate knowledge of mind-dependent matter is given in sense.667.“scepticism”—“sceptical cant”in the first edition.668.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.669.Berkeley's argument against afinally representativeperception so far resembles that afterwards employed by Reid and Hamilton. They differ as regards the dependence of the sensible object upon percipient spirit for its reality.670.Omitted in second edition.671.Omitted in second edition.672.But whilst unthinking things depend on being perceived, do not our spirits depend on ideas of some sort for their percipient life?673.The important passage within brackets was added in the second edition.674.“reason,”i.e. reasoning.675.“Notion,”in its stricter meaning, is thus confined by Berkeley to apprehension of theEgo, and intelligence ofrelations. The term“notion,”in this contrast withhis“idea,”becomes important in his vocabulary, although he sometimes uses it vaguely.676.Locke usesideain this wider signification.677.Inasmuch as they arerealin and through living percipient mind.678.i.e.unthinkingarchetypes.679.In this section Berkeley explains what he means byexternality. Men cannot act, cannot live, without assuming an external world—in some meaning of the term“external.”It is the business of the philosopher to explicate its true meaning.680.i.e. they are notsubstancesin the truest or deepest meaning of the word.681.“Ideas of the corporeal substances.”Berkeley might perhaps say—Divine Ideas which arethemselvesour world of sensible things in its ultimate form.682.On the scheme of ideal Realism,“creation”of matter is presenting to finite minds sense-ideas or phenomena, which are, as it were, letters of the alphabet, in that language of natural order which God employs for the expression ofHisIdeas to us.683.Theindependenteternity of Matter must be distinguished from an unbeginning and endlesscreationof sensible ideas or phenomena, in percipient spirits, according to divine natural law and order, with implied immanence of God.684.Because the question at issue with Atheism is, whether the universe of things and persons is finally substantiated and evolved in unthinking Matter or in the perfect Reason of God.685.Of which Berkeley doesnotpredicate anumericalidentity. Cf.Third Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.686.“matter,”i.e. matter abstracted from all percipient life and voluntary activity.687.“external”—not in Berkeley's meaning of externality. Cf. sect. 90, note 2.688.Si non rogas, intelligo.Berkeley writes long after this to Johnson thus:—“A succession of ideas (phenomena) I take toconstitutetime, and not to be only the sensible measure thereof, as Mr. Locke and others think. But in these matters every man is to think for himself, and speak as he finds. One of my earliest inquiries was abouttime; which led me into several paradoxes that I did not think it fit or necessary to publish, particularly into the notion that the resurrection follows the next moment after death. We are confounded and perplexed about time—supposing a succession in God; that we have an abstract idea of time; that time in one mind is to be measured by succession of ideas in another mind: not considering the true use of words, which as often terminate in the will as in the understanding, being employed to excite and direct action rather than to produce clear and distinct ideas.”Cf. Introduction, sect. 20.689.As theesseof unthinking things ispercipi, according to Berkeley, so theesseof persons ispercipere. The real existence of individual Mind thus depends on having ideas of some sort: the real existence of matter depends on a percipient.690.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.691.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 43.692.“objects of sense,”i.e. sensible things, practically external to each person. Cf. sect. 1, on the meaning ofthing, as distinct from the distinguishable ideas or phenomena that are naturally aggregated in the form of concrete things.693.Omitted in second edition.694.Omitted in second edition.695.Cf. Introduction, sect. 1-3. With Berkeley, the real essence of sensible things is given in perception—so far as our perceptions carry us.696.e.g. Locke'sEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 3.697.Berkeley advocates a Realism, which eliminates effective causation from the material world, concentrates it in Mind, and in physical research seeks among data of sense for their divinely maintained natural laws.698.In interpreting the data of sense, we are obliged to assume that everynewphenomenon must have previously existed in some equivalent form—but not necessarily in this or that particular form, for a knowledge of which we are indebted to inductive comparisons of experience.699.The preceding forms of new phenomena, being finally determined by Will, are, in that sense, arbitrary; but not capricious, for the Will is perfect Reason. God is the immanent cause of the natural order.700.He probably refers to Bacon.701.Omitted in second edition.702.What we are able to discover in the all-comprehensive order may be subordinate and provisional only. Nature in its deepest meaning explains itself in the Divine Omniscience.703.i.e. inductively.704.i.e. deductively.705.“seem to consider signs,”i.e. to be grammarians rather than philosophers: physical sciences deal with the grammar of the divine language of nature.706.“A man may be well read in the language of nature without understanding the grammar of it, or being able to say,”&c.—in first edition.707.“extend”—“stretch”—in first edition.708.Omitted in second edition.709.In the first edition, the section commences thus:“The best grammar of the kind we are speaking of will be easily acknowledged to be a treatise ofMechanics, demonstrated and applied to Nature, by a philosopher of a neighbouring nation, whom all the world admire. I shall not take upon me to make remarks on the performance of that extraordinary person: only some things he has advanced so directly opposite to the doctrine we have hitherto laid down, that we should be wanting in the regard due to the authority of so great a man did we not take some notice of them.”He refers, of course, to Newton. The first edition of Berkeley'sPrincipleswas published in Ireland—hence“neighbouring nation.”Newton'sPrincipiaappeared in 1687.710.“Motion,”in various aspects, is treated specially in theDe Motu. An imagination of trinal space presupposes locomotive experience—unimpeded, in contrast with—impeded locomotion. Cf. sect. 116.711.Omitted in second edition.712.Added in second edition.713.Omitted in second edition.714.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 13, §§ 7-10.715.“applied to”—“impressed on”—in first edition.716.“applied to”—“impressed on”—in first edition.717.“theforcecausing the change”—which“force,”according to Berkeley, can only be attributed metaphorically to the so-called impelling body; inasmuch asbodies, or the data of sense, can only be signs of their consequent events, not efficient causes of change.718.Added in second edition.719.What follows to the end of this section is omitted in the second edition.720.“seems impossible”—“is above my capacity”—in first edition.721.In short, empty Spaceisthe sensuous idea of unresisted motion. This is implied in theNew Theory of Vision. He minimises Space, treating it as a datum of sense.722.He probably refers to Samuel Clarke'sDemonstration of the Being and Attributes of God, which appeared in 1706, and a treatiseDe Spatio Reali, published in the same year.723.Sect. 118-132 are accordingly concerned with the New Principles in their application to Mathematics. The foundation of the mathematical sciences engaged much of Berkeley's thought in early life and in his later years. See hisAnalyst.724.Numerical relations arerealisedonly in concrete experience.725.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 107, &c.726.Ibid. sect. 122-125, 149-160.727.An infinitely divided extension, being unperceived, must be unreal—if its existence is made real only in and through actual perception, or at least imagination. The only possible extension is, accordingly, sensible extension, which could not be infinitely divided without the supposed parts ceasing to be perceived or real.728.“converted Gentile”—“pagan convert”—in first edition.729.Cf. Locke'sEssay, Bk. I, ch. 3, § 25.730.“will perhaps in virtue thereof be brought to admit,”&c.—“will not stick to affirm,”&c.—in first edition.731.Omitted in second edition. See theAnalyst.732.“we must mean”—“we mean (if we mean anything)”—in first edition.733.Omitted in the second edition.734.Does this refer to the intended“Part II”of thePrinciples?735.“men of great abilities and obstinate application,”&c.—“men of the greatest abilities and most obstinate application,”&c.—in first edition.736.What follows to the end of this section is omitted in the second edition.737.“absolute,”i.e. abstract, independent, irrelative existence—as something of which there can be no sensuous perception or conception.738.Matter unrealised in perception—not the material world that is realised in percipient experience of sense.739.Omitted in second edition.740.Sect. 135-156 treat of consequences of the New Principles, in their application to sciences concerned with our notions ofSpiritorMind; as distinguished from sciences of ideas in external Nature, and their mathematical relations. Individual mind, with Berkeley, needs data of sense in order to its realisation in consciousness; while it is dependent on God, in a relation which he does not define distinctly.741.e.g. Locke suggests this.742.Is this analogy applicable?743.Omitted in second edition, as he had previously learned to distinguishnotionfromidea. Cf. sect. 89, 142.744.Ibid. In the omitted passage it will be seen that he makesideaandnotionsynonymous.745.Is the reality of mind as dependent on having ideas (of some sort) as ideas are on mind; although mind is more deeply and truly real than its ideas are?746.Introduced in second edition.747.We knowother finite personsthrough sense-presented phenomena, but not as themselves phenomena. Cf. sect. 145. It is a mediate knowledge that we have of other persons. The question about the individuality of finite egos, as distinguished from God, Berkeley has not touched.748.These sentences are omitted in the second edition.749.“the soul,”i.e. the individual Ego.750.Cf. sect. 2; 25-27.751.This is Berkeley's application of his new conception of the reality of matter, to the final human question of the self-conscious existence of the individual human Ego, after physical death. Philosophers and theologians were accustomed in his generation to ground their argument for a future life on the metaphysical assumption of the physical indivisibility of our self-conscious spirit, and on our contingent connexion with the body.“Our bodies,”says Bishop Butler,“are no moreourselves, orpart of ourselves, than any other matter around us.”This train of thought is foreign to us at the present day, when men of science remind us that self-conscious life is found only in correlation with corporeal organisation, whatever may be the abstract possibility. Hope of continued life after physical death seems to depend on ethical considerations more than on metaphysical arguments, and on what is suggested by faith in the final outcome of personal life in adivinelyconstituted universe.752.Mind and the ideas presented to the senses are at opposite poles of existence. But he does not say that, thus opposed, they are each independent of the other.753.What follows was introduced in the second edition, in whichnotionis contrasted withidea.754.Here is a germ of Kantism. But Berkeley has not analysed that activity of mind which constitutesrelation, nor systematically unfolded the relations involved in the rational constitution of experience. There is more disposition to this inSiris.755.As with Locke, for example.756.Note this condemnation of the tendency to substantiate“powers of mind.”757.Omitted in second edition. Berkeley was after all reluctant to“depart from received modes of speech,”notwithstanding their often misleading associations.758.Omitted in second edition.759.This is one of the notable sections in thePrinciples, as it suggests therationaleof Berkeley's rejection of Panegoism or Solipsism. Is this consistent with his conception of the reality of the material world? It is objected (e.g. by Reid) that ideal realism dissolves our faith in the existence of other persons. The difficulty is to shew how appearances presented to my senses, which are sensuous and subjective, can be media of communication between persons. The question carries us back to the theistic presupposition in the trustworthiness of experience—which is adapted to deceive if I am the only person existing. With Berkeley a chief function of ideas of sense is to signify other persons to each person. SeeAlciphron, Dial. IV;New Theory of Vision Vindicated, andSiris.760.“repugnant”—for it would involve thought in incoherence, by paralysis of its indispensable causal presupposition.761.Is not God the indispensable presupposition of trustworthy experience, rather than an empirical inference?762.This suggests an explanation of the objective reality and significance ofideas of sense; through which they become media of social intercourse in the fundamentally divine universe. God so regulates the sense-given ideas of which human beings are individually percipient, as that,while numerically different, as in each mind, those ideas are nevertheless a sufficient medium for social intercourse, if the Power universally at work is morally trustworthy. Unless our God-given experience is deceiving, Solipsism is not a necessary result of the fact that no one but myself can be percipient of my sensuous experience.763.Omitted in second edition.764.Malebranche, as understood by Berkeley. SeeRecherche, Liv. III. p. ii. ch. 6, &c.765.For all finite personssomehowlive, and move, and have their being“in God.”The existence ofeternalliving Mind, and thepresentexistence of other men, are bothinferences, resting on the same foundation, according to Berkeley.766.The theistic trust in which our experience is rooted remaining latent, or being unintelligent.767.Cf. sect. 25-28, 51-53, 60-66. His conception of Divine causation in Nature, as the constant omnipresent agency in all natural law, is the deepest part of his philosophy. It is pursued in theDe Motu.768.Is not the unbeginning and unending natural evolution, an articulate revelation of Eternal Spirit or Active Reason at the heart of the whole?769.Omitted in second edition.770.So Pascal in thePensées.771.Divine reason ever active in Nature is the necessary correlate to reason in man; inasmuch as otherwise the changing universe in which we live would be unfit to be reasoned about or acted in.772.The existence ofmoralevil, or what ought not to exist, isthedifficulty which besets faith in the fundamental divinity or goodness of the universe. Yet that faith is presupposed in interpretation of nature, which proceeds on thepostulateof universal order; and this implies the moral trustworthiness of the world which we begin to realise when we begin to be conscious. That we are living and having our being in omnipotent goodness is thus not an inference, but the implied basis of all real inferences. I have expanded this thought in myPhilosophy of Theism. We cannotproveGod, for we must assume God, as the basis of all proof. Faith even in the uniformity of nature is virtually faith in omnipotent goodness immanent in the universe.773.So Leibniz in hisTheodicée, which was published in the same year as Berkeley'sPrinciples.774.The divine presupposition, latent in all human reasoning and experience, is hid from the unreflecting, in whom the higher life is dormant, and the ideal in the universe is accordingly undiscerned. Unless the universe is assumed to be physically and morally trustworthy, i.e. unless God is presupposed, even natural science has no adequate foundation.775.Our necessarily incomplete knowledge of the Universe in which we find ourselves is apt to disturb the fundamental faith, that the phenomena presented to us are significant of God. Yet wetacitly assumethat they are thus significant when we interpret real experience, physical or moral.776.Omitted in second edition.777.For the following extracts from previously unpublished correspondence of Berkeley and Sir John Percival, I am indebted to the kindness of his descendant, the late Lord Egmont.778.What Berkeley seeks to shew is, not that the world of the senses is unreal, but in what its reality consists. Is it inexplicable chaos, or explicable expression of ever active Intelligence, more or less interpreted in natural science?779.Leibniz:De modo distinguendi Phenomena Realia ab Imaginariis(1707).780.For some information relative to Gua de Malves, see Querard'sLa France Littéraire,tom. iii. p. 494.781.The following is the translator's Prefatory Note, on the objects of theDialogues,and in explanation of the three illustrative vignettes:—“L'Auteur expose dans le premier Dialogue le sentiment du Vulgaire et celui des Philosophes, sur les qualités secondaires et premieres, la nature et l'existence des corps; et il prétend prouver en même tems l'insuffisance de l'un et de l'autre. La Vignette qu'on voit à la téte du Dialogue, fait allusion à cet objet. Elle représente un Philosophe dans son cabinet, lequel est distrait de son travail par un enfant qu'il appercoit se voyant lui-méme dans un miroir, en tendant les mains pour embrasser sa propre image. Le Philosophe rit de l'erreur où il croit que tombe l'enfant; tandis qu'on lui applique à lui-même ces mots tirés d'Horace:Quid rides?....de teFabula narratur.“Le second Dialogue est employé à exposer le sentiment de l'Auteur sur le même sujet, sçavoir, que les choses corporelles ont une existence réelle dans les esprits qui les apperçoivent; mais qu'elles ne sçauroient exister hors de tous les esprits à la fois, même de l'esprit infini de Dieu; et que par conséquent la Matière, prise suivant l'acception ordinaire du mot, non seulement n'existe point, mais seroit même absolument impossible. On a taché de représenter aux yeux ce sentiment dans la Vignette du Dialogue. Le mot grec νοῦς qui signifieâme, désigne l'àme: les rayons qui en partent marquent l'attention que l'âme donne à des idées ou objets; les tableaux qu'on a placés aux seuls endroits où les rayons aboutissent, et dont les sujets sont tirés de la description des beautés de la nature, qui se trouve dans le livre, représentent les idées ou objets que l'âme considère, pas le secours des facultes qu'elle a reçues de Dieu; et l'action de l'Étre suprème sur l'âme est figurée par un trait, qui, partant d'un triangle, symbole de la Divinité, et perçant les nuages dont le triangle est environné. s'étend jusqu'à l'âme pour la vivifier; enfin, on a fait en sorte de rendre le même sentiment par ces mots:Quæ noscere cumque Deus det,Esse puta.“L'objet du troisième Dialogue est de répondre aux difficultés auxquelles le sentiment qu'on a établi dans les Dialogues précédens, peut être sujet, de l'éclaircir en cette sorte de plus, d'en développer toutes les heureuses conséquences, enfin de faire voir, qu'étant bien entendu, il revient aux notions les plus communes. Et comme l'Auteur exprime à la fin du livre cette dernière pensée, en comparant ce qu'il vient de dire, à l'eau que les deux Interlocuteurs sont supposés voir jaillir d'un jet, et qu'il remarque que la même force de la gravité fait élever jusqu'à une certaine hauteur et retomber ensuite dans le bassin d'où elle étoit d'abord partie; on a pris cet emblême pour le sujet de la Vignette de ce Dialogue; on a représenté en conséquence dans cette dernière Vignette les deux Interlocuteurs, se promenant dans le lieu où l'Auteur les suppose, et s'entretenant là-dessus, et pour donner au Lecteur l'explication de l'emblême, on a mis au bas le vers suivant:Urget aquas vis sursum, eadem flectitque deorsum.”782.Collier never came fairly in sight of the philosophical public of last century. He is referred to in Germany by Bilfinger, in hisDilucidationes Philosophicæ(1746), and also in theAda Eruditorum, Suppl. VI. 244, &c., and in England by Corry in hisReflections on Liberty and Necessity(1761), as well as in theRemarkson the Reflections, andAnswersto the Remarks, pp. 7, 8 (1763), where he is described as“a weak reasoner, and a very dull writer also.”Collier was dragged from his obscurity by Dr. Reid, in hisEssays on the Intellectual Powers, Essay II. ch. 10. He was a subject of correspondence between Sir James Mackintosh, then at Bombay, and Dr. Parr, and an object of curiosity to Dugald Stewart. A beautiful reprint of theClavis(of the original edition of which only seven copies were then known to exist) appeared in Edinburgh in 1836; and in the following year it was included in a collection ofMetaphysical Tracts by English Philosophers of the Eighteenth Century, prepared for the press by Dr. Parr.783.William, fourth Lord Berkeley of Stratton, born about 1663, succeeded his brother in 1697, and died in 1741 at Bruton in Somersetshire. The Berkeleys of Stratton were descended from a younger son of Maurice, Lord Berkeley of Berkeley Castle, who died in 1326. His descendant, Sir John Berkeley of Bruton, a zealous Royalist, was created first Lord Berkeley of Stratton in 1658, and in 1669 became Lord Lieutenant of Ireland, an office which he held till 1672, when he was succeeded by the Earl of Essex (see Burke'sExtinct Peerages). It is said that Bishop Berkeley's father was related to him. The Bishop himself was introduced by Dean Swift, in 1713, to the Lord Berkeley of Stratton, to whom theDialoguesare dedicated, as“a cousin of his Lordship.”The title of Berkeley of Stratton became extinct on the death of the fifth Lord in 1773.784.This interesting Preface is omitted in his last edition of theDialogues.785.The Second Part of thePrincipleswas never published, and only in part written. See Editor's Preface to thePrinciples.786.Principles, Introduction, sect. 1.787.Berkeley's philosophy is professedly a“revolt”from abstract ideas to an enlightened sense of concrete realities. In these DialoguesPhilonouspersonates the revolt, and represents Berkeley.Hylasvindicates the uncritical conception of independent Matter.788.Berkeley's zeal against Matter in the abstract, and all abstract ideas of concrete things, is therefore not necessarily directed against“universal intellectual notions”—“the principles and theorems of sciences.”789.Here“reason”means reasoning or inference. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 42, including the distinction between“suggestion”and“inference.”790.“figure”as well as colour, is here included among the original data of sight.791.“without the mind,”i.e. unrealised by any percipient mind.792.Cf.Principles, sect. 14.793.Cf.Principles, sect. 14, 15.794.“Sensible qualities,”i.e. the significant appearances presented in sense.795.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 80-86.796.Descartes and Locke for example.797.On Primary and Secondary Qualities of Matter, and their mutual relations, cf.Principles, sect. 9-15. See also Descartes,Meditations, III,Principia, I. sect. 69; Malebranche,Recherche, Liv. VI. Pt. II. sect. 2; Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 8.798.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 80.799.What follows, within brackets, is not contained in the first and second editions.800.Percipient mind is, in short, the indispensable realising factor ofallthe qualities of sensible things.801.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 122-126;Principles, sect. 123, &c.;Siris, sect. 270, &c.802.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 15.803.Is“notion”here a synonym for idea?804.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 16.805.“Size or figure, or sensible quality”—“size, color &c.,”in the first and second editions.806.In Berkeley's later and more exact terminology, the data or implicates of pure intellect are callednotions, in contrast to hisideas, which are concrete or individual sensuous presentations.807.They need living percipient mind to make them real.808.So Reid'sInquiry, ch. ii, sect. 8, 9;Essays on the Intellectual Powers, II. ch. 16. Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 8, &c.809.i.e. figured or extended visible colour. Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 43, &c.810.Cf.Principles, sect. 25, 26.811.After maintaining, in the preceding part of this Dialogue, the inevitable dependence of all the qualities of Matter upon percipient Spirit, the argument now proceeds to dispose of the supposition that Matter may still be an unmanifested or unqualifiedsubstratum, independent of living percipient Spirit.812.[See theEssay towards a New Theory of Vision, and itsVindication.] Note by theAuthorin the 1734 edition.813.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 2.814.Cf. Ibid., sect. 43.815.“an idea,”i.e. a phenomenon present to our senses.816.This was Reid's fundamental question in his criticism of Berkeley.817.Cf.Principles, sect. 8.818.Cf.Principles, sect. 25, 26.819.In other words, the percipient activity of a living spirit is the necessary condition of the real existence of all ideas or phenomena immediately present to our senses.820.An“explanation”afterwards elaborately developed by Hartley, in hisObservations on Man(1749). Berkeley has probably Hobbes in view.821.The brain with the human body in which it is included constitutes a part of the material world, and must equally with the rest of the material world depend for its realisation upon percipient Spirit as the realising factor.822.Cf.Principles, sect. 23.823.“in stones and minerals”—in first and second editions.824.Cf.Principles, sect. 29-33; also sect. 90.—Thepermanenceof a thing, during intervals in which it may be unperceived and unimagined by human beings, is here assumed, as a natural conviction.825.In other words, men are apt to treat the omniscience of God as an inference from the dogmatic assumption that God exists, instead of seeing that our cosmic experience necessarily presupposes omnipotent and omniscient Intelligence at its root.826.Cf.Principles, sect. 90. A permanent material world is grounded on Divine Mind, because it cannot but depend on Mind, while its reality is only partially and at intervals sustained by finite minds.827.“necessarily inferred from”—rather necessarily presupposed in.828.The present reality of Something implies the eternal existence of living Mind, if Somethingmustexist eternally, and if real or concrete existence involves living Mind. Berkeley's conception of material nature presupposes a theistic basis.829.He refers of course to Malebranche and his Divine Vision.830.But Malebranche usesideain a higher meaning than Berkeley does—akin to the Platonic, and in contrast to the sensuous phenomena which Berkeley calls ideas.831.The passage within brackets first appeared in the third edition.832.Cf.Principles, sect. 25-33.833.Cf. Ibid., sect. 3-24.834.Icanrepresent to myself another mind perceiving and conceiving things; because I have an example of this my own conscious life. Icannotrepresent to myself sensible things existing totally unperceived and unimagined; because I cannot, without a contradiction, have an example of this in my own experience.835.“reason,”i.e. by reasoning.836.Berkeley'smaterial substanceis a natural or divinely ordered aggregate of sensible qualities or phenomena.837.Inasmuch as, according to Berkeley, it must be a living Spirit, and it would be an abuse of language to call this Matter.838.Cf.Principles, sect. 25, 26.839.It is here argued that asvolitionis the onlyoriginativecause implied in our experience, and which consequently alone puts true meaning into the term Cause, to apply that term to what is not volition is to make it meaningless, or at least to misapply it.840.While thus arguing against the need for independent matter, as an instrument needed by God, Berkeley fails to explain how dependent matter can be a medium of intercourse between persons. It must be more than a subjective dream, however well ordered, if it is available for this purpose. Unless the visible and audible ideas or phenomena presented to me are actually seen and heard by other men, how can they be instrumental in intercommunication?841.Cf.Principles, sect. 68-79.842.Cf.Principles, sect. 20.843.Cf.Principles, sect. 80, 81.844.i.e. all Spirits and their dependent ideas or phenomena.845.This, according to Hume (who takes for granted that Berkeley's reasonings can produce no conviction), is the natural effect of Berkeley's philosophy.—“Most of the writings of that very ingenious author (Berkeley) form the best lessons of scepticism which are to be found either among the ancient or modern philosophers, Bayle not excepted.... That all his arguments, though otherwise intended, are, in reality, merely sceptical, appear from this—that they admit of no answer, and produce no conviction. Their only effect is to cause that momentary amazement and irresolution and confusion, which is the result of scepticism.”(Hume'sEssays, vol. II. Note N, p. 554.)846.Omitted in last edition.847.“Tell me, Hylas,”—“So Hylas”—in first and second editions.848.Variously callednoumena,“things-in-themselves,”absolute substances, &c.—which Berkeley's philosophy banishes, on the ground of their unintelligibility, and thus annihilates all farther questions concerning them. Questions about existence are thus confined within the concrete or realising experiences of living spirits.849.Berkeley claims that his doctrine supersedes scepticism, and excludes the possibility of fallacy in sense, in excluding an ultimately representative perception of Matter. He also assumes the reasonableness of faith in the reality and constancy of natural law. When we see an orange, the visual sense guarantees only colour. The other phenomena, which we associate with this colour—the other“qualities”of the orange—are, when we onlyseethe orange, matter of faith. We believe them to be realisable.850.He accepts the common belief on which interpretation of sense symbols proceeds—that sensible phenomena are evolved in rational order, under laws that are independent of, and in that respect external to, the individual percipient.851.Mediately as well as immediately.852.We can hardly be said to have animmediatesense-perception of an individual“thing”—meaning by“thing”a congeries of sense-ideas or phenomena, presented to different senses. We immediately perceive some of them, and believe in the others, which those suggest. See the last three notes.853.He probably refers to Descartes, whoarguesfor the trustworthiness of our faculties from the veracity of God; thus apparently arguing in a circle, seeing that the existence of God is manifested to us only through our suspected faculties. But is not confidence in the trustworthiness of the Universal Power at the heart of the universe, the fundamentalpresuppositionof all human experience, and God thus the basis and end of philosophy and of experience?854.As Locke does. SeeEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 11.855.Cf.Principles of Human Knowledge, sect. 45-48.856.And to be thus external to individual minds.857.It is here that Berkeley differs, for example, from Hume and Comte and J.S. Mill; who accept sense-given phenomena, and assume the constancy of their orderly reappearances,as a matter of fact, while they confess total ignorance of thecauseof natural order. (Thus ignorant, why do they assume reason or order in nature?) The ground of sensible things, which Berkeley refers to Divine Power, Mill expresses by the term“permanent possibilityof sensation.”(See hisExamination of Hamilton, ch. 11.) Our belief in the continued existence of a sensible thingin our absencemerely means, with him, our conviction, derived from custom, that we should perceive it under inexplicable conditions which determine its appearance.858.Cf.Principles, sect. 25, 26.859.Cf. Ibid., sect. 2, 27, 135-142.860.Inasmuch as I am conscious ofmyself, I can gather, through the sense symbolism, the real existence of other minds, external to my own. For I cannot, of course, enter into the very consciousness of another person.861.“reason,”i.e. reasoning or necessary inference—founded here on our sense of personal dependence; not merely on our faith in sense symbolism and the interpretability of the sensible world. Our belief in the existence of finite minds, external to our own, is, with Berkeley, an application of this faith.862.“Matter,”i.e. Matter as abstract substance. Cf.Principles, sect. 135-138.863.Does this imply that with Berkeley,self, as distinguished from thephenomenaof which the material world consists, is not a necessary presuppostion of experience? He says in many places—I amconsciousof“my own being,”and that my mind is myself. Cf.Principles, sect, 2.864.Cf.Principles, sect. 8.865.Cf. Ibid., sect. 20866.This important passage, printed within brackets, is not found in the first and second editions of theDialogues. It is, by anticipation, Berkeley's answer to Hume's application of the objections to the reality of abstract or unperceived Matter, to the reality of the Ego or Self, of which we are aware through memory, as identical amid the changes of its successive states.867.See note 4 on preceding page.868.Cf.Principles, sect. 142.869.Cf. Ibid., sect. 2. Does he assume that he exists when he is not conscious of ideas—sensible or other? Or, does he deny that he is ever unconscious?870.That is of matter supposed to exist independently of any mind. Berkeley speaks here of aconsciousnessof matter. Does he mean consciousness of belief in abstract material Substance?871.Cf.Principles, sect. 54-57.872.Which he does not doubt.873.This sentence expresses the whole question between Berkeley and his antagonists.874.Cf.Principles, sect. 29-41.875.The words within brackets are omitted in the third edition.876.The index pointing to the originative causes in the universe is thus the ethical judgment, which fastens upon the free voluntary agency ofpersons, as absolutely responsible causes, not merely caused causes.877.That only ideas or phenomena are presented to our senses may be assented to by those who nevertheless maintain that intelligent sensuous experience implies more than the sensuous or empirical data.878.Cf.Principles, sect. 49.879.Cf.Principles, sect. 58.880.“without the mind,”i.e. without the mind of each percipient person.881.This is the gist of the whole question. According to the Materialists, sense-presented phenomena are due to unpresented, unperceived, abstract Matter; according to Berkeley, to living Spirit; according to Hume and Agnostics, their origin is unknowable, yet (incoherently) they claim that wecaninterpret them—in physical science.882.A similar objection is urged by Erdmann, in his criticism of Berkeley in theGrundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie.883.Cf.Principles, sect. 50;Siris, sect. 319.884.Cf.Principles, sect. 58.885.“order”—“series,”in first and second editions.886.“Matter,”i.e. when the reality of“matter”is supposed to signify what Berkeley argues cannot be; because really meaningless.887.“the connexion of ideas,”i.e. the physical coexistences and sequences, maintained in constant order by Power external to the individual, and which are disclosed in the natural sciences.888.Cf.Principles, sect. 38. Berkeley is not for making thingssubjective, but for recognising ideas or phenomena presented to the senses asobjective.889.They are not mere illusory appearances but are the very things themselves making their appearance, as far as our limited senses allow them to be realised for us.890.i.e. abstract Matter.891.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 49; andNew Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 9, 10, 15, &c.892.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 84-86.893.“the connexion of ideas,”i.e. the order providentially maintained in nature.894.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 23-25.895.Cf.Principles, sect. 8-10, 86, 87.896.This difficulty is thus pressed by Reid:—“The ideas in my mind cannot be the same with the ideas in any other mind; therefore, if the objects I perceive be only ideas, it is impossible that two or more such minds can perceive the same thing. Thus there is one unconfutable consequence of Berkeley's system, which he seems not to have attended to, and from which it will be found difficult, if at all possible, to guard it. The consequence I mean is this—that, although it leaves us sufficient evidence of a Supreme Mind, it seems to take away all the evidence we have of other intelligent beings like ourselves. What I call a father, or a brother, or a friend, is only a parcel of ideas in my own mind ; they cannot possibly have that relation to another mind which they have to mine, any more than the pain felt by me can be theindividual painfelt by another. I am thus left alone as the only creature of God in the universe”(Hamilton'sReid, pp. 284-285). Implied Solipsism or Panegoism is thus charged against Berkeley, unless his conception of the material world is further guarded.897.Reid and Hamilton argue in like manner against a fundamentally representative sense-perception.898.Cf.Principles, sect. 6.899.Cf. Ibid., sect. 87-90.900.Cf. Ibid., sect. 18.901.Cf.Principles, sect. 24.902.“unknown,”i.e. unrealised in percipient life.903.Cf.Principles, sect. 28-33.904.See also Collier'sClavis Universalis, p. 6:“Two or more persons who are present at a concert of music may indeed in some measure be said to hear thesamenotes; yet the sound which the one hears isnot the very samewith the sound which another hears,because the souls or persons are supposed to be different.”905.Berkeley seems to hold that inthingsthere is no identity other than perfect similarity—only inpersons. And even as to personal identity he is obscure. Cf.Siris, sect. 347, &c.906.But the question is, whether the very ideas or phenomena that are perceived by mecanbe also perceived by other persons; and if not, how I can discover that“other persons”exist, or that any finite person except myself is cognizant of the ideal cosmos—if the sort ofsamenessthat Berkeley advocates is all that can be predicated of concrete ideas; which are thus onlysimilar, or generically the same. Unless the ideas arenumericallythe same, can different persons make signs to one another through them?907.Omitted in author's last edition.908.This seems to imply that intercourse between finite persons is maintained through ideas or phenomena presented to the senses, under a tacit faith in divinely guaranteed correspondence between the phenomena of which I am conscious, and the phenomena of which my neighbour is conscious; so that they arepractically“the same.”If we are living in a fundamentally divine, and therefore absolutely trustworthy, universe, the phenomena presented to my senses, which I attribute to the agency of another person, are so attributed rightly. For if not, the so-called cosmos is adapted to mislead me.909.This explanation is often overlooked by Berkeley's critics.910.Cf.Principles, sect. 82-84.911.i.e. if you take the termideain its wholly subjective and popular meaning.912.i.e. if you take the termideain its objective meaning.913.“philosophic,”i.e.pseudo-philosophic, against which he argues.914.Had this their relative existence—this realisation of the material world through finite percipient and volitional life—any beginning? May not God have been eternally presenting phenomena to the senses of percipient beings in cosmical order, if not on this planet yet elsewhere, perhaps under other conditions? Has there been any beginning in the succession of finite persons?915.In the first and second editions only.916.Is“creation”by us distinguishable from continuous evolution, unbeginning and unending, in divinely constituted order; and is there a distinction between creation or evolution ofthingsand creation or evolution ofpersons?917.Cf.Siris, sect. 347-349.918.“Matter,”i.e. Matter in this pseudo-philosophical meaning of the word.919.Thus Origen in the early Church. That“Matter”is co-eternal with God would mean that God is eternally making things real in the percipient experience of persons.920.Cf.Principles, sect. 85-156, in which the religious and scientific advantages of the new conception of matter and the material cosmos are illustrated, when it is rightly understood and applied.921.“substance and accident”—“subjects and adjuncts,”—in the first and the second edition.922.Cf.Principles, sect. 28-42. InSiris, sect. 294-297, 300-318, 335, 359-365, we have glimpses of thought more allied to Platonism, if not to Hegelianism.923.“Matter,”i.e. matter unrealised in any mind, finite or Divine.924.These two propositions are a summary of Berkeley's conception of the material world. With him, theimmediateobjects of sense, realise inperception, are independent of thewillof the percipient, and are thus external to his proper personality. Berkeley's“material world”of enlightened Common Sense, resulting from two factors, Divine and human, is independent of each finite mind; but not independent of all living Mind.925.“voces male intellectæ.”Cf.Principles of Human Knowledge,“Introduction,”sect. 6, 23-25, on the abuse of language, especially by abstraction.926.“veterum philosophorum.”The history of ancient speculations about motion, from the paradoxes of Zeno downwards, is, in some sort, a history of ancient metaphysics. It involves Space, Time, and the material world, with the ultimate causal relation of Nature to Spirit.927.“hujus ævi philosophos.”As in Bacon on motion, and in the questions raised by Newton, Borelli, Leibniz, and others, discussed in the following sections.928.Sect. 3-42 are concerned with the principle of Causality, exemplified in the motion, or change of place and state, that is continually going on in the material world, and which was supposed by some to explain all the phenomena of the universe.929.“vis.”The assumption thatactive poweris an immediate datum of sense is the example here offered of the abase of abstract words. He proceeds to dissolve the assumption by shewing that it is meaningless.930.“principio”—the ultimate explanation or originating cause. Cf. sect. 36. Metaphors, or indeed empty words, are accepted for explanations, it is argued, whenbodilypower or force, in any form, e.g. gravitation, is taken as the real cause of motion. To call these“occult causes”is to say nothing that is intelligible. The perceived sensible effects and their customary sequences are all we know. Physicists are still deluded by words and metaphors.931.Cf. sect. 53, wheresense,imagination, andintelligenceare distinguished.932.Cf.Principles, Introd. 16, 20, 21; alsoAlciphron, Dial. VII. sect. 8, 17.933.[La Materia altro non è che un vaso di Circe incantato, il quale serve per ricettacolo della forza et de' momenti dell' impeto. La forzae l'impeti sono astratti tanto sottili, sono quintessenze tanto spiritose, che in altre ampolle non si possono racchiudere, fuor che nell' intima corpulenza de' solidi naturali, VideLezioni Accademiche.]—Author.Torricelli (1608-47), the eminent Italian physicist, and professor of mathematics at Florence, who invented the barometer.934.Borelli (1608-79), Italian professor of mathematics at Pisa, and then of medicine at Florence; see hisDe Vi Percussionis, cap. XXIV. prop. 88, and cap. XXVII.935.“per effectum,”i.e. by its sensible effects—real power or active force not being a datum of the senses, but found in the spiritual efficacy, of which we have an example in our personal agency.936.“vim mortuam.”The only power we can find is the living power of Mind. Reason is perpetually active in the universe, imperceptible through the senses, and revealed tothemonly in its sensible effects.“Power,”e.g.“gravitation,”in things,per se, is distinguished from perceived“motion”only through illusion due to misleading abstraction. There is nophysicalpower, intermediate between spiritual agency, on the one hand, and the sensible changes we see, on the other. Cf. sect. 11.937.“meditatione subigenda sunt.”Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 35, 70.938.“distingui.”It is here argued that so-called power within the things of sense is not distinguishable from the sensibly perceived sequences. To the meaningless supposition that it is, he attributes the frivolous verbal controversies among the learned mentioned in the following section. The province of natural philosophy, according to Berkeley, is to inquire what the rules are under which sensible effects are uniformly manifested. Cf.Siris, sect. 236, 247, 249.939.Principia Math.Def. III.940.De Vi Percussionis, cap. I.941.“utiles.”Such words as“force,”“power,”“gravity,”“attraction,”are held to be convenient in physical reasonings about thephenomenaof motion, but worthless as philosophical expressions of thecauseof motion, which transcends sense and mechanical science. Cf.Siris, sect. 234, 235.942.Cf. sect. 67.943.“candem.”So in recent discussions on the conservation of force.944.[Borellus.]—Author.SeeDe Vi Percussionis, cap. XXIII.945.[Leibnitius.]—Author.946.On Berkeley's reasoning all terms which involve the assumption that real causality is something presentable to the senses are a cover for meaninglessness. Only through self-conscious experience of personal activity does real meaning enter into the portion of language which deals with active causation. This is argued in detail in sect. 21-35.947.Our concrete experience is assumed to be confined to (a)bodies, i.e. the data of the senses, and (b)mindorspirit—sentient, intelligent, active—revealed by internal consciousness. Cf.Principles, sect. 1, 2, in which experience is resolved intoideasand theactive intelligencewhich they presuppose. Here the word idea disappears, but, in accordance with its signification,“bodies”is still regarded as aggregates of external phenomena, the passive subjects of changes of place and state: the idealisation of the material world is tacitly implied, but not obtruded.948.“nihilque,”&c. Cf.Principles of Human Knowledge, e.g. sect. 26, 65, 66. where the essential passivity of theideaspresented to the senses, i.e. the material world, is maintained as a cardinal principle—on the positive ground of our percipient experience of sensible things. To speak of the cause of motion assomething sensible, he argues (sect. 24), is merely to shew that we know nothing about it. Cf. sect. 28, 29, infra.949.The phenomena that can be presented to the senses are taken as the measure of what can be attributed to the material world; and as the senses presentonlyconditioned change of place in bodies, we must look for the active cause in the invisible world which internal consciousness presents to us.950.“genus rerum cogitantium.”Cf.Principles, sect. 2.951.“experientia didicimus.”Can the merely empirical data even of internal consciousness reveal this causal connexion between volition and bodily motions, without the venture of theistic faith?952.“a primo et universali Principio”i.e. God, or the Universal Spirit, in whom the universe of bodies and spirits finds explanation; in a way which Berkeley does not attempt to unfold articulately and exhaustively in philosophical system.953.Phys.θ. 4. 255 a 5-7.954.Princip. Math.Def. III.955.“resistentia.”Our muscularsensationof resistance is apt to be accepted empirically as itselfactive power in the concrete, entering very much, as has been said, into the often inaccurate idea of power which is formed. See Editor's Preface.956.“nec incommode.”Cf. sect. 17, and note.957.“hypothesis mathematica.”Cf. sect. 17, 35, 36-41, 66, 67; alsoSiris, sect. 250-251.958.“nihil.”This section sums up Berkeley's objections to creditingmatterwith real power; the senses being taken as the test of what is contained in matter. It may be compared with David Hume, Thomas Brown, and J.S. Mill on Causation. Berkeley differs from them in recognising active power in spirit, while with them he resolves causation among bodies into invariable sequence.959.Can the data presented to us reveal more than sequence, in the relation between our volitions and the corresponding movements of our bodies? Is not the difference found in the moral presupposition, whichsupernaturalisesman in his voluntary or morally responsible activity? This obliges us to seeourselvesas absolutely original causes of all bodily and mental states for which we can be morally approved or blamed.960.“novumque genus.”Cf. sect. 21. We have here Berkeley's antithesis of mind and matter—spirits and external phenomena presented to the senses—persons in contrast to passive ideas.961.De Anima, I. ii. 13, 22, 24.962.“Cartesius.”The antithesis of extended things and thinking things pervades Descartes; but not, as with Berkeley, on the foundation of the new conception of what is truly meant by matter or sensible things. See e.g.Principia, P. I. §§ 63, 64.963.“alii.”Does he refer to Locke, who suggests the possibility of matter thinking?964.See Aristotle,De Anima, I. ii. 5, 13; Diogenes Laertius, Lib. VI. i. 6.965.Nat. Ausc.VIII. 15; alsoDe Anima, III, x. 7.966.Hardly any passage in theTimæusexactly corresponds to this. The following is, perhaps, the most pertinent:—Κίνησιν γὰρ ἀπένειμεν αὐτῷ τὴν τοῦ σώματος οἰκείαν, τῶν ἑπτὰ τὴν περὶ νοῦν καὶ φρόνησιν μάλιστα οὖσαν (p. 34 a). Aristotle quotes theTimæusin the same connexion,De Anima, I. iii. ii.967.“philosophi Cartesiani.”Secundum Cartesium causa generalis omnium motuum et quietum est Deus.—Derodon,Physica, I. ix. 30.968.Principia Mathematica—Scholium Generale.969.“naturam naturantem esse Deum”—as we might say, God considered as imminent cause in the universe. See St. Thomas Aquinas,Opera, vol. XXII. Quest. 6, p. 27.970.“juxta certam et constantem rationem.”While all changes in Nature are determined by Will, it is not capricious but rational Will. The so-called arbitrariness of the Language of Nature is relative to us, and from our point of view. In itself, the universe of reality expresses Perfect Reason.971.“permaneret.”Cf. sect. 51.972.“spectat potius ad philosophiam primam.”The drift of theDe Motuis to distinguish the physical sequences of molecular motion, which the physical sciences articulate, from the Power with which metaphysics and theology are concerned, and which we approach through consciousness.973.“regulas.”Cf.Siris, sect. 231-235.974.Having, in the preceding sections, contrasted perceived motions and their immanent originating Power—matter and mind—physics and metaphysics—he proceeds in this and the seven following sections to explain more fully what ha means byprincipiumand also the two meanings (metaphysical and mechanical) ofsolutio. Byprincipium, in philosophy, he understands universally efficient supersensible Power. In natural philosophy the term is applied to the orderly sequences manifested to our senses, not to the active cause of the order.975.“ratiocinio ... redditæ universales.”Relations of the data of sense to universalising reason are here recognised.976.“natura motus.”Sect. 43-66 treat of the nature of theeffect—i.e. perceptible motion, as distinguished from its true causal origin (principium) in mind or spirit. The origin of motion belongs to metaphysics; its nature, as dependent on percipient experience, belongs to physics. Is motion independent of a plurality of bodies; or does it involve bodies in relation to other bodies, so that absolute motion is meaningless? Cf.Principles, sect. 111-116.977.“idea illa tenuissima et subtilissima.”The difficulty as to definition of motion is attributed to abstractions, and the inclination of the scholastic mind to prefer these to concrete experience.978.Motion is thus defined by Aristotle:—Διὸ ἡ κίνησις ἐντελέχεια τοῦ κινητοῦ, ᾗ κινητόν. Nat. Ausc. III. ii; see also i. and iii. Cf. Derodon,Physica, I. ix.979.Newton.980.Cf. sect. 3-42.981.Descartes,Principia, P. II. § 25; also Borellus,De Vi Percussionis, p. 1.982.“res faciles difficillimas.”Cf.Principles,“Introduction,”sect. 1.983.Καὶ διὰ τοῦτο δὴ χαλεπὸν αὐτὴν λαβεῖν τί ἐστίν.Nat. Ausc.III. ii.984.e.g. Zeno, in his noted argument against the possibility of motion, referred to as a signal example of fallacy.985.“de infinite, &c.”Cf.Principles, sect. 130-132, and theAnalystpassim, for Berkeley's treatment of infinitesimals.986.“confundere.”Cf. sect. 3-42 for illustrations of this confusion.987.The modern conception of the“conservation of force.”988.Aristotle states the question inNat. Ausc.VIII. cap. i, and solves it in cap. iv.989.“mutatio loci”is the effect, i.e. motion perceived by sense;“vitale principium”the real cause, i.e. vital rational agency.990.“moventis et moti,”i.e. as concauses.991.“motum localem.”Sect. 52-65 discuss the reality of absolute or empty space, in contrast with concrete space realised in perception of the local relations of bodies. The meaninglessness of absolute space and motion is argued. Cf.Principles, sect. 116, 117. See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 13, 15, 17; alsoPapers which passed between Mr. Leibnitz and Dr. Clarke in 1715-16, pp. 55-59; 73-81; 97-103, &c. Leibniz calls absolute space“an ideal of some modern Englishman.”992.Newton'sPrincipia, Def. Sch. III. See also Derodon,Physica, P. I. cap. vi. § 1.993.Cf. Locke on a vacuum, and the“possibility of space existing without matter,”Essay, Bk. II. ch. 13.994.Note the account here given ofimaginationandintellect, as distinguished fromsense, which may be compared with αἴσθησις, φαντασία, and νοῦς in Aristotelian psychology.995.“attributorum divinorum particeps.”See Samuel Clarke, in hisDemonstration, and in thePapers between Clarke and Leibnitz.996.“nostrum,”sc. corpus. When we imagine space emptied of bodies, we are apt to forget that our own bodies are part of the material world.997.[Vide quæ contra spatium absolutum disseruntur in libroDe Principiis Cognitionis Humanæ, idiomate anglicano decem abhine annis edito.]—Author.He refers to sect. 116 of thePrinciples.998.He treats absolute space as nothing, and relative space as dependent on Perception and Will.999.Phys.α. 5. 188a. 22, 23.1000.See Locke,Essay, Bk. II. ch. 13, §§ 7-10.1001.Sect. 67-72 treat of the supposed ejection of motion from the striking body into the body struck. Is this only metaphorical? Is the motion received by the latter to be supposed identical with, or equivalent to, that given forth by the former?1002.Principia, Def. IV.1003.Lezioni Accademiche.1004.De Vi Percussionis, cap. IX.1005.Newton's third law of motion.1006.Berkeley sees in motion only a link in the chain which connects the sensible and intelligible worlds—a conception unfolded in hisSiris, more than twenty years later.1007.“provincia sua.”TheDe Motu, so far as it treats of motion perceptible to the senses, is assigned to physics; in contrast to theology or metaphysics, alone concerned with active causation.
Footnotes1.Philosophy of Theism: The Gifford Lectures delivered before the University of Edinburgh in 1894-96. (Second Edition, 1899.)2.Essay on Vision, sect. 147, 148.3.Principles, sect. 6.4.Preface to theThree Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous.5.By Anthony Collins.6.See vol. III, Appendix B.7.Murdoch Martin, a native of Skye, author of aVoyage to St. Kilda(1698), and aDescription of the Western Islands of Scotland(1703).8.See Stewart'sWorks(ed. Hamilton), vol. I. p. 161. There is a version of this story by DeQuincey, in his quaint essay onMurder considered as one of the Fine Arts.9.Sir John became Lord Percival in that year.10.A place more than once visited by Berkeley.11.Bakewell'sMemoirs of the Court of Augustus, vol. II. p. 177.12.A letter in Berkeley'sLife and Letters, p. 93, which led me to a different opinion, I have now reason to believe was not written by him, nor was it written in 1721. The research of Dr. Lorenz, confirmed by internal evidence, shews that it was written in October, 1684, before Berkeley the philosopher was born, and when the Duke of Ormond was Lord Lieutenant of Ireland. The writer was probably the Hon. and Rev. George Berkeley, a Prebendary of Westminster in 1687, who died in 1694. The wife of the“pious Robert Nelson”was a daughter of Earl Berkeley, and this“George”was her younger brother.13.Percival MSS.14.For the letter, see Editor's Preface to theProposal for a College in Bermuda, vol. IV. pp. 343-44.15.Afterwards Sir John James.16.Smibert the artist, who made a picture of Berkeley in 1725, and afterwards in America of the family party then at Gravesend.17.Historical Register, vol. XIII, p. 289 (1728).18.New England Weekly Courier, Feb. 3, 1729.19.For valuable information about Rhode Island, reproduced inBerkeley's Life and Correspondenceand here, I am indebted to Colonel Higginson, to whom I desire to make this tardy but grateful acknowledgement.20.James, Dalton, and Smibert.21.Whitehall, having fallen into decay, has been lately restored by the pious efforts of Mrs. Livingston Mason, in concert with the Rev. Dr. E. E. Hale, and others. This good work was completed in the summer of 1900; and the house is now as nearly as possible in the state in which Berkeley left it.22.See vol. III, Appendix C.23.Three Men of Letters, by Moses Coit Tyler (New York, 1895). He records some of the American academical and other institutions that are directly or indirectly, due to Berkeley.24.The thought implied in this paragraph is pursued in myPhilosophy of Theism, in which the ethical perfection of the Universal Mind is taken as the fundamental postulate in all human experience. If the Universal Mind is not ethically perfect, the universe (including our spiritual constitution) is radically untrustworthy.25.Life and Letters of Berkeley, p. 222.26.The third Earl of Shaftesbury, the pupil of Locke, and author of theCharacteristics. In addition to the well-known biography by Dr. Fowler, the present eminent Vice-Chancellor of Oxford, Shaftesbury has been interpreted in two other lately published works—aLifeby Benjamin Rand, Ph.D. (1900), and an edition of theCharacteristics, with an Introduction and Notes, by John M. Robertson (1900).27.The title of this book is—Things Divine and Supernatural conceived by Analogy with Things Natural and Human, by the Author ofThe Procedure, Extent and Limits of the Human Understanding. TheDivine Analogyappeared in 1733, and theProcedurein 1728.28.Spinoza argues that what iscalled“understanding”and“will”in God, has no more in common with human understanding and will than the dog-star in the heavens has with the animal we call a dog. See Spinoza'sEthica, I. 17,Scholium.29.The question of the knowableness of God, or Omnipotent Moral Perfection in the concrete, enters into recent philosophical and theological discussion in Britain. Calderwood, in hisPhilosophy of the Infinite(1854), was one of the earliest, and not the least acute, of Hamilton's critics in this matter. The subject is lucidly treated by Professor Andrew Seth (Pringle-Pattison) in hisLectures on Theism(1897) and in a supplement to Calderwood'sLife(1900). So also Huxley'sDavid Humeand Professor Iverach'sIs God Knowable?30.Stewart'sWorks. vol. I. pp. 350-1.31.Berkeley MSS. possessed by Archdeacon Rose.32.Pope's poetic tribute to Berkeley belongs to this period—“Even in a bishop I can spy desert;Secker is decent; Rundle has a heart:Manners with candour are to Benson given,To Berkeley—every virtue under heaven.”Epilogue to the Satires.Also his satirical tribute to the critics of Berkeley—“Truth's sacred fort th' exploded laugh shall win;And Coxcombs vanquish Berkeley with a grin.”Essay on Satire,Part II.33.Berkeley'sLife and Letters, p. 210.34.Bacon'sNovuin Organum. Distributio Operis.35.Section 141.36.See“Editor's Preface to Alciphron.”37.Compare Essay II in theGuardianwith this.38.Taylor, in later life, conformed to the Anglican Church.39.See Berkeley'sLife and Letters, chap. viii.40.The Primacy.41.This seems to have been his eldest son, Henry.42.His son George was already settled at Christ Church. Henry, the eldest son, born in Rhode Island, was then“abroad in the south of France for his health,”as one of his brother George's letters tells us, found among the Johnson MSS.43.See Appendix D. Reid, like Berkeley, held that“matter cannot be the cause of anything,”but this not as a consequence of the new conception of the world presented to the senses, through which alone Berkeley openshisway to its powerlessness; although Reid supposes that in his youth he followed Berkeley in this too. SeeThomas Reid(1898), in“Famous Scots Series,”where I have enlarged on this.44.Johnson MSS.45.That Berkeley was buried in Oxford is mentioned in his son's letter to Johnson, in which he says :“His remains are interred in the Cathedral of Christ Church, and next week a monument to his memory will be erected with an inscription by Dr. Markham, a Student of this College.”As the son was present at, and superintended the arrangements for his father's funeral, it can be no stretch of credulity to believe that he knew where his father was buried. It may be added that Berkeley himself had provided in his Will“that my body be buried in the churchyard of the parish in which I die.”The Will, dated July 31, 1752, is givenin extensoin myLife and Lettersof Berkeley, p. 345. We have also the record of burial in the Register of Christ Church Cathedral, which shews that“on January ye 20th1753, ye Right Reverend John (sic) Berkley, LdBishop of Cloyne, was buryed”there. This disposes of the statement on p. 17 of Diprose'sAccount of the Parish of Saint Clement Danes(1868), that Berkeley was buried in that church.I may add that a beautiful memorial of Berkeley has lately been placed in the Cathedral of Cloyne, by subscriptions in this country and largely in America.46.“General ideas,”i.e.abstractgeneral ideas, distinguished, in Berkeley's nominalism, fromconcretegeneral ideas, or from general names, which are signs of any one of an indefinite number of individual objects. Cf.Principles,Introduction, sect. 16.47.Introduction to thePrinciples of Human Knowledge.48.“co-existing ideas,”i.e. phenomena presented in uniform order to the senses.49.Newton postulates a world of matter and motion, governed mechanically by laws within itself: Berkeley finds himself charged with New Principles, demanded by reason, with which Newton's postulate is inconsistent.50.He attempts this in many parts of thePrinciplesandDialogues. He recognises the difficulty of reconciling his New Principles with theidentityandpermanenceof sensible things.51.He contemplated thus early applications of his New Principles to Mathematics, afterwards made in his book ofPrinciples, sect. 118-32.52.What Berkeley callsideasare either perceptible by the senses or imagined: either way they are concrete:abstract ideasare empty words.53.i.e. the existence of bodies and qualities independently of—in abstraction from—all percipient mind. While the spiritual theism of Descartes is acceptable, he rejects his mechanical conception of the material world.54.But a“house”or a“church”includes more thanvisibleideas, so that we cannot, strictly speaking, be said to see it. We see immediately only visible signs of its invisible qualities.55.This is added in the margin.56.The total impotence of Matter, and the omnipotence of Mind or Spirit in Nature, is thus early becoming the dominant thought with Berkeley.57.This refers to an objection to the New Principles that is apparently reinforced by recent discoveries in geology. But if these contradict the Principles, so does the existence of a table while I am only seeing it.58.Existence, in short, can be realised only in the form of living percipient mind.59.Berkeley hardly distinguishes uncontingent mathematicalrelations, to which the sensible ideas or phenomena in which the relations are concretely manifested must conform.60.M. T. = matter tangible; M. V. = matter visible; M. . = matter sensible. The distinctions n question were made prominent in theEssay on Vision. See sect. 1, 121-45.61.Which the common supposition regarding primary qualities seems to contradict.62.[That need not have been blotted out—'tis good sense, if we do but determine wtwe mean bythingandidea.]—Author, on blank page of the MS.63.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. III. ch. 4, § 8, where he criticises attempts to define motion, as involving apetitio.64.George Cheyne, the physician (known afterwards as author of theEnglish Malady), published in 1705 a work on Fluxions, which procured him admission to the Royal Society. He was born in 1670.65.This reminds us of Hume, and inclines towards the empirical notion of Causation, as merely constancy in sequence—not even continuous metamorphosis.66.This is Berkeley's objection to abstract, i.e. unperceived, quantities and infinitesimals—important in the sequel.67.The“lines and figures”of pure mathematics, that is to say; which he rejects as meaningless, in his horror unrealisable abstractions.68.Things really exist, that is to say, in degrees, e.g. in a lesser degree, when they are imagined than when they are actually perceived by our senses; but, in this wide meaning of existence, they may in both cases be said to exist.69.Added on blank page of the MS.70.In Berkeley's limitation of the termideato what is presented objectively in sense, or represented concretely in imagination. Accordingly“an infinite idea”would be an idea which transcends ideation—an express contradiction.71.Does thehumanspirit depend onsensibleideas as much as they depend on spirit? Other orders of spiritual beings may be percipient of other sorts of phenomena than those presented in those few senses to which man is confined, although self-conscious activity abstracted fromallsorts of presented phenomena seems impossible. But a self-conscious spirit is not necessarily dependent onourmaterial world oroursense experience.72.[This I do not altogether approve of.]—Author, on margin.73.He afterwards guarded the difference, by contrastingnotionandidea, confining the latter to phenomena presented objectively to our senses, or represented in sensuous imagination, and applying the former to intellectual apprehension of“operations of the mind,”and of“relations”among ideas.74.SeePrinciples, sect. 89.75.Is thought, then, independent of language? Can we realise thought worthy of the name without use of words? This is Berkeley's excessive juvenile reaction against verbal abstractions.76.Every general notion isideally realisablein one or other of its possible concrete or individual applications.77.This is the germ of Berkeley's notion of the objectivity of the material world to individual percipients and so of the rise of individual self-consciousness.78.Added by Berkeley on blank page of the MS.79.Cf. p.420, note 2. Bishop Sprat'sHistory of the Royal Societyappeared in 1667.80.Much need; for what he means byideahas not been attended to by his critics.81.What“Second Book”is this? Does he refer to the“Second Part”of thePrinciples, which never appeared? God is the culmination of his philosophy, inSiris.82.This is Berkeley's material substance. Individual material substances are for him, steady aggregates of sense-given phenomena, having the efficient and final cause of their aggregation in eternally active Mind—active mind, human and Divine, being essential to their realisation for man.83.Cf. Introduction to thePrinciples, especially sect. 18-25.84.Stillingfleet charges Locke with“discarding substance out of the reasonable part of the world.”85.The philosophers supposed the real things to exist behind our ideas, in concealment: Berkeley was now beginning to think that the objective ideas or phenomena presented to the senses, the existence of which needs no proof, werethemselvesthe significant and interpretable realities of physical science.86.If the material world can berealonly in and through a percipient intelligence, as the realising factor.87.Cf.Principles, sect. 13, 119-122, which deny the possibility of an idea or mental picture corresponding to abstract number.88.“Præcedaneous,”i.e. precedent.89.Who refunds human as well as natural causation into Divine agency.90.In which Locke treats“Of the Reality of Knowledge,”including questions apt to lead Berkeley to inquire, Whether we could in reason suppose reality in the absence of all realising mind.91.Locke's“abstract idea”is misconceived and caricatured by Berkeley in his impetuosity.92.This and other passages refer to the scepticism, that is founded on the impossibility of our comparing our ideas of things with unperceived real things; so that we can never escape from the circle of subjectivity. Berkeley intended to refute this scepticism.93.Probably Samuel Madden, who afterwards edited theQuerist.94.This“First Book”seems to be“Part I”of the projectedPrinciples—the only Part ever published. Here he inclines to“perception or thought in general,”in the language of Descartes; but in the end he approximates to Locke's“sensation and reflection.”SeePrinciples, sect. 1, and notes.95.Does he mean, like Hume afterwards, that ideas or phenomena constitute the ego, so that I am only the transitory conscious state of each moment?96.“Consciousness”—a term rarely used by Berkeley or his contemporaries.97.This too, if strictly interpreted, looks like an anticipation of Hume's reduction of the ego into successive“impressions”—“nothing but a bundle or collection of different perceptions, which succeed one another with inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and movement.”See Hume'sTreatise, Part IV. sect. 6.98.What“Third Book”is here projected? Was a“Third Part”of thePrinciplesthen in embryo?99.This is scarcely done in the“Introduction”to thePrinciples.100.Berkeley, as we find in theCommonplace Book, is fond of conjecturing how a man all alone in the world, freed from the abstractions of language, would apprehend the realities of existence, which he must then face directly, without the use or abuse of verbal symbols.101.This“N. B.”is expanded in the Introduction to thePrinciples.102.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 4.103.What is immediately realised in our percipient experience must be presumed or trusted in as real, if we have any hold of reality, or the moral right to postulate that our universe is fundamentally trustworthy.104.But he distinguishes, in thePrinciplesand elsewhere, between an idea of sense and a percipient ego.105.They reappear inSiris.106.In one of Berkeley's letters to Johnson, a quarter of a century after theCommonplace Book, when he was in America, he observes that“the mechanical philosophers pretend to demonstrate that matter is proportional to gravity. But their argument concludes nothing, and is a mere circle”—as he proceeds to show.107.In thePrinciples, sect. 1-33, he seeks to fulfil the expository part of this intention; in sect. 33-84, also in theDialogues between Hylas and Philonous, he is“particular in answering objections.”108.If Matter is arbitrarily credited with omnipotence.109.On freedom as implied in a moral and responsible agent, cf.Siris, sect. 257 and note.110.Is not this one way of expressing the Universal Providence and constant uniting agency of God in the material world?111.Hereideaseems to be used in its wider signification, includingnotion.112.“infinitely greater”—Does infinity admit of imaginable degrees?113.'embrangled'—perplexed—involved in disputes.114.SeePrinciples, Introduction, sect. 24.115.“homonymy,”i.e. equivocation.116.Voluntary or responsible activity is not an idea or datum of sense, nor can it be realised in sensuous imagination. He uses“thing”in the wide meaning which comprehends persons.117.Voluntary or responsible activity is not an idea or datum of sense, nor can it be realised in sensuous imagination. He uses“thing”in the wide meaning which comprehends persons.118.Is this consistent with other entries?119.Essay, Bk. II. ch. i. sect. 9-19.120.This is one way of meeting the difficulty of supposed interruptions of conscious or percipient activity.121.This seems to imply that voluntary action is mysteriously self-originated.122.“perception.”He does not include the percipient.123.“without,”i.e. unrealised by any percipient.124.This would makeideathe term only for what is imagined, as distinguished from what is perceived in sense.125.In a strict use of words, onlypersonsexercise will—notthings.126.As we must do in imagination, which (unlike sense) is representative; for the mental images represent original data of sense-perception.127.Does he not allow that we havemeaning, if notideas, when we use the terms virtue and vice and moral action?128.As Locke says we are.129.“Existenceandunityare ideas that are suggested to the understanding by every object without and every idea within. When ideas are in our minds, we consider thattheyexist.”Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 7. sect. 7.130.i.e. of Existence in the abstract—unperceived and unperceiving—realised neither in percipient life nor in moral action.131.This suggests that God knows sensible things without being sentient of any.132.Cf.Principles, Introd., sect. 1-5.133.Cf. Preface toPrinciples; also toDialogues.134.i.e. that ethics was a science of phenomena or ideas.135.i.e. of theindependentexistence of Matter.136.'bodies'—i.e. sensible things—not unrealised Matter.137.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 13.138.Locke died in October, 1704.139.“without the mind,”i.e. abstracted from all active percipient life.140.e.g. secondary qualities of sensible things, in which pleasure and pain are prominent.141.e.g. primary qualities, in which pleasure and pain are latent.142.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 13. § 21, ch. 17. § 4; also Bk. IV. ch. 3. § 6; also his controversy with Bishop Stillingfleet regarding the possibility of Matter thinking. With Berkeley real space is a finite creature, dependent for realisation on living percipient Spirit.143.But what of the origination of the volition itself?144.Essay, Bk. I. ch. iv. § 18. See also Locke'sLettersto Stillingfleet.145.It is, according to Berkeley, the steady union or co-existence of a group of sense-phenomena.146.Essay, Bk. II. ch. i. § 10—where he argues for interruptions of consciousness.“Men think not always.”147.In other words, the material world is wholly impotent: all activity in the universe is spiritual.148.On the order of its four books and the structure of Locke'sEssay, see the Prolegomena in my edition of theEssay, pp. liv-lviii.149.i.e. independent imperceptible Matter.150.What of the earliest geological periods, asks Ueberweg? But is there greater difficulty in such instances than in explaining the existence of a table or a house, while one is merely seeing, without touching?151.Locke explains“substance”as“an uncertain supposition of we know not what.”Essay, Bk. I. ch. 4. § 18.152.Locke makes certainty consist in the agreement of“our ideas with the reality of things.”SeeEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 4. § 18. Here the sceptical difficulty arises, which Berkeley meets under his Principle. If we have no perception of reality, we cannot compare our ideas with it, and so cannot have any criterion of reality.153.[This seems wrong. Certainty, real certainty, is of sensible ideas. I may be certain without affirmation or negation.—Author.] This needs further explanation.154.This entry and the preceding tends to resolve all judgments which are not what Kant calls analytical into contingent.155.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 1, §§ 3-7, and ch. 3. §§ 7-21. The stress Berkeley lays on“co-existence”is significant.156.i.e. we must not doubt the reality of the immediate data of sense but accept it, as“the mob”do.157.But is imagination different from actual perception only indegreeof reality?158.Cf.Principles, sect. 13, 120; also Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 7. sect. 7.159.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 1.160.Berkeley's aim evidently is to deliver men from empty abstractions, by a return to more reasonably interpreted common-sense.161.The sort ofexternalworld that is intelligible to us is that of whichanother personis percipient, and which isobjectiveto me, in a percipient experience foreign to mine.162.Cf. Berkeley'sArithmeticaandMiscellanea Mathematica, published while he was making his entries in thisCommonplace Book.163.Minima sensibilia?164.Pleasures,quâpleasures, are natural causes of correlative desires, as pains or uneasinesses are of correlative aversions. This is implied in the very nature of pleasure and pain.165.Here we have his explanation ofidea.166.Absent things.167.Here, as elsewhere, he resolves geometry, as strictly demonstrable, into a reasoned system of analytical or verbal propositions.168.Compare this with note 3, p. 34; also with the contrast between Sense and Reason, inSiris. Is the statement consistent with implied assumptions even in thePrinciples, apart from which they could not cohere?169.To have anideaof God—as Berkeley uses idea—would imply that God is an immediately perceptible, or at least an imaginable object.170.Cf.Principles, sect. 89.171.Ch. 11. § 5.172.Why add—“or perception”?173.Here we have Berkeley's favourite thought of the divine arbitrariness of the constitution of Nature, and of its laws of change.174.This suggests the puzzle, that the cause of every volition must be a preceding volition, and so onad infinitum.175.Recherche, I. 19.176.i.e. of his own individual mind.177.i.e. toapercipient mind, but not necessarily tomine; for natural laws are independent of individual will, although the individual participates in perception of the ordered changes.178.Cf. theArithmetica.179.i.e. which are not phenomena. This recognition of originative Will even then distinguished Berkeley.180.Is this Part II of thePrinciples, which was lost in Italy?181.The thought of articulaterelationsto which real existence must conform, was not then at least in Berkeley's mind. Hence the empiricism and sensationalism into which he occasionally seems to rush in theCommonplace Book, in his repulsion from empty abstractions.182.This is the essence of Berkeley's philosophy—“a blind agent is a contradiction.”183.This is the basis of Berkeley's reasoning for the necessarilyunrepresentativecharacter of the ideas or phenomena that are presented to our senses.Theyare the originals.184.Berkeley's horror of abstract or unperceived space and atoms is partly explained by dogmas in natural philosophy that are now antiquated.185.Ralph [?] Raphson, author ofDemonstratio de Deo(1710), and also ofDe Spatio Reali, seu ente Infinito: conamen mathematico-metaphysicum(1697), to which Berkeley refers in one of his letters to Johnson. See also Green'sPrinciples of Natural Philosophy(1712). The immanence of omnipotent goodness in the material world was unconsciously Berkeley's presupposition. In God we have our being.186.Note here Berkeley's version of the causal principle, which is really the central presupposition of his whole philosophy—viz. every event in the material world must be the issue of acting Will.187.So Locke on an ideally perfect memory.Essay, Bk. II. ch. x. § 9.188.John Sergeant was the author ofSolid Philosophy asserted against the Fancies of the Ideists(London, 1697); also ofthe Method to Science(1696). He was a deserter from the Church of England to the Church of Rome, and wrote several pieces in defence of Roman theology—some of them in controversy with Tillotson.189.Spirit and Matter are mutually dependent; but Spirit is the realising factor and real agent in the universe.190.See Descartes,Meditations, III; Spinoza,Epist.II, ad Oldenburgium.191.Cf.Principles, sect. 2.192.Is“inclusion”here virtually a synonym for verbal definition?193.SeePrinciples, sect. 2. The universe of Berkeley consists of Active Spirits that perceive and produce motion in impotent ideas or phenomena, realised in the percipient experience of persons. All supposed powers in Matter are refunded into Spirit.194.When self-conscious agents are included among“things.”We can have no sensuous image, i.e. idea, ofspirit, although he maintains we can use the word intelligently.195.Berkeley insists that we should individualise our thinking—“ipsis consuescere rebus,”as Bacon says,—to escape the dangers of artificial signs. This is the drift of his assault on abstract ideas, and his repulsion from what is not concrete. He would even dispense with words in his meditations in case of being sophisticated by abstractions.196.Nature or the phenomenal world in short is the revelation of perfectly reasonable Will.197.Gerard De Vries, the Cartesian.198.Are the things of sense only modes in which percipient persons exist?199.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 9. § 8.200.Time being relative to the capacity of the percipient.201.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 9. § 8.202.To perceive what is not an idea (as Berkeley uses idea) is to perceive what is not realised, and therefore not real.203.So things have apotentialobjective existence in the Divine Will.204.With Berkeley, change is time, and time, abstracted from all changes, is meaningless.205.Could he know, by seeing only, even that hehada body?206.“the ideas attending these impressions,”i.e. the ideas that are correlatives of the (by us unperceived) organic impressions.207.The Italian physical and metaphysical philosopher Fardella (1650-1718) maintained, by reasonings akin to those of Malebranche, that the existence of the material world could not be scientifically proved, and could only be maintained by faith in authoritative revelation. See hisUniversæ Philosophiæ Systema(1690), and especially hisLogica(1696).208.Locke'sEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 11.209.What does he mean by“unknown substratum”?210.He gets rid of the infinite in quantity, because it is incapable of concrete manifestation to the senses. When a phenomenon given in sense reaches theminimum sensibile, it reaches what is for us the margin of realisable existence: it cannot be infinitely little and still a phenomenon: insensible phenomena of sense involve a contradiction. And so too of the infinitely large.211.In short he would idealise the visible world but not the tangible world. In thePrinciples, Berkeley idealises both.212.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 149-59, where he concludes that“neither abstract nor visible extension makes the object of geometry.”213.By the adult, who has learned to interpret its visual signs.214.Inasmuch as no physical consequencesfollowthe volition; which however is still self-originated.215.“A succession of ideas I take toconstitutetime, and not to be only the sensible measure thereof, as Mr. Locke and others think.”(Berkeley's letter to Johnson.)216.Cf.Essay, Bk. II. ch. 16, sect. 8.217.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 67-77.218.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 88-120.219.This is of the essence of Berkeley's philosophy.220.But in moral freedom originates in the agent, instead of being“consecutive”to his voluntary acts or found only in their consequences.221.“Strigose”(strigosus)—meagre.222.As he afterwards expresses it, we have intelligiblenotions, but notideas—sensuous pictures—of the states or acts of our minds.223.[“Omnes reales rerum proprietates continentur in Deo.”What means Le Clerc &c. by this? Log. I. ch. 8.]—Author, on margin.224.“Si non rogas intelligo.”225.This way of winning others to his own opinions is very characteristic of Berkeley. See p.92and note.226.SeeThird Dialogue, onsamenessin things andsamenessin persons, which it puzzles him to reconcile with his New Principles.227.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 52-61.228.Cf.Principles, sect. 101-134.229.“distance”—on opposite page in the MS. Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 140.230.Direct perception of phenomena is adequate to the perceived phenomena; indirect or scientific perception is inadequate, leaving room for faith and trust.231.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 107-8.232.The Divine Ideas of Malebranche and the sensuous ideas of Berkeley differ.233.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 71.234.Cf. Malebranche,Recherche, Bk. I. c. 6. That and the following chapters seem to have been in Berkeley's mind.235.He here assumes that extension (visible) is implied in the visible idea we call colour.236.This strikingly illustrates Berkeley's use of“idea,”and what he intends when he argues against“abstract”ideas.237.An interesting autobiographical fact. From childhood he was indisposed to take things on trust.238.Essay on Vision, sect. 88-119.239.“thoughts,”i.e. ideas of sense?240.This, in a crude way, is the distinction of δύναμις and ἐνέργεια. It helps to explain Berkeley's meaning, when he occasionally speaks of the ideas or phenomena that appear in the sense experience of different persons as if they were absolutely independent entities.241.To be“in an unperceiving thing,”i.e. to be real, yet unperceived. Whatever is perceived is, because realised only through a percipient act, anidea—in Berkeley's use of the word.242.This as to the“Platonic strain”is not in the tone ofSiris.243.John Keill (1671-1721), an eminent mathematician, educated at the University of Edinburgh; in 1710 Savilian Professor of Astronomy at Oxford, and the first to teach the Newtonian philosophy in that University. In 1708 he was engaged in a controversy in support of Newton's claims to the discovery of the method of fluxions.244.This suggests a negative argument for Kant's antinomies, and for Hamilton's law of the conditioned.245.Newton became Sir Isaac on April 16, 1705. Was this written before that date?246.These may beconsideredseparately, but notpicturedas such.247.In as far as they have not been sensibly realised in finite percipient mind.248.[Or rather that invisible length does exist.]—Author, on margin.249.Bonaventura Cavalieri (1598-1647), the Italian mathematician. HisGeometry of Indivisibles(1635) prepared the way for the Calculus.250.[By“the excuse”is meant the finiteness of our mind—making it possible for contradictions to appear true to us.]—Author, on margin.251.He allows elsewhere that words with meanings not realisable in imagination, i.e. in the form of idea, may discharge a useful office. SeePrinciples, Introduction, sect. 20.252.We do not perceive unperceived matter, but only matter realised in living perception—the percipient act being the factor of its reality.253.The secondary qualities of things.254.Because, while dependent on percipient sense, they are independent ofmypersonal will, being determined to appear under natural law, by Divine agency.255.Keill'sIntroductio ad veram Physicam(Oxon. 1702)—Lectio 5—a curious work, dedicated to the Earl of Pembroke.256.[Extension without breadth—i. e. insensible, intangible length—is not conceivable. 'Tis a mistake we are led into by the doctrine of abstraction.]—Author, on margin of MS.257.Here“Sir Isaac.”Hence written after April, 1705.258.Essay, Bk. IV. ch. iv. sect. 18; ch. v. sect. 3, &c.259.He appliesthingto self-conscious persons as well as to passive objects of sense.260.Scaligerana Secunda, p. 270.261.[These arguments must be proposed shorter and more separate in the Treatise.]—Author, on margin.262.“Idea”here used in its wider meaning—for“operations of mind,”as well as for sense presented phenomena that are independent of individual will. Cf.Principles, sect. 1.263.“sensations,”i.e. objective phenomena presented in sense.264.SeePrinciples, sect. 1.265.SeePrinciples, sect. 2.266.An“unperceiving thing”cannot be the factor of material reality.267.[To the utmost accuracy, wanting nothing of perfection.Theirsolutions of problems, themselves must own to fall infinitely short of perfection.]—Author, on margin.268.Jean de Billy and René de Billy, French mathematicians—the former author ofNova Geometriæ Clavisand other mathematical works.269.According to Baronius, in the fifth volume of his“Annals,”Ficinus appeared after death to Michael Mercatus—agreeably to a promise he made when he was alive—to assure him of the life of the human spirit after the death of the body.270.So far as we are factors of their reality, in sense and in science, or can be any practical way concerned with them.271.Cf.Principles, sect. 101-34.272.“something,”i.e.abstractsomething.273.Lord Pembroke (?)—to whom thePrincipleswere dedicated, and to whom Locke dedicated hisEssay.274.This is an interesting example of a feature that is conspicuous in Berkeley—the art of“humoring an opponent in his own way of thinking,”which it seems was an early habit. It is thus that he insinuates his New Principles in theEssay on Vision, and so prepares to unfold and defend them in the book ofPrinciplesand the threeDialogues—straining language to reconcile them with ordinary modes of speech.275.In Diderot'sLettre sur les aveugles, à l'usage de ceux qui voient, where Berkeley, Molyneux, Condillac, and others are mentioned. Cf. also Appendix, pp. 111, 112; andTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 71, with the note, in which some recorded experiments are alluded to.276.De Anima, II. 6, III. 1, &c. Aristotle assigns a pre-eminent intellectual value to the sense of sight. See, for instance, hisMetaphysics, I. 1.277.Sir A. Grant, (Ethics of Aristotle, vol. II. p. 172) remarks, as to the doctrine that the Common Sensibles are apprehended concomitantly by the senses, that:“this is surely the true view; we see in the apprehension of number, figure, and the like, not an operation of sense, but the mind putting its own forms and categories, i.e. itself, on the external object. It would follow then that the senses cannot really be separated from the mind; the senses and the mind each contribute an element to every knowledge. Aristotle's doctrine of κοινὴ αἴσθησις would go far, if carried out, to modify his doctrine of the simple and innate character of the senses, e.g. sight (cf.Eth.II. 1, 4), and would prevent its collision with Berkeley'sTheory of Vision.”—See also Sir W. Hamilton,Reid's Works, pp. 828-830.Dugald Stewart (Collected Works, vol. I. p. 341, note) quotes Aristotle'sEthics, II. 1, as evidence that Berkeley's doctrine,“with respect to the acquired perceptions of sight, was quite unknown to the best metaphysicians of antiquity.”278.A work resembling Berkeley's in its title, but in little else, appeared more than twenty years before theEssay—theNova Visionis Theoriaof Dr. Briggs, published in 1685.279.SeeTreatise on the Eye, vol. II. pp. 299, &c.280.See Reid'sInquiry, ch. v. §§ 3, 5, 6, 7; ch. vi. § 24, andEssays on the Intellectual Powers, II. ch. 10 and 19.281.While Sir W. Hamilton (Lectures on Metaphysics, lxxviii) acknowledges the scientific validity of Berkeley's conclusions, as to the way we judge of distances, he complains, in the same lecture, that“the whole question is thrown into doubt by the analogy of the lower animals,”i.e. by their probablevisual instinctof distances; and elsewhere (Reid'sWorks, p. 137, note) he seems to hesitate about Locke's Solution of Molyneux's Problem, at least in its application to Cheselden's case. Cf. Leibniz,Nouveaux Essais, Liv. II. ch. 9, in connexion with this last.282.An almost solitary exception in Britain to this unusual uniformity on a subtle question in psychology is found in Samuel Bailey'sReview of Berkeley's Theory of Vision, designed to show the unsoundness of that celebrated Speculation, which appeared in 1842. It was the subject of two interesting rejoinders—a well-weighed criticism, in theWestminster Review, by J.S. Mill, since republished in hisDiscussions; and an ingenious Essay by Professor Ferrier, inBlackwood's Magazine, republished in hisPhilosophical Remains. The controversy ended on that occasion with Bailey'sLetter to a Philosopher in reply to some recent attempts to vindicate Berkeley's Theory of Vision, and in further elucidation of its unsoundness, and a reply to it by each of his critics. It was revived in 1864 by Mr. Abbott of Trinity College, Dublin, whose essay onSight and Touchis“an attempt to disprove the received (or Berkeleian) Theory of Vision.”283.Afterwards (in 1733) Earl of Egmont. Born about 1683, he succeeded to the baronetcy in 1691, and, after sitting for a few years in the Irish House of Commons, was in 1715 created Baron Percival, in the Irish peerage. In 1732 he obtained a charter to colonise the province of Georgia in North America. His name appears in the list of subscribers to Berkeley's Bermuda Scheme in 1726. He died in 1748. He corresponded frequently with Berkeley from 1709 onwards.284.Similar terms are applied to the sense of seeing by writers with whom Berkeley was familiar. Thus Locke (Essay, II. ix. 9) refers to sight as“the most comprehensive of all our senses.”Descartes opens hisDioptriqueby designating it as“le plus universal et le plus noble de nos sens;”and he alludes to it elsewhere (Princip.IV. 195) as“le plus subtil de tous les sens.”Malebranche begins his analysis of sight (Recherche, I. 6) by describing it as“le premier, le plus noble, et le plus étendu de tous les sens.”The high place assigned to this sense by Aristotle has been already alluded to. Its office, as the chief organ through which a conception of the material universe as placed in ambient space is given to us, is recognised by a multitude of psychologists and metaphysicians.285.On Berkeley's originality in his Theory of Vision see the Editor's Preface.286.In the first edition alone this sentence followed:—“In treating of all which, it seems to me, the writers of Optics have proceeded on wrong principles.”287.Sect. 2-51 explain the way in which we learn in seeing to judge of Distance or Outness, and of objects as existing remote from our organism, viz. by their association with what we see, and with certain muscular and other sensations in the eye which accompany vision. Sect. 2 assumes, as granted, the invisibility of distance in the line of sight. Cf. sect. 11 and 88—First Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous—Alciphron, IV. 8—Theory of Vision Vindicated and Explained, sect. 62-69.288.i.e. outness, or distance outward from the point of vision—distance in the line of sight—the third dimension of space. Visible distance is visible space or interval between two points (see sect. 112). We can be sensibly percipient of it only whenbothpoints are seen.289.This section is adduced by some of Berkeley's critics as if it were the evidence discovered by him for hisTheory, instead of being, as it is, a passing reference to the scientific ground of the already acknowledged invisibility of outness, or distance in the line of sight. See, for example, Bailey'sReview of Berkeley's Theory of Vision, pp. 38-43, also hisTheory of Reasoning, p. 179 and pp. 200-7—Mill'sDiscussions, vol. II. p. 95—Abbott'sSight and Touch, p. 10, where this sentence is presented as“the sole positive argument advanced by Berkeley.”The invisibility of outness is not Berkeley's discovery, but the way we learn to interpret its visual signs, and what these are.290.i.e. aerial and linear perspective are acknowledged signs of remote distances. But the question, in this and the thirty-six following sections, concerns the visibility ofneardistances only—a few yards in front of us. It was“agreed by all”that beyond this limit distances are suggested by our experience of their signs.291.Cf. this and the four following sections with the quotations in the Editor's Preface, from Molyneux'sTreatise of Dioptrics.292.In the author's last edition we have this annotation:“See what Des Cartes and others have written upon the subject.”293.In the first edition this section opens thus:“I have here set down the common current accounts that are given of our perceiving near distances by sight, which, though they are unquestionably received for true by mathematicians, and accordingly made use of by them in determining the apparent places of objects, do nevertheless,”&c.294.Omitted in the author's last edition.295.i.e. although immediately invisible, it is mediately seen. Mark, here and elsewhere, the ambiguity of the termperception, which now signifies the act of being conscious of sensuous phenomena, and again the act of inferring phenomena of which we are at the time insentient; while it is also applied to the object perceived instead of to the percipient act; and sometimes to imagination, and the higher acts of intelligence.296.“Some men”—“mathematicians,”in first edition.297.i.e. themediateperception.298.“any man”—“all the mathematicians in the world,”in first edition.299.Omitted in the author's last edition.300.Omitted in the author's last edition.301.Sect. 3, 9.302.Observe the first introduction by Berkeley of the termsuggestion, used by him to express a leading factor in his account of the visible world, and again in his more comprehensive account of our knowledge of the material universe in thePrinciples. It had been employed occasionally, among others, by Hobbes and Locke. There are three ways in which the objects we have an immediate perception of in sight may be supposed to conduct us to what we do not immediately perceive: (1) Instinct, or what Reid calls“original suggestion”(Inquiry, ch. VI. sect. 20-24); (2) Custom; (3) Reasoning from accepted premisses. Berkeley's“suggestion”corresponds to the second. (Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 42.)303.In theTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 66, it is added that this“sensation”belongs properly to the sense of touch. Cf. also sect. 145 of thisEssay.304.Here“natural”=“necessary”: elsewhere=divinely arbitrary connexion.305.That ourmediatevision of outness and of objects as thus external, is due to media which have a contingent or arbitrary, instead of a necessary, connexion with the distances which they enable us to see, or of which they are the signs, is a cardinal part of his argument.306.Sect. 2.307.Here, as generally in theEssay, the appeal is to our inward experience, not to phenomena observed by our senses in the organism.308.See sect. 35 for the difference between confused and faint vision. Cf. sect. 32-38 with this section. AlsoTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 68.309.See sect. 6.310.These sections presuppose previous contiguity as an associative law of mental phenomena.311.See Reid'sInquiry, ch. vi. sect. 22.312.Sect. 16-27.—For the signs of remote distances, see sect. 3.313.These are muscular sensations felt in the organ, and degrees of confusion in a visible idea. Berkeley's“arbitrary”signs of distance, near and remote, are either (a) invisible states of the visual organ, or (b) visible appearances.314.In Molyneux'sTreatise of Dioptrics, Pt. I. prop. 31, sect. 9, Barrow's difficulty is stated. Cf. sect. 40 below.315.Christopher Scheiner, a German astronomer, and opponent of the Copernican system, born 1575, died 1650.316.Andrea Tacquet, a mathematician, born at Antwerp in 1611, and referred to by Molyneux as“the ingenious Jesuit.”He published a number of scientific treatises, most of which appeared after his death, in a collected form, at Antwerp in 1669.317.In what follows Berkeley tries to explain by his visual theory seeming contradictions which puzzled the mathematicians.318.This is offered as a verification of the theory that near distances are suggested, according to the order of nature, by non-resembling visual signs, contingently connected with real distance.319.Cf. sect. 78; alsoNew Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 31.320.Berkeley here passes from his proof of visual“suggestion”of all outward distances—i.e. intervals between extremes in the line of sight—by means of arbitrary signs, and considers the nature of visible externality. See note in Hamilton'sReid, p. 177, on the distinction between perception of the external world and perception of distance through the eye.321.See Descartes,Dioptrique, VI—Malebranche,Recherche, Liv. I. ch. 9, 3—Reid'sInquiry, VI. 11.322.Berkeley here begins to found, on the experienced connexion between extension and colour, and between visible and tangible extension, a proof thatoutnessis invisible. From Aristotle onwards it has been assumed that colour is the only phenomenon of which we are immediately percipient in seeing. Visible extension, visible figure, and visible motion are accordingly taken to be dependent on the sensation of colour.323.In connexion with this and the next illustration, Berkeley seems to argue that we are not only unable to see distance in the line of sight, but also that we do not see a distant object in itsreal visiblemagnitude. But elsewhere he affirms that onlytangiblemagnitude is entitled to be calledreal. Cf. sect. 55, 59, 61.324.The sceptical objections to the trustworthiness of the senses, proposed by the Eleatics and others, referred to by Descartes in hisMeditations, and by Malebranche in the First Book of hisRecherche, may have suggested the illustrations in this section. Cf. also Hume's EssayOn the Academical or Sceptical Philosophy. The sceptical difficulty is founded on the assumption that the object seen at different distances is thesame visible object: it is really different, and so the difficulty vanishes.325.Here Berkeley expressly introduces“touch”—a term which with him includes, not merely organic sense of contact, but also muscular and locomotive sense-experience. After this he begins to unfold the antithesis of visual and tactual phenomena, whose subsequent synthesis it is the aim of theNew Theoryto explain. Cf.Principles of Human Knowledge, sect. 43—Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 22 and 25. Note here Berkeley's reticence of his idealization of Matter—tangible as well as visible. Cf.Principles, sect. 44.326.This connexion of our knowledge of distance with our locomotive experience points to a theory which ultimately resolves space into experience of unimpeded locomotion.327.Locke (Essay, Introduction, § 8) takesideavaguely as“the term which serves best to stand whatsoever is the object of the understanding when a man thinks.”Oversight of what Berkeley intends the term idea has made his whole conception of nature and the material universe a riddle to many, of which afterwards.328.The expressive term“outness,”favoured by Berkeley, is here first used.329.“We get the idea of Space,”says Locke,“both by our sight and touch”(Essay, II. 13. § 2). Locke did not contemplate Berkeley's antithesis of visible and tangible extension, and the consequent ambiguity of the term extension; which sometimes signifiescoloured, and at othersresistantexperience in sense.330.For an explanation of this difficulty, see sect. 144.331.“object”—“thing,”in the earlier editions.332.This is the issue of the analytical portion of theEssay.333.Cf. sect. 139-40.334.Here the question of externality, signifying independence of all percipient life, is again mixed up with that of the invisibility of distance outwards in the line of sight.335.Omitted in author's last edition.336.i.e. including muscular and locomotive experience as well as sense of contact. But what are thetangibiliathemselves? Are they also significant, likevisibilia, of a still ulterior reality? This is the problem of thePrinciples of Human Knowledge.337.In this section the conception of a natural Visual Language, makes its appearance, with its implication that Nature is (for us) virtually Spirit. Cf. sect. 140, 147—Principles, sect. 44—Dialogues of Hylas and Philonous—Alciphron, IV. 8, 11—andTheory of Vision Vindicated, passim.338.Sect. 52-87 treat of the invisibility of real, i.e. tactual, Magnitude. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 54-61.339.Sect. 8-15.340.Sect. 41, &c.341.See Molyneux'sTreatise on Dioptrics, B. I. prop. 28.342.See sect. 122-126.343.In short there is a point at which, with our limited sense, we cease to be percipient of colour, in seeing; and of resistance, in locomotion. Though Berkeley regards all visible extensions as sensible, and therefore dependent for their reality on being realised by sentient mind, he does not mean that mind or consciousness is extended. With him, extension, though it exists only in mind,—i.e. as an idea seen, in the case of visible extension, and as an idea touched, in the case of tangible extension,—is yet nopropertyof mind. Mind can exist without being percipient of extension, although extension cannot be realised without mind.344.But this is true, though less obviously, of tangible as well as of visible objects.345.Sect. 49.346.Cf. sect. 139, 140, &c.347.“situation”—not in the earlier editions.348.Sect. 55.349.Omitted in the author's last edition.350.Ordinary sight is virtually foresight. Cf. sect. 85.—See also Malebranche on the external senses, as given primarily for the urgent needs of embodied life, not to immediately convey scientific knowledge,Recherche, Liv. I. ch. 5, 6, 9, &c.351.Sect. 44.—See also sect. 55, and note.352.This supposes“settled”tangibilia, but not“settled”visibilia. Yet the sensible extension given in touch and locomotive experience is also relative—an object beingfeltas larger or smaller according to the state of the organism, and the other conditions of our embodied perception.353.What follows, to end of sect. 63, added in the author's last edition.354.“outward objects,”i.e. objects of which we are percipient in tactual experience, taken in thisEssayprovisionally as the real external objects. SeePrinciples, sect. 44.355.Cf. sect. 144. Note, in this and the three preceding sections, the stress laid on thearbitrarinessof the connexion between the signs which suggest magnitudes, or other modes of extension, and their significates. This is the foundation of theNew Theory; which thus resolvesphysicalcausality into a relation of signs to what they signify and predict—analogous to the relation between words and their accepted meanings.356.In sect. 67-78, Berkeley attempts to verify the foregoing account of the natural signs of Size, by applying it to solve a phenomenon, the cause of which had been long debated among men of science—the visible magnitude of heavenly bodies when seen in the horizon.357.Cf. sect. 10.358.Omitted in the author's last edition. Cf sect. 76, 77.—The explanation in question is attributed to Alhazen, and by Bacon to Ptolemy, while it is sanctioned by eminent scientific names before and since Berkeley.359.“Fourthly”in the second edition. Cf. what follows with sect. 74. Why“lesser”?360.When Berkeley, some years afterwards, visited Italy, he remarked that distant objects appeared to him much nearer than they really were—a phenomenon which he attributed to the comparative purity of the southern air.361.i.e. the original perception, apart from any synthetic operation of suggestion and inferential thought, founded on visual signs.362.In Riccioli'sAlmagest, II. lib. X. sect. 6. quest. 14, we have an account of many hypotheses then current, in explanation of the apparent magnitude of the horizontal moon.363.Gassendi's“Epistolæ quatuor de apparente magnitudine solis humilis et sublimis.”—Opera, tom. III pp. 420-477. Cf. Appendix to thisEssay, p. 110.364.SeeDioptrique, VI.365.Opera Latina, vol. I, p. 376, vol. II, pp. 26-62;English Works, vol. I. p. 462. (Molesworth's Edition.)366.The paper in the Transactions is by Molyneux.367.See Smith'sOptics, pp. 64-67, andRemarks, pp. 48, &c. At p. 55 Berkeley'sNew Theoryis referred to, and pronounced to be at variance with experience. Smith concludes by saying, that in“the second edition of Berkeley'sEssay, and also in a Vindication and Explanation of it (called theVisual Language), very lately published, the author has made some additions to his solution of the said phenomenon; but seeing it still involves and depends on the principle of faintness, I may leave the rest of it to the reader's consideration.”This, which appeared in 1738, is one of the very few early references to Berkeley'sNew Theory of Vision Vindicated.368.Sect. 2-51.369.This sentence is omitted in the author's last edition.370.What follows to the end of this section is not contained in the first edition.371.i.e. tangible.372.Cf. sect. 38; andTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 31.373.“Never”—“hardly,”in first edition.374.Cf. Appendix, p.208.—See Smith'sOptics, B. I. ch. v, andRemarks, p. 56, in which he“leaves it to be considered, whether the said phenomenon is not as clear an instance of the insufficiency of faintness”as of mathematical computation.375.A favourite doctrine with Berkeley, according to whose theory of visibles there can be no absolute visible magnitude, theminimumbeing the least that isperceivableby each seeing subject, and thus relative to his visual capacity. This section is thus criticised, in January, 1752, in a letter signed“Anti-Berkeley,”in theGent. Mag.(vol. XXII, p. 12):“Upon what his lordship asserts with respect to theminimum visibile, I would observe that it is certain that there are infinite numbers of animals which are imperceptible to the naked eye, and cannot be perceived but by the help of a microscope; consequently there are animals whose whole bodies are far less than theminimum visibileof a man. Doubtless these animals have eyes, and, if theirminimum visibilewere equal to that of a man, it would follow that they cannot perceive anything but what is much larger than their whole body; and therefore their own bodies must be invisible to them, because we know they are so to men, whoseminimum visibileis asserted by his lordship to be equal to theirs.”There is some misconception in this. Cf. Appendix toEssay, p. 209.376.Those two defects belong to human consciousness. See Locke'sEssay, II. 10, on the defects of human memory. It is this imperfection which makes reasoning needful—to assist finite intuition. Reasoning is the sign at once of our dignity and our weakness.377.Sect. 59.378.Sect. 80-82.379.Sect. 88-119 relate to the nature, invisibility, and arbitrary visual signs of Situation, or of the localities of tangible things. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 44-53.380.Cf. sect. 2, 114, 116, 118.381.This illustration is taken from Descartes. See Appendix.382.Sect. 10 and 19.383.Sect. 2-51.384.Omitted in author's last edition.385.This is Berkeley's universal solvent of the psychological difficulties involved in visual-perception.386.Cf. sect. 103, 106, 110, 128, &c. Berkeley treats this case hypothetically in theEssay, in defect of actual experiments upon the born-blind, since accumulated from Cheselden downwards. See however the Appendix, andTheory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 71.387.i.e. tangible things. Cf.Principles, sect. 44.388.The“prejudice,”to wit, which Berkeley would dissolve by his introspective analysis of vision. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 35.389.Thus forming individual concrete things out of what is perceived separately through different senses.390.This briefly is Berkeley's solution of“the knot about inverted images,”which long puzzled men of science.391.i.e. perceivemediately—visible objects,per se, having no tactual situation. Pure vision, he would say, has nothing to do with“high”and“low,”“great”and“inverted,”in the real or tactual meaning of those terms.392.i.e. tangible.393.e.g.“extension,”which, according to Berkeley, is an equivocal term, common (in its different meanings) tovisibiliaandtangibilia. Cf. sect. 139, 140.394.Cf. sect. 93, 106, 110, 128.395.i.e. real or tangible head.396.Cf. sect. 140, 143. In theGent. Mag.(vol. XXII. p. 12),“Anti-Berkeley”thus argues the case of one born blind.“This man,”he adds,“would, by being accustomed to feel one hand with the other, have perceived that the extremity of the hand was divided into fingers—that the extremities of these fingers were distinguished by certain hard, smooth surfaces, of a different texture from the rest of the fingers—and that each finger had certain joints or flexures. Now, if this man was restored to sight, and immediately viewed his hand before he touched it again, it is manifest that the divisions of the extremity of the hand into fingers would be visibly perceived. He would note too the small spaces at the extremity of each finger, which affected his sight differently from the rest of the fingers; upon moving his fingers he would see the joints. Though therefore, by means of this lately acquired sense of seeing, the object affected his mind in a new and different manner from what it did before, yet, as bytouchhe had acquired the knowledge of these several divisions, marks, and distinctions of the hand, and, as the new object ofsightappeared to be divided, marked, and distinguished in a similar manner, I think he would certainly conclude,before he touched his hand, that the thing which he now saw wasthe samewhich he had felt before and called his hand.”397.Locke,Essay, II. 8, 16. Aristotle regards number as a Common Sensible.—De Anima, II. 6, III. 1.398.“If the visible appearance of two shillings had been found connected from the beginning with the tangible idea of one shilling, that appearance would as naturally and readily have signified the unity of the (tangible) object as it now signifies its duplicity.”Reid,Inquiry, VI. 11.399.Here again note Berkeley's inconvenient reticence of his full theory of matter, as dependent on percipient life for its reality. Tangible things are meantime granted to be real“without mind.”Cf.Principles, sect. 43, 44.“Without the mind”—in contrast to sensuous phenomenon only.400.Cf. sect. 131.401.Sect. 2, 88, 116, 118.402.In short, weseeonlyquantities of colour—the real or tactual distance, size, shape, locality, up and down, right and left, &c., being gradually associated with the various visible modifications of colour.403.i.e. tangible.404.Sect. 41-44.405.i.e. tangible things.406.i.e. visible.407.Cf. sect. 41-44. The“eyes”—visible and tangible—are themselves objects of sense.408.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 21-25.409.“Visible ideas”—including sensations muscular and locomotive,feltin the organ of vision. Sect. 16, 27, 57.410.i.e. objects which, in this tentativeEssay, are granted, for argument's sake, to be external, or independent of percipient mind.411.i.e. to inquire whether there are, in this instance, Common Sensibles; and, in particular, whether anextensionof the same kind at least, if not numerically the same, is presented in each. The Kantian theory of ana prioriintuition of space, the common condition of tactual and visual experience, because implied in sense-experience as such, is not conceived by Berkeley. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 15.412.In the following reasoning against abstract, as distinguished from concrete or sense presented (visible or tangible) extension, Berkeley urges some of his favourite objections to“abstract ideas,”fully unfolded in hisPrinciples, Introduction, sect. 6-20.—See alsoAlciphron, VII. 5-8.—Defence of Free Thinking in Mathematics, sect. 45-48.413.Berkeley'sideasare concrete or particular—immediate data of sense or imagination.414.i.e. it cannot be individualized, either as a perceived or an imagined object.415.Sect. 105.416.“Endeavours”in first edition.417.i.e. a mental image of an abstraction, an impossible image, in which the extension and comprehension of the notion must be adequately pictured.418.“deservedly admired author,”in the first edition.419.“this celebrated author,”—“that great man”in second edition. In assailing Locke's“abstract idea,”he discharges the meaning which Locke intended by the term, and then demolishes his own figment.420.Omitted in the author's last edition.421.Omitted in last edition.422.Omitted in last edition.423.Omitted in last edition.424.SeePrinciples, passim.425.Omitted in author's last edition.426.He probably has Locke in his eye.427.On Berkeley's theory, space without relation to bodies (i.e. insensible or abstract space) would not be extended, as not having parts; inasmuch as parts can be assigned to it only with relation to bodies. Berkeley does not distinguish space from sensible extension. Cf. Reid'sWorks, p. 126, note—in which Sir W. Hamilton suggests that one may have ana prioriconception of pure space, andalsoana posterioriperception of finite, concrete space.428.Sect. 121. Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 15.429.i.e. there are no Common Sensibles: from which it follows that we can reason from the one sense to the other only by founding on the constant connexion of their respective phenomena, under a natural yet (for us) contingent law. Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 27, 28.430.Omitted in last edition.431.Cf. sect. 93, 103, 106, 110.432.Omitted in last edition.433.Cf. sect. 43, 103, &c. A plurality of co-existentminimaof coloured points constitutes Berkeley's visible extension; while a plurality of successively experiencedminimaof resistant points constitutes his tactual extension. Whether we can perceive visible extension without experience of muscular movement at least in the eye, he does not here say.434.Omitted in last edition.435.Real distance belongs originally, according to theEssay, to our tactual experience only—in the wide meaning of touch, which includes muscular and locomotive perceptions, as well as the simple perception of contact.436.Added in second edition.437.Omitted in last edition.438.See also Locke's“Correspondence”with Molyneux, in Locke'sWorks, vol. IX. p. 34.—Leibniz,Nouveaux Essais, Liv. II. ch. 9, who, so far granting the fact, disputes the heterogeneity.—Smith'sOptics.—Remarks, §§ 161-170.—Hamilton's Reid, p. 137, note, andLect. Metaph.II. p. 176.439.Omitted in last edition.440.Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 70.441.Cf. sect. 49, 146, &c. Here“same”includes“similar.”442.i.e. visible and tangible motions being absolutely heterogeneous, and the former,at man's point of view, only contingent signs of the latter, we should not, at first sight, be able to interpret the visual signs of tactual phenomena.443.Cf. sect. 122-125.444.Cf.Principles, sect. 111-116; alsoAnalyst, query 12. On Berkeley's system space in its three dimensions is unrealisable without experience of motion.445.Here the term“language of nature”makes its appearance, as applicable to the ideas or visual signs of tactual realities.446.Cf. sect. 16, 27, 97.447.Is“tangible”here used in its narrow meaning—excluding muscular and locomotive experience?448.i.e. as natural signs, divinely associated with their thus implied meanings.449.Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 35.450.Berkeley, in this section, enunciates the principal conclusion in theEssay, which conclusion indeed forms his new theory of Vision.451.A suggestion thus due to natural laws of association. The explanation of the fact that we apprehend, by those ideas or phenomena which are objects of sight, certain other ideas, which neither resemble them, nor efficiently cause them, nor are so caused by them, nor have any necessary connexion with them, comprehends, according to Berkeley, the whole Theory of Vision.“The imagination of every thinking person,”remarks Adam Smith,“will supply him with instances to prove that the ideas received by any one of the senses do readily excite such other ideas, either of the same sense or of any other, as have habitually been associated with them. So that if, on this account, we are to suppose, with a late ingenious writer, that the ideas of sight constitute a Visual Language, because they readily suggest the corresponding ideas of touch—as the terms of a language excite the ideas answering to them—I see not but we may, for the same reason, allow of a tangible, audible, gustatory, and olefactory language; though doubtless the Visual Language will be abundantly more copious than the rest.”Smith'sOptics.—Remarks, p. 29.—And into this conception of a universal sense symbolism, Berkeley's theory of Vision ultimately rises.452.Cf.Alciphron, Dialogue IV. sect. 11-15.453.Sect. 122-125.454.Sect. 127-138.455.Some modern metaphysicians would say, that neither tangible nor visible extension is the object geometry, but abstract extension; and others that space is a necessary implicate of sense-experience, rather than,per se, an object of any single sense. Cf. Kant's explanation of the origin of our mathematical knowledge,Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Elementarlehre, I.456.Cf. sect. 51-66, 144.457.This is a conjecture, not as to the probable ideas of one born blind, but as to the ideas of an“unbodied”intelligence, whoseonlysense was that of seeing. See Reid's speculation (Inquiry, VI. 9) on the“Geometry of Visibles,”and the mental experience of Idomenians, or imaginary beings supposed to have no ideas of the material world except those got by seeing.458.Cf. sect. 130, andNew Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 57. Does Berkeley, in this and the two preceding sections, mean to hint that the only proper object of sight isunextendedcolour; and that, apart from muscular movement in the eye or other locomotion,visibiliaresolve into unextended mathematical points? This question has not escaped more recent British psychologists, including Stewart, Brown, Mill, and Bain, who seem to hold that unextended colour is perceivable and imaginable.459.The bracketed sentence is not retained in the author's last edition, in which the first sentence of sect. 160 is the concluding one of sect. 159, and of theEssay.460.This passage is contained in theDioptricesof Descartes, VI. 13; see also VI. 11.461.The arbitrariness or contingency—as far as our knowledge carries us—of the connexion between the visual phenomena, as signs, on the one hand, and actual distance, as perceived through this means, on the other.462.Cf. sect. 80-83.463.The reference here seems to be to the case described in theTatler(No. 55) of August 16, 1709, in which William Jones, born blind, had received sight after a surgical operation, at the age of twenty, on the 29th of June preceding. A medical narrative of this case appeared, entitledA full and true account of a miraculous cure of a Young Man in Newington, who was born blind, and was in five minutes brought to perfect sight, by Mr. Roger Grant, oculist. London, 1709.464.Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 71, with the relative note.465.Omitted on the title-page in the second edition, but retained in the body of the work.466.Beardsley'sLife and Correspondence of Samuel Johnson, D.D., First President of King's College, New York, p. 72 (1874).467.Beardsley'sLife of Johnson, pp. 71, 72.468.Chandler'sLife of Johnson, Appendix, p. 161.469.Commonplace Book.470.Moreover, even if the outness or distance of thingswerevisible, it would not follow that either they or their distances could be real if unperceived. On the contrary, Berkeley implies that theyareperceivedvisually.471.It is also to be remembered that sensible things exist“in mind,”without being exclusivelymine, as creatures ofmy will. In one sense, that only is mine in which my will exerts itself. But, in another view, my involuntary states of feeling and imagination aremine, because their existence depends on my consciousness of them; and even sensible things are so farmine, because, though present in many minds in common, they are, for me, dependent onmypercipient mind.472.Thomas Herbert, eighth Earl of Pembroke and fifth Earl of Montgomery, was the correspondent and friend of Locke—who dedicated his famousEssayto him, as a work“having some little correspondence with some parts of that nobler and vast system of the sciences your lordship has made so new, exact, and instructive a draft of.”He represents a family renowned in English political and literary history. He was born in 1656; was a nobleman of Christ Church, Oxford, in 1672; succeeded to his titles in 1683; was sworn of the Privy Council in 1689; and made a Knight of the Garter in 1700. He filled some of the highest offices in the state, in the reigns of William and Mary, and of Anne. He was Lord Lieutenant of Ireland in 1707, having previously been one of the Commissioners by whom the union between England and Scotland was negotiated. He died in January 1733.473.Trinity College, Dublin.474.In hisCommonplace BookBerkeley seems to refer his speculations to his boyhood. The conception of the material world propounded in the following Treatise was in his view before the publication of theNew Theory of Vision, which was intended to prepare the way for it.475.Cf. Locke, in the“Epistle Dedicatory”of hisEssay. Notwithstanding the“novelty”of the New Principles, viz.negationof abstract or unperceived Matter, Space, Time, Substance, and Power; andaffirmationof Mind, as the Synthesis, Substance, and Cause of all—much in best preceding philosophy, ancient and modern, was a dim anticipation of it.476.Cf. sect. 6, 22, 24, &c., in illustration of the demonstrative claim of Berkeley's initial doctrine.477.Berkeley entreats his reader, here and throughout, to take pains to understand his meaning, and especially to avoid confounding the ordered ideas or phenomena, objectively presented to our senses, with capricious chimeras of imagination.478.“Philosophy is nothing but the true knowledge of things.”Locke.479.The purpose of those early essays of Berkeley was to reconcile philosophy with common sense, by employing reflection to makelatentcommon sense, or common reason, reveal itself in its genuine integrity. Cf. the closing sentences in theThird Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.480.Cf. Locke'sEssay, Introduction, sect. 4-7; Bk. II. ch. 23, § 12, &c. Locke (who is probably here in Berkeley's eye) attributes the perplexities of philosophy to our narrow faculties, which are meant to regulate our lives, not to remove all mysteries. See also Descartes,Principia, I. 26, 27, &c.; Malebranche,Recherche, III. 2.481.His most significant forerunners were Descartes in hisPrincipia, and Locke in hisEssay.482.Here“idea”and“notion”seem to be used convertibly. See sect. 142. Cf. with the argument againstabstract ideas, unfolded in the remainder of the Introduction,Principles, sect. 97-100, 118-132, 143;New Theory of Vision, sect. 122-125;Alciphron, Dial. vii. 5-7;Defence of Free Thinking in Mathematics, sect. 45-48. AlsoSiris, sect. 323, 335, &c., where he distinguishes Idea in a higher meaning from his sensuous ideas. As mentioned in my Preface, the third edition ofAlciphron, published in 1752, the year before Berkeley died, omits the three sections of the Seventh Dialogue which repeat the following argument against abstract ideas.483.As in Derodon'sLogica, Pt. II. c. 6, 7;Philosophia Contracta, I. i. §§ 7-11; and Gassendi,Leg. Instit., I. 8; also Cudworth,Eternal and Immutable Morality, Bk. IV.484.Omitted in second edition.485.We must remember that what Berkeley intends by anideais either a percept of sense, or a sensuous imagination; and his argument is that none ofthesecan be an abstraction. We can neither perceive nor imagine what is not concrete and part of a succession.486.“abstract notions”—here used convertibly with“abstract ideas.”Cf.Principles, sect. 89 and 142, on the special meaning ofnotion.487.Supposed by Berkeley to mean, that we can imagine, in abstraction from all phenomena presented in concrete experience, e.g. imagineexistence, in abstraction from all phenomena in which it manifests itself to us; ormatter, stripped of all the phenomena in which it is realised in sense.488.Omitted in second edition.489.Locke.490.Descartes, who regarded brutes as (sentient?) machines.491.“To this I cannot assent, being of opinion that a word,”&c.—in first edition.492.“an idea,”i.e. a concrete mental picture.493.So that“generality”in an idea is our“consideration”of a particular idea (e.g. a“particular motion”or a“particular extension”) notper se, but under general relations, which that particular idea exemplifies, and which, as he shews, may be signified by a corresponding word. All ideas (in Berkeley's confined meaning of“idea”) are particular. We rise above particular ideas by an intellectual apprehension of their relations; not by formingabstract pictures, which are contradictory absurdities.494.Locke is surely misconceived. He does not say, as Berkeley seems to suppose, that in forming“abstract ideas,”we are forming abstract mental images—pictures in the mind that are not individual pictures.495.Does Locke intend more than this, although he expresses his meaning in ambiguous words?496.It is a particular idea, but considered relatively—asignificantparticular idea, in other words. We realise our notions in examples, and these must be concrete.497.i.e.“ideas”in Locke's meaning of idea, under which he comprehends, not only the particular ideas of sense and imagination—Berkeley's“ideas”—but these considered relatively, and so seen intellectually, when Locke calls them abstract, general, or universal. Omniscience in its all-comprehensive intuition may not require, or even admit, such general ideas.498.Here and in what follows,“abstractnotion,”“universalnotion,”instead of abstractidea. Notion seems to be here a synonym for idea, and not taken in the special meaning which he afterwards attached to the term, when he contrasted it with idea.499.“notions,”again synonymous with ideas, which are all particular or concrete, in his meaning ofidea, when he uses it strictly.500.idea, i.e. individual mental picture.501.In all this he takes no account of the intellectual relations necessarily embodied in concrete knowledge, and without which experience could not cohere.502.“have in view,”i.e. actually realise in imagination.503.What follows, to the end of this section, was added in the second or 1734 edition.504.So Bacon in many passages of hisDe Augmentis ScientiariumandNovum Organum.505.“wide influence,”—“wide and extended sway”—in first edition.506.“idea,”i.e. individual datum of sense or of imagination.507.See Leibniz on Symbolical Knowledge (Opera Philosophica, pp. 79, 80, Erdmann), and Stewart in hisElements, vol. I. ch. 4, § 1, on our habit of using language without realising, in individual examples or ideas, the meanings of the common terms used.508.“doth”—“does,”here and elsewhere in first edition.509.“ideas,”i.e. representations in imagination ofanyof the individual objects to which the names are applicable. The sound or sight of a verbal sign may do duty for the concrete idea in which the notion signified by the word might be exemplified.510.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.511.Elsewhere he mentions Aristotle as“certainly a great admirer and promoter of the doctrine of abstraction,”and quotes his statement that there is hardly anything so incomprehensible to men as notions of the utmost universality; for they are the most remote from sense.Metaph., Bk. I. ch. 2.512.Added in second edition.513.Omitted in second edition.514.Omitted in second edition.515.Omitted in second edition.516.“my own ideas,”i.e. the concrete phenomena which I can realise as perceptions of sense, or in imagination.517.He probably refers to Locke.518.According to Locke,“that which has most contributed to hinder the due tracing of our ideas, and finding out their relations, and agreements or disagreements one with another, has been, I suppose, the ill use of words. It is impossible that men should ever truly seek, or certainly discover, the agreement or disagreement of ideas themselves, whilst their thoughts flutter about, or stick only in sounds of doubtful and uncertain significations. Mathematicians, abstracting their thoughts from names, and accustoming themselves to set before their minds the ideas themselves that they would consider, and not sounds instead of them, have avoided thereby a great part of that perplexity, puddering, and confusion which has so much hindered men's progress in other parts of knowledge.”Essay, Bk. IV. ch. 3, § 30. See also Bk. III. ch. 10, 11.519.General names involve in their signification intellectual relations among ideas or phenomena; but the relations,per se, are unimaginable.520.The rough draft of the Introduction, prepared two years before the publication of thePrinciples(see Appendix, vol. III), should be compared with the published version. He there tells that“there was a time when, being bantered and abused by words,”he“did not in the least doubt”that he was“able to abstract his ideas”; adding that“after a strict survey of my abilities, I not only discovered my own deficiency on this point, but also cannot conceive it possible that such a power should be even in the most perfect and exalted understanding.”What he thus pronounces“impossible,”is asensuousperception or imagination of an intellectual relation, as to which most thinkers would agree with him. But in so arguing, he seems apt to discard the intellectual relations themselves that are necessarily embodied in experience.David Hume refers thus to Berkeley's doctrine about“abstract ideas”:—“A great philosopher has asserted that all general ideas are nothing but particular ones annexed to a certain term, which gives them a more extensive signification. I look upon this to be one of the greatest and most valuable discoveries that has been made of late years in the republic of letters.”(Treatise of H. N.Pt. I, sect. 7.)521.This resembles Locke's account of the ideas with which human knowledge is concerned. They are all originally presented to the senses, or got by reflexion upon the passions and acts of the mind; and the materials contributed in this external and internal experience are, with the help of memory and imagination, elaborated by the human understanding in ways innumerable, true and false. See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II, ch. 1, §§ 1-5; ch. 10, 11, 12.522.The ideas or phenomena of which we are percipient in our five senses make their appearance, not isolated, but in individual masses, constituting the things, that occupy their respective places in perceived ambient space. It is asqualitiesofthingsthat the ideas or phenomena of sense arise in human experience.523.This is an advance upon the language of theCommonplace Book, in which“mind”is spoken of as only a“congeries of perceptions.”Here it is something“entirely distinct”from ideas or perceptions, in which they exist and are perceived, and on which they ultimately depend. Spirit, intelligent and active, presupposed with its implicates in ideas, thus becomes the basis of Berkeley's philosophy. Is this subjective idealism only? Locke appears in sect. 1, Descartes, if not Kant by anticipation, in sect. 2.524.This sentence expresses Berkeley's New Principle, which filled his thoughts in theCommonplace Book. Note“inamind,”not necessarily inmymind.525.That is to say, one has only to put concrete meaning into the termsexistenceandreality, in order to have“an intuitive knowledge”that matter depends for its real existence on percipient spirit.526.In other words, the things of sense become real, only in the concrete experience of living mind, which gives them the only reality we can conceive or have any sort of concern with. Extinguish Spirit and the material world necessarily ceases to be real.527.Thatesseispercipiis Berkeley's initial Principle, called“intuitive”or self-evident.528.Mark that it is the“natural or real existence”of the material world, in the absence of all realising Spirit, that Berkeley insists is impossible—meaningless.529.“our own”—yet not exclusivelymine. They depend for their reality uponapercipient, not onmyperception.530.“this tenet,”i.e. that the concrete material world could still be a reality after the annihilation of all realising spiritual life in the universe—divine or other.531.“existing unperceived,”i.e. existing without being realised in any living percipient experience—existing in a totally abstract existence, whatever that can mean.532.“notions”—a term elsewhere (see sect. 27, 89, 142) restricted, is here applied to the immediate data of the senses—the ideas of sense.533.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.534.In the first edition, instead of this sentence, we have the following:“To make this appear with all the light and evidence of an Axiom, it seems sufficient if I can but awaken the reflexion of the reader, that he may take an impartial view of his own meaning, and turn his thoughts upon the subject itself; free and disengaged from all embarras of words and prepossession in favour of received mistakes.”535.In other words, active percipient Spirit is at the root of all intelligible trustworthy experience.536.'proof'—“demonstration”in first edition; yet he calls it“intuitive.”537.“the ideas themselves,”i.e. the phenomena immediately presented in sense, and that are thus realised in and through the percipient experience of living mind, as their factor.538.As those say who assume that perception is ultimately only representative of the material reality, the very things themselves not making their appearance to us at all.539.He refers especially to Locke, whose account of Matter is accordingly charged with being incoherent.540.“inert.”See theDe Motu.541.“ideas existing in the mind,”i.e. phenomena of whichsomemind is percipient; which are realised in the sentient experience of a living spirit, human or other.542.What follows to the end of the section is omitted in the second edition.543.“the existence of Matter,”i.e. the existence of the material world, regarded as a something that does not need to be perceived in order to be real.544.Sometimes calledobjectivequalities, because they are supposed to be realised in an abstract objectivity, which Berkeley insists is meaningless.545.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II, ch. 8, §§ 13, 18; ch. 23, § 11; Bk. IV, ch. 3, § 24-26. Locke suggests this relation between the secondary and the primary qualities of matter only hypothetically.546.“in the mind, and nowhere else,”i.e. perceived or conceived, but in no other manner can they be real or concrete.547.“without the mind,”i.e. independently of all percipient experience.548.Extension is thus the distinguishing characteristic of the material world. Geometrical and physical solidity, as well as motion, imply extension.549.“number is the creature of the mind,”i.e. is dependent on being realised in percipient experience. This dependence is here illustrated by the relation of concrete number to the point of view of each mind; as the dependence of the other primary qualities was illustrated by their dependence on the organisation of the percipient. In this, the preceding, and the following sections, Berkeley argues the inconsistency of the abstract reality attributed to the primary qualities with their acknowledged dependence on the necessary conditions of sense perception.550.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 109.551.e.g. Locke,Essay, Bk. II, ch. 7, § 7; ch. 16, § 1.552.“without any alteration in any external object”—“without any external alteration”—in first edition.553.These arguments, founded on the mind-dependent nature ofallthe qualities of matter, are expanded in theFirst Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.554.“an outward object,”i.e. an object wholly abstract from living Mind.555.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.556.“reason,”i.e. reasoning. It is argued, in this and the next section, that a reality unrealised in percipient experience cannot be proved, either by our senses or by reasoning.557.Omitted in the second edition, and the sentence converted into a question.558.But the ideas of which we are cognizant in waking dreams, and dreams of sleep, differ in important characteristics from the external ideas of which we are percipient in sense. Cf. sect. 29-33.559.“external bodies,”i.e. bodies supposed to be real independently of all percipients in the universe.560.i.e. they cannot shew how their unintelligible hypothesis of Matter accounts for the experience we have, or expect to have; or which we believe other persons have, or to be about to have.561.“the production,”&c., i.e. the fact that we and others have percipient experience.562.Mind-dependent Matter he not only allows to exist, but maintains its reality to be intuitively evident.563.i.e. bodies existing in abstraction from living percipient spirit.564.“Matter,”i.e. abstract Matter, unrealised in sentient intelligence.565.The appeal here and elsewhere is to consciousness—directly in each person's experience, and indirectly in that of others.566.i.e. otherwise than in the form of an idea or actual appearance presented to our senses.567.This implies that the material world may be realised in imagination as well as in sensuous perception, but in a less degree of reality; for reality, he assumes, admits of degrees.568.“to conceive the existence of external bodies,”i.e. to conceive bodies that are not conceived—that are not ideas at all, but which exist in abstraction. To suppose what we conceive to be unconceived, is to suppose a contradiction.569.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.570.“The existence of things without mind,”or in the absence of all spiritual life and perception, is what Berkeley argues against, asmeaningless, if notcontradictory; not the existence of a material world, when this means the realised order of nature, regulated independently of individual will, and to which our actions must conform if we are to avoid physical pain.571.Here againnotionis undistinguished fromidea.572.This and the three following sections argue for the essential impotence of matter, and that, as far as we are concerned, so-called“natural causes”are onlysignswhich foretell the appearance of their so-called effects. The material world is presented to our senses as a procession of orderly, and therefore interpretable, yet in themselves powerless, ideas or phenomena: motion is always an effect, never an originating active cause.573.As Locke suggests.574.This tacitly presupposes the necessity in reason of the Principle of Causality, or the ultimate need for an efficient cause of every change. To determine the sort of Causation that constitutes and pervades the universe is the aim of his philosophy.575.In other words, the material world is not only real in and through percipient spirit, but the changing forms which its phenomena assume, in the natural evolution, are the issue of the perpetual activity of in-dwelling Spirit. The argument in this section requires a deeper criticism of its premisses.576.In other words, an agent cannot, as such, be perceived or imagined, though its effects can. The spiritual termagentis not meaningless; yet we have nosensuous ideaof its meaning.577.Omitted in second edition.578.This sentence is not contained in the first edition. It is remarkable for first introducing the termnotion, to signifyidealess meaning, as in the words soul, active power, &c. Here he says that“the operations of the mind”belong to notions, while, in sect. 1, he speaks of“ideasperceived by attending to the‘operations’of the mind.”579.“ideas,”i.e. fancies of imagination; as distinguished from the more real ideas or phenomena that present themselves objectively to our senses.580.With Berkeley the world of external ideas is distinguished from Spirit by its essential passivity. Active power is with him the essence of Mind, distinguishing me from the changing ideas of which I am percipient. We must not attribute free agency to phenomena presented to our senses.581.In this and the four following sections, Berkeley mentionsmarksby which the ideas or phenomena that present themselves to the senses may be distinguished from all other ideas, in consequence of which they may be termed“external,”while those of feeling and imagination are wholly subjective or individual.582.This mark—the superior strength and liveliness of the ideas or phenomena that are presented to the senses—was afterwards noted by Hume. SeeInquiry concerning Human Understanding, sect. II.583.Berkeley here and always insists on thearbitrarycharacter of“settled laws”of change in the world, as contrasted with“necessary connexions”discovered in mathematics. The material world is thus virtually an interpretable natural language, constituted in what, at our point of view, isarbitrarinessorcontingency.584.Under this conception of the universe,“second causes”aredivinely established signsof impending changes, and are only metaphorically called“causes.”585.So Schiller, inDon Carlos, Act III, where he represents sceptics as failing to see the God who veils Himself in everlasting laws. But in truth God is eternal law or order vitalised and moralised.586.“sensations,”with Berkeley, are not mere feelings, but in a sense external appearances.587.“morereality.”This implies that reality admits of degrees, and that the difference between the phenomena presented to the senses and those which are only imagined is a difference in degree of reality.588.In the preceding sections, two relations should be carefully distinguished—that of the material world to percipient mind, in which it becomesreal; and that between changes in the world and spiritual agency. These are Berkeley's two leading Principles. The first conducts to and vindicates the second—inadequately, however, apart from explication of their root in moral reason. The former gives a relationsui generis. The latter gives our only example of active causality—the natural order of phenomena being the outcome of the causal energy of intending Will.589.Sect. 34-84 contain Berkeley's answers to supposedobjectionsto the foregoing Principles concerning Matter and Spirit in their mutual relations.590.To be an“idea”is, with Berkeley, to be the imaginable object of a percipient spirit. But he does not define precisely the relation of ideas to mind.“Existence in mind”is existencein this relation. His question (which he determines in the negative) is, the possibility of concrete phenomena, naturally presented to sense,yet out of all relation to living mind.591.Omitted in second edition.592.i.e. of imagination. Cf. sect. 28-30.593.Cf. sect. 29.594.“more reality.”This again implies that reality admits of degrees. What is perceived in sense is more real than what is imagined, and eternal realities are more deeply real than the transitory things of sense.595.Cf. sect. 33.“Not fictions,”i.e. they are presentative, and therefore cannot misrepresent.596.With Berkeleysubstanceis either (a) active reason, i.e. spirit—substance proper, or (b) an aggregate of sense-phenomena, called a“sensible thing”—substance conventionally and superficially.597.And which, because realised in living perception, are calledideas—to remind us that reality is attained in and through percipient mind.598.“combined together,”i.e. in the form of“sensible things,”according to natural laws. Cf. sect. 33.599.“thinking things”—more appropriately calledpersons.600.Berkeley uses the word idea to mark the fact, that sensible things are real only as they manifest themselves in the form of passive objects, presented to sense-percipient mind; but he does not, as popularly supposed, regard“sensible things”as created and regulated by the activity of his own individual mind. They are perceived, but are neither created nor regulated, by the individual percipient, and are thuspractically externalto each person.601.Cf. sect. 87-91, against the scepticism which originates in alleged fallacy of sense.602.Omitted in second edition.603.It is always to be remembered that with Berkeley ideas or phenomena presented to sense arethemselvesthe real things, whilst ideas of imagination are representative (or misrepresentative).604.Here feelings of pleasure or pain are spoken of, without qualification, as in like relation to living mind as sensible things or ideas are.605.That the ideas of sense should be seen“at a distance of several miles”seems not inconsistent with their being dependent on a percipient, if ambient space isitself(as Berkeley asserts) dependent on percipient experience. Cf. sect. 67.606.In the preceding year.607.Essay, sect. 2.608.Ibid. sect. 11-15.609.Ibid. sect. 16-28.610.Ibid. sect. 51.611.Ibid. sect. 47-49, 121-141.612.Ibid. sect. 43.613.i.e. what we areimmediatelypercipient of in seeing.614.Touch is here and elsewhere taken in its wide meaning, and includes our muscular and locomotive experience, all which Berkeley included in the“tactual”meaning of distance.615.To explain the condition of sensible thingsduring the intervals of our perception of them, consistently with the belief of all sane persons regarding the material world, is a challenge which has been often addressed to the advocates of ideal Realism. According to Berkeley, there are no intervals in the existence of sensible things. They are permanently perceivable, under the laws of nature, though not always perceived by this, that or the other individual percipient. Moreover they always existreallyin the Divine Idea, andpotentially, in relation to finite minds, in the Divine Will.616.Berkeley allows to bodies unperceived by me potential, but (for me) not real existence. When I say a body exists thus conditionally, I mean that if, in the light, I open my eyes, I shall see it, and that if I move my hand, I must feel it.617.i.e. unperceived material substance.618.Berkeley remarks, in a letter to the American Samuel Johnson, that“those who have contended for a material world have yet acknowledged thatnatura naturans(to use the language of the Schoolmen) is God; and that the Divine conservation of things is equipollent to, and in fact the same thing with, a continued repeated creation;—in a word, that conservation and creation differ only as theterminus a quo. These are the common opinions of Schoolmen; and Durandus, who held the world to be a machine, like a clock made up and put in motion by God, but afterwards continued to go of itself, was therein particular, and had few followers. The very poets teach a doctrine not unlike the Schools—mens agitat molem(Virgil, Æneid, VI). The Stoics and Platonists are everywhere full of the same notion. I am not therefore singular in this point itself, so much as in my way of proving it.”Cf.Alciphron, Dial. IV. sect. 14;Vindication of New Theory of Vision, sect. 8, 17, &c.;Siris,passim, but especially in the latter part. See alsoCorrespondence between Clarke and Leibniz(1717). Is it not possible that the universe of things and persons is in continuous natural creation, unbeginning and unending?619.Cf. sect. 123-132.620.He distinguishes“idea”from“mode or attribute.”With Berkeley, the“substance”ofmatter(if the term is still to be applied to sensible things) is the naturally constituted aggregate of phenomena of which each particular thing consists. Now extension, and the other qualities of sensible things, are not, Berkeley argues,“in mind”either (a) according to the abstract relation of substance and attribute of which philosophers speak; nor (b) as one idea or phenomenon is related to another idea or phenomenon, in the natural aggregation of sense-phenomena which constitute, with him, thesubstanceof amaterialthing. Mind and its“ideas”are, on the contrary, related as percipient to perceived—in whatever“otherness”that altogethersui generisrelation implies.621.“Matter,”i.e. abstract material Substance, as distinguished from the concrete things that are realised in living perceptions.622.“take away natural causes,”i.e. empty the material world of all originative power, and refer the supposed powers of bodies to the constant and omnipresent agency of God.623.Some philosophers have treated the relation of Matter to Mind inperceptionas one of cause and effect. This, according to Berkeley, is an illegitimate analysis, which creates a fictitious duality. On his New Principles, philosophy is based on a recognition of the fact, that perception is neither the cause nor the effect of its object, but in a relation to it that is altogethersui generis.624.He refers to Descartes, and perhaps Geulinx and Malebranche, who, while they argued for materialsubstance, denied thecausal efficiencyof sensible things. Berkeley's new Principles are presented as the foundation in reason for this denial, and for the essential spirituality of all active power in the universe.625.On the principle,“Entia non sunt multiplicanda præter necessitatem.”626.“external things,”i.e. things in the abstract.627.That the unreflecting part of mankind should have a confused conception of what should be meant by theexternal realityof matter is not wonderful. It is the office of philosophy to improve their conception, making it deeper and truer, and this was Berkeley's preliminary task; as a mean for shewing the impotence of the things of sense, and conclusive evidence of omnipresent spiritual activity.628.Cf. sect. 4, 9, 15, 17, 22, 24.629.i.e. theirsense-ideas.—Though sense-ideas, i.e. the appearances presented to the senses, are independent of thewillof the individual percipient, it does not follow that they are independent ofall perception, so that they can be real in the absence of realising percipient experience. Cf. sect. 29-33.630.By shewing that what we are percipient of in sense must beidea, or that it is immediately known by us only as sensuous appearance.631.i.e.“imprinted”by unperceived Matter, which, on this dogma of a representative sense-perception, was assumed to exist behind the perceived ideas, and to be thecauseof their appearance. Cf.Third Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.632.Hence the difficulty men have in recognising that Divine Reason and Will, and Law in Nature, are coincident. But the advance of scientific discovery of the laws which express Divine Will in nature, instead of narrowing, extends our knowledge of God. Anddivineorabsolutely reasonable“arbitrariness”is not caprice.633.“ideas,”i.e. ideas ofsense. This“experience”implied an association of sensuous ideas, according to the divine or reasonable order of nature.634.Cf. sect. 25-33, and other passages in Berkeley's writings in which he insists upon thearbitrariness—divine or reasonable—of the natural laws and sense-symbolism.635.Cf. sect. 3, 4, 6, 22-24, 26, in which he proceeds upon the intuitive certainty of his two leading Principles, concerningRealityandCausation.636.In short, what is virtually the language of universal natural order is the divine way of revealing omnipresent Intelligence; nor can we conceive how this revelation could be made through a capricious or chaotic succession of changes.637.He here touches on moral purpose in miraculous phenomena, but without discussing their relation to the divine, or perfectly reasonable, order of the universe. Relatively to a fine knowledge of nature, they seem anomalous—exceptions from general rules, which nevertheless express, immediately and constantly, perfect active Reason.638.“ideas,”i.e. the phenomena presented to the senses.639.“imaginable”—in first edition.640.“the connexion of ideas,”i.e. the presence of law or reasonable uniformity in the coexistence and succession of the phenomena of sense; which makes them interpretable signs.641.According to Berkeley, it is by an abuse of language that the term“power”is applied to those ideas which are invariable antecedents of other ideas—the prior forms of their existence, as it were.642.Berkeley, in meeting this objection, thus implies Universal Natural Symbolism as the essential character of the sensible world, in its relation to man.643.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. IV, ch. 3, § 25-28, &c., in which he suggests that the secondary qualities of bodies may be the natural issue of the different relations and modifications of their primary qualities.644.With Berkeley,material substanceis merely the natural combination of sense-presented phenomena, which, under adivineorreasonable“arbitrariness,”constitute a concrete thing. Divine Will, or Active Reason, is the constantly sustaining cause of this combination or substantiation.645.i.e. that it is not realised in a living percipient experience.646.For“place”is realised only as perceived—percipient experience being its concrete existence. Living perception is, with Berkeley, the condition of the possibility of concrete locality.647.So in the Cartesian theory of occasional causes.648.So Geulinx and Malebranche.649.As known in Divine intelligence, they are accordinglyDivine Ideas. And, if this means that the sensible system is the expression of Divine Ideas, which are its ultimate archetype—that the Ideas of God are symbolised to our senses, and then interpreted (or misinterpreted) by human minds, this allies itself with Platonic Idealism.650.“It seems to me,”Hume says,“that this theory of the universal energy and operation of the Supreme Being istoo boldever to carry conviction with it to a mind sufficiently apprised of the weakness of human reason, and the narrow limits to which it is confined in all its operations.”But is it not virtually presupposed in the assumed trustworthiness of our experience of the universe?651.Accordingly we are led to ask, what the deepest support of their reality must be. Is it found in living Spirit, i.e. Active Reason, or in blind Matter?652.e.g. Descartes, Malebranche, Locke, &c.653.In short, if we mean by Matter, something unrealised in percipient experience of sense, what is called itsrealityis something unintelligible.654.And if sensible phenomena aresufficientlyexternalised, when regarded as regulated by Divine Reason.655.Twenty years after the publication of thePrinciples, in a letter to his American friend Johnson, Berkeley says:—“I have no objection against calling the Ideas in the mind of Godarchetypesof ours. But I object against those archetypes by philosophers supposed to be real things, and so to have an absolute rational existence distinct from their being perceived by any mind whatsoever; it being the opinion of all materialists that an ideal existence in the Divine Mind is one thing, and the real existence of material things another.”656.Berkeley's philosophy is not inconsistent with Divine Ideas which receive expression in the laws of nature, and of which human science is the imperfect interpretation. In this view, assertion of the existence of Matter is simply an expression of faith that the phenomenal universe into which we are born is a reasonable and interpretable universe; and that it would be fully interpreted, if our notions could be fully harmonised with the Divine Ideas which it expresses.657.Cf. sect. 3-24.658.So that superhuman persons, endowed with a million senses, would be no nearer this abstract Matter than man is, with his few senses.659.Matter and physical science isrelative, so far that we may suppose in other percipients than men, an indefinite number of additional senses, affording corresponding varieties of qualities in things, of course inconceivable by man. Or, we may suppose an intelligence destitute ofall oursenses, and so in a material world wholly different in its appearances from ours.660.The authority of Holy Scripture, added to our natural tendency to believe in external reality, are grounds on which Malebranche and Norris infer a material world. Berkeley's material world claims no logical proof of its reality. His is not to prove the reality of the world, but to shew what we should mean when we affirm its reality, and the basis of its explicability in science.661.i.e. existing unrealised in any intelligence—human or Divine.662.“external things,”i.e. things existing really, yet out of all relation to active living spirit.663.Simultaneous perception of the“same”(similar?)sense-ideas,by different persons, as distinguished from purely individual consciousness of feelings and fancies, is here taken as a test of thevirtually external realityof the former.Berkeley does not ask whether the change of the rod into a serpent, or of the water into wine, is the issue of divine agency and order, otherwise than as all natural evolution is divinely providential.664.Some of the Consequences of adoption of the New Principles, in their application to the physical sciences and mathematics, and then to psychology and theology, are unfolded in the remaining sections of thePrinciples.665.Berkeley disclaims the supposedrepresentativecharacter of the ideas given in sensuous perception, and recognises as the real object only what is ideally presented in consciousness.666.So Hume, Reid, and Hamilton, who all see in a wholly representative sense-perception, with its double object, the germ of total scepticism. Berkeley claims that, underhisinterpretation of what the reality of the material world means, immediate knowledge of mind-dependent matter is given in sense.667.“scepticism”—“sceptical cant”in the first edition.668.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.669.Berkeley's argument against afinally representativeperception so far resembles that afterwards employed by Reid and Hamilton. They differ as regards the dependence of the sensible object upon percipient spirit for its reality.670.Omitted in second edition.671.Omitted in second edition.672.But whilst unthinking things depend on being perceived, do not our spirits depend on ideas of some sort for their percipient life?673.The important passage within brackets was added in the second edition.674.“reason,”i.e. reasoning.675.“Notion,”in its stricter meaning, is thus confined by Berkeley to apprehension of theEgo, and intelligence ofrelations. The term“notion,”in this contrast withhis“idea,”becomes important in his vocabulary, although he sometimes uses it vaguely.676.Locke usesideain this wider signification.677.Inasmuch as they arerealin and through living percipient mind.678.i.e.unthinkingarchetypes.679.In this section Berkeley explains what he means byexternality. Men cannot act, cannot live, without assuming an external world—in some meaning of the term“external.”It is the business of the philosopher to explicate its true meaning.680.i.e. they are notsubstancesin the truest or deepest meaning of the word.681.“Ideas of the corporeal substances.”Berkeley might perhaps say—Divine Ideas which arethemselvesour world of sensible things in its ultimate form.682.On the scheme of ideal Realism,“creation”of matter is presenting to finite minds sense-ideas or phenomena, which are, as it were, letters of the alphabet, in that language of natural order which God employs for the expression ofHisIdeas to us.683.Theindependenteternity of Matter must be distinguished from an unbeginning and endlesscreationof sensible ideas or phenomena, in percipient spirits, according to divine natural law and order, with implied immanence of God.684.Because the question at issue with Atheism is, whether the universe of things and persons is finally substantiated and evolved in unthinking Matter or in the perfect Reason of God.685.Of which Berkeley doesnotpredicate anumericalidentity. Cf.Third Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.686.“matter,”i.e. matter abstracted from all percipient life and voluntary activity.687.“external”—not in Berkeley's meaning of externality. Cf. sect. 90, note 2.688.Si non rogas, intelligo.Berkeley writes long after this to Johnson thus:—“A succession of ideas (phenomena) I take toconstitutetime, and not to be only the sensible measure thereof, as Mr. Locke and others think. But in these matters every man is to think for himself, and speak as he finds. One of my earliest inquiries was abouttime; which led me into several paradoxes that I did not think it fit or necessary to publish, particularly into the notion that the resurrection follows the next moment after death. We are confounded and perplexed about time—supposing a succession in God; that we have an abstract idea of time; that time in one mind is to be measured by succession of ideas in another mind: not considering the true use of words, which as often terminate in the will as in the understanding, being employed to excite and direct action rather than to produce clear and distinct ideas.”Cf. Introduction, sect. 20.689.As theesseof unthinking things ispercipi, according to Berkeley, so theesseof persons ispercipere. The real existence of individual Mind thus depends on having ideas of some sort: the real existence of matter depends on a percipient.690.This sentence is omitted in the second edition.691.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 43.692.“objects of sense,”i.e. sensible things, practically external to each person. Cf. sect. 1, on the meaning ofthing, as distinct from the distinguishable ideas or phenomena that are naturally aggregated in the form of concrete things.693.Omitted in second edition.694.Omitted in second edition.695.Cf. Introduction, sect. 1-3. With Berkeley, the real essence of sensible things is given in perception—so far as our perceptions carry us.696.e.g. Locke'sEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 3.697.Berkeley advocates a Realism, which eliminates effective causation from the material world, concentrates it in Mind, and in physical research seeks among data of sense for their divinely maintained natural laws.698.In interpreting the data of sense, we are obliged to assume that everynewphenomenon must have previously existed in some equivalent form—but not necessarily in this or that particular form, for a knowledge of which we are indebted to inductive comparisons of experience.699.The preceding forms of new phenomena, being finally determined by Will, are, in that sense, arbitrary; but not capricious, for the Will is perfect Reason. God is the immanent cause of the natural order.700.He probably refers to Bacon.701.Omitted in second edition.702.What we are able to discover in the all-comprehensive order may be subordinate and provisional only. Nature in its deepest meaning explains itself in the Divine Omniscience.703.i.e. inductively.704.i.e. deductively.705.“seem to consider signs,”i.e. to be grammarians rather than philosophers: physical sciences deal with the grammar of the divine language of nature.706.“A man may be well read in the language of nature without understanding the grammar of it, or being able to say,”&c.—in first edition.707.“extend”—“stretch”—in first edition.708.Omitted in second edition.709.In the first edition, the section commences thus:“The best grammar of the kind we are speaking of will be easily acknowledged to be a treatise ofMechanics, demonstrated and applied to Nature, by a philosopher of a neighbouring nation, whom all the world admire. I shall not take upon me to make remarks on the performance of that extraordinary person: only some things he has advanced so directly opposite to the doctrine we have hitherto laid down, that we should be wanting in the regard due to the authority of so great a man did we not take some notice of them.”He refers, of course, to Newton. The first edition of Berkeley'sPrincipleswas published in Ireland—hence“neighbouring nation.”Newton'sPrincipiaappeared in 1687.710.“Motion,”in various aspects, is treated specially in theDe Motu. An imagination of trinal space presupposes locomotive experience—unimpeded, in contrast with—impeded locomotion. Cf. sect. 116.711.Omitted in second edition.712.Added in second edition.713.Omitted in second edition.714.See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 13, §§ 7-10.715.“applied to”—“impressed on”—in first edition.716.“applied to”—“impressed on”—in first edition.717.“theforcecausing the change”—which“force,”according to Berkeley, can only be attributed metaphorically to the so-called impelling body; inasmuch asbodies, or the data of sense, can only be signs of their consequent events, not efficient causes of change.718.Added in second edition.719.What follows to the end of this section is omitted in the second edition.720.“seems impossible”—“is above my capacity”—in first edition.721.In short, empty Spaceisthe sensuous idea of unresisted motion. This is implied in theNew Theory of Vision. He minimises Space, treating it as a datum of sense.722.He probably refers to Samuel Clarke'sDemonstration of the Being and Attributes of God, which appeared in 1706, and a treatiseDe Spatio Reali, published in the same year.723.Sect. 118-132 are accordingly concerned with the New Principles in their application to Mathematics. The foundation of the mathematical sciences engaged much of Berkeley's thought in early life and in his later years. See hisAnalyst.724.Numerical relations arerealisedonly in concrete experience.725.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 107, &c.726.Ibid. sect. 122-125, 149-160.727.An infinitely divided extension, being unperceived, must be unreal—if its existence is made real only in and through actual perception, or at least imagination. The only possible extension is, accordingly, sensible extension, which could not be infinitely divided without the supposed parts ceasing to be perceived or real.728.“converted Gentile”—“pagan convert”—in first edition.729.Cf. Locke'sEssay, Bk. I, ch. 3, § 25.730.“will perhaps in virtue thereof be brought to admit,”&c.—“will not stick to affirm,”&c.—in first edition.731.Omitted in second edition. See theAnalyst.732.“we must mean”—“we mean (if we mean anything)”—in first edition.733.Omitted in the second edition.734.Does this refer to the intended“Part II”of thePrinciples?735.“men of great abilities and obstinate application,”&c.—“men of the greatest abilities and most obstinate application,”&c.—in first edition.736.What follows to the end of this section is omitted in the second edition.737.“absolute,”i.e. abstract, independent, irrelative existence—as something of which there can be no sensuous perception or conception.738.Matter unrealised in perception—not the material world that is realised in percipient experience of sense.739.Omitted in second edition.740.Sect. 135-156 treat of consequences of the New Principles, in their application to sciences concerned with our notions ofSpiritorMind; as distinguished from sciences of ideas in external Nature, and their mathematical relations. Individual mind, with Berkeley, needs data of sense in order to its realisation in consciousness; while it is dependent on God, in a relation which he does not define distinctly.741.e.g. Locke suggests this.742.Is this analogy applicable?743.Omitted in second edition, as he had previously learned to distinguishnotionfromidea. Cf. sect. 89, 142.744.Ibid. In the omitted passage it will be seen that he makesideaandnotionsynonymous.745.Is the reality of mind as dependent on having ideas (of some sort) as ideas are on mind; although mind is more deeply and truly real than its ideas are?746.Introduced in second edition.747.We knowother finite personsthrough sense-presented phenomena, but not as themselves phenomena. Cf. sect. 145. It is a mediate knowledge that we have of other persons. The question about the individuality of finite egos, as distinguished from God, Berkeley has not touched.748.These sentences are omitted in the second edition.749.“the soul,”i.e. the individual Ego.750.Cf. sect. 2; 25-27.751.This is Berkeley's application of his new conception of the reality of matter, to the final human question of the self-conscious existence of the individual human Ego, after physical death. Philosophers and theologians were accustomed in his generation to ground their argument for a future life on the metaphysical assumption of the physical indivisibility of our self-conscious spirit, and on our contingent connexion with the body.“Our bodies,”says Bishop Butler,“are no moreourselves, orpart of ourselves, than any other matter around us.”This train of thought is foreign to us at the present day, when men of science remind us that self-conscious life is found only in correlation with corporeal organisation, whatever may be the abstract possibility. Hope of continued life after physical death seems to depend on ethical considerations more than on metaphysical arguments, and on what is suggested by faith in the final outcome of personal life in adivinelyconstituted universe.752.Mind and the ideas presented to the senses are at opposite poles of existence. But he does not say that, thus opposed, they are each independent of the other.753.What follows was introduced in the second edition, in whichnotionis contrasted withidea.754.Here is a germ of Kantism. But Berkeley has not analysed that activity of mind which constitutesrelation, nor systematically unfolded the relations involved in the rational constitution of experience. There is more disposition to this inSiris.755.As with Locke, for example.756.Note this condemnation of the tendency to substantiate“powers of mind.”757.Omitted in second edition. Berkeley was after all reluctant to“depart from received modes of speech,”notwithstanding their often misleading associations.758.Omitted in second edition.759.This is one of the notable sections in thePrinciples, as it suggests therationaleof Berkeley's rejection of Panegoism or Solipsism. Is this consistent with his conception of the reality of the material world? It is objected (e.g. by Reid) that ideal realism dissolves our faith in the existence of other persons. The difficulty is to shew how appearances presented to my senses, which are sensuous and subjective, can be media of communication between persons. The question carries us back to the theistic presupposition in the trustworthiness of experience—which is adapted to deceive if I am the only person existing. With Berkeley a chief function of ideas of sense is to signify other persons to each person. SeeAlciphron, Dial. IV;New Theory of Vision Vindicated, andSiris.760.“repugnant”—for it would involve thought in incoherence, by paralysis of its indispensable causal presupposition.761.Is not God the indispensable presupposition of trustworthy experience, rather than an empirical inference?762.This suggests an explanation of the objective reality and significance ofideas of sense; through which they become media of social intercourse in the fundamentally divine universe. God so regulates the sense-given ideas of which human beings are individually percipient, as that,while numerically different, as in each mind, those ideas are nevertheless a sufficient medium for social intercourse, if the Power universally at work is morally trustworthy. Unless our God-given experience is deceiving, Solipsism is not a necessary result of the fact that no one but myself can be percipient of my sensuous experience.763.Omitted in second edition.764.Malebranche, as understood by Berkeley. SeeRecherche, Liv. III. p. ii. ch. 6, &c.765.For all finite personssomehowlive, and move, and have their being“in God.”The existence ofeternalliving Mind, and thepresentexistence of other men, are bothinferences, resting on the same foundation, according to Berkeley.766.The theistic trust in which our experience is rooted remaining latent, or being unintelligent.767.Cf. sect. 25-28, 51-53, 60-66. His conception of Divine causation in Nature, as the constant omnipresent agency in all natural law, is the deepest part of his philosophy. It is pursued in theDe Motu.768.Is not the unbeginning and unending natural evolution, an articulate revelation of Eternal Spirit or Active Reason at the heart of the whole?769.Omitted in second edition.770.So Pascal in thePensées.771.Divine reason ever active in Nature is the necessary correlate to reason in man; inasmuch as otherwise the changing universe in which we live would be unfit to be reasoned about or acted in.772.The existence ofmoralevil, or what ought not to exist, isthedifficulty which besets faith in the fundamental divinity or goodness of the universe. Yet that faith is presupposed in interpretation of nature, which proceeds on thepostulateof universal order; and this implies the moral trustworthiness of the world which we begin to realise when we begin to be conscious. That we are living and having our being in omnipotent goodness is thus not an inference, but the implied basis of all real inferences. I have expanded this thought in myPhilosophy of Theism. We cannotproveGod, for we must assume God, as the basis of all proof. Faith even in the uniformity of nature is virtually faith in omnipotent goodness immanent in the universe.773.So Leibniz in hisTheodicée, which was published in the same year as Berkeley'sPrinciples.774.The divine presupposition, latent in all human reasoning and experience, is hid from the unreflecting, in whom the higher life is dormant, and the ideal in the universe is accordingly undiscerned. Unless the universe is assumed to be physically and morally trustworthy, i.e. unless God is presupposed, even natural science has no adequate foundation.775.Our necessarily incomplete knowledge of the Universe in which we find ourselves is apt to disturb the fundamental faith, that the phenomena presented to us are significant of God. Yet wetacitly assumethat they are thus significant when we interpret real experience, physical or moral.776.Omitted in second edition.777.For the following extracts from previously unpublished correspondence of Berkeley and Sir John Percival, I am indebted to the kindness of his descendant, the late Lord Egmont.778.What Berkeley seeks to shew is, not that the world of the senses is unreal, but in what its reality consists. Is it inexplicable chaos, or explicable expression of ever active Intelligence, more or less interpreted in natural science?779.Leibniz:De modo distinguendi Phenomena Realia ab Imaginariis(1707).780.For some information relative to Gua de Malves, see Querard'sLa France Littéraire,tom. iii. p. 494.781.The following is the translator's Prefatory Note, on the objects of theDialogues,and in explanation of the three illustrative vignettes:—“L'Auteur expose dans le premier Dialogue le sentiment du Vulgaire et celui des Philosophes, sur les qualités secondaires et premieres, la nature et l'existence des corps; et il prétend prouver en même tems l'insuffisance de l'un et de l'autre. La Vignette qu'on voit à la téte du Dialogue, fait allusion à cet objet. Elle représente un Philosophe dans son cabinet, lequel est distrait de son travail par un enfant qu'il appercoit se voyant lui-méme dans un miroir, en tendant les mains pour embrasser sa propre image. Le Philosophe rit de l'erreur où il croit que tombe l'enfant; tandis qu'on lui applique à lui-même ces mots tirés d'Horace:Quid rides?....de teFabula narratur.“Le second Dialogue est employé à exposer le sentiment de l'Auteur sur le même sujet, sçavoir, que les choses corporelles ont une existence réelle dans les esprits qui les apperçoivent; mais qu'elles ne sçauroient exister hors de tous les esprits à la fois, même de l'esprit infini de Dieu; et que par conséquent la Matière, prise suivant l'acception ordinaire du mot, non seulement n'existe point, mais seroit même absolument impossible. On a taché de représenter aux yeux ce sentiment dans la Vignette du Dialogue. Le mot grec νοῦς qui signifieâme, désigne l'àme: les rayons qui en partent marquent l'attention que l'âme donne à des idées ou objets; les tableaux qu'on a placés aux seuls endroits où les rayons aboutissent, et dont les sujets sont tirés de la description des beautés de la nature, qui se trouve dans le livre, représentent les idées ou objets que l'âme considère, pas le secours des facultes qu'elle a reçues de Dieu; et l'action de l'Étre suprème sur l'âme est figurée par un trait, qui, partant d'un triangle, symbole de la Divinité, et perçant les nuages dont le triangle est environné. s'étend jusqu'à l'âme pour la vivifier; enfin, on a fait en sorte de rendre le même sentiment par ces mots:Quæ noscere cumque Deus det,Esse puta.“L'objet du troisième Dialogue est de répondre aux difficultés auxquelles le sentiment qu'on a établi dans les Dialogues précédens, peut être sujet, de l'éclaircir en cette sorte de plus, d'en développer toutes les heureuses conséquences, enfin de faire voir, qu'étant bien entendu, il revient aux notions les plus communes. Et comme l'Auteur exprime à la fin du livre cette dernière pensée, en comparant ce qu'il vient de dire, à l'eau que les deux Interlocuteurs sont supposés voir jaillir d'un jet, et qu'il remarque que la même force de la gravité fait élever jusqu'à une certaine hauteur et retomber ensuite dans le bassin d'où elle étoit d'abord partie; on a pris cet emblême pour le sujet de la Vignette de ce Dialogue; on a représenté en conséquence dans cette dernière Vignette les deux Interlocuteurs, se promenant dans le lieu où l'Auteur les suppose, et s'entretenant là-dessus, et pour donner au Lecteur l'explication de l'emblême, on a mis au bas le vers suivant:Urget aquas vis sursum, eadem flectitque deorsum.”782.Collier never came fairly in sight of the philosophical public of last century. He is referred to in Germany by Bilfinger, in hisDilucidationes Philosophicæ(1746), and also in theAda Eruditorum, Suppl. VI. 244, &c., and in England by Corry in hisReflections on Liberty and Necessity(1761), as well as in theRemarkson the Reflections, andAnswersto the Remarks, pp. 7, 8 (1763), where he is described as“a weak reasoner, and a very dull writer also.”Collier was dragged from his obscurity by Dr. Reid, in hisEssays on the Intellectual Powers, Essay II. ch. 10. He was a subject of correspondence between Sir James Mackintosh, then at Bombay, and Dr. Parr, and an object of curiosity to Dugald Stewart. A beautiful reprint of theClavis(of the original edition of which only seven copies were then known to exist) appeared in Edinburgh in 1836; and in the following year it was included in a collection ofMetaphysical Tracts by English Philosophers of the Eighteenth Century, prepared for the press by Dr. Parr.783.William, fourth Lord Berkeley of Stratton, born about 1663, succeeded his brother in 1697, and died in 1741 at Bruton in Somersetshire. The Berkeleys of Stratton were descended from a younger son of Maurice, Lord Berkeley of Berkeley Castle, who died in 1326. His descendant, Sir John Berkeley of Bruton, a zealous Royalist, was created first Lord Berkeley of Stratton in 1658, and in 1669 became Lord Lieutenant of Ireland, an office which he held till 1672, when he was succeeded by the Earl of Essex (see Burke'sExtinct Peerages). It is said that Bishop Berkeley's father was related to him. The Bishop himself was introduced by Dean Swift, in 1713, to the Lord Berkeley of Stratton, to whom theDialoguesare dedicated, as“a cousin of his Lordship.”The title of Berkeley of Stratton became extinct on the death of the fifth Lord in 1773.784.This interesting Preface is omitted in his last edition of theDialogues.785.The Second Part of thePrincipleswas never published, and only in part written. See Editor's Preface to thePrinciples.786.Principles, Introduction, sect. 1.787.Berkeley's philosophy is professedly a“revolt”from abstract ideas to an enlightened sense of concrete realities. In these DialoguesPhilonouspersonates the revolt, and represents Berkeley.Hylasvindicates the uncritical conception of independent Matter.788.Berkeley's zeal against Matter in the abstract, and all abstract ideas of concrete things, is therefore not necessarily directed against“universal intellectual notions”—“the principles and theorems of sciences.”789.Here“reason”means reasoning or inference. Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 42, including the distinction between“suggestion”and“inference.”790.“figure”as well as colour, is here included among the original data of sight.791.“without the mind,”i.e. unrealised by any percipient mind.792.Cf.Principles, sect. 14.793.Cf.Principles, sect. 14, 15.794.“Sensible qualities,”i.e. the significant appearances presented in sense.795.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 80-86.796.Descartes and Locke for example.797.On Primary and Secondary Qualities of Matter, and their mutual relations, cf.Principles, sect. 9-15. See also Descartes,Meditations, III,Principia, I. sect. 69; Malebranche,Recherche, Liv. VI. Pt. II. sect. 2; Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 8.798.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 80.799.What follows, within brackets, is not contained in the first and second editions.800.Percipient mind is, in short, the indispensable realising factor ofallthe qualities of sensible things.801.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 122-126;Principles, sect. 123, &c.;Siris, sect. 270, &c.802.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 15.803.Is“notion”here a synonym for idea?804.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 16.805.“Size or figure, or sensible quality”—“size, color &c.,”in the first and second editions.806.In Berkeley's later and more exact terminology, the data or implicates of pure intellect are callednotions, in contrast to hisideas, which are concrete or individual sensuous presentations.807.They need living percipient mind to make them real.808.So Reid'sInquiry, ch. ii, sect. 8, 9;Essays on the Intellectual Powers, II. ch. 16. Cf.New Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 8, &c.809.i.e. figured or extended visible colour. Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 43, &c.810.Cf.Principles, sect. 25, 26.811.After maintaining, in the preceding part of this Dialogue, the inevitable dependence of all the qualities of Matter upon percipient Spirit, the argument now proceeds to dispose of the supposition that Matter may still be an unmanifested or unqualifiedsubstratum, independent of living percipient Spirit.812.[See theEssay towards a New Theory of Vision, and itsVindication.] Note by theAuthorin the 1734 edition.813.Cf.Essay on Vision, sect. 2.814.Cf. Ibid., sect. 43.815.“an idea,”i.e. a phenomenon present to our senses.816.This was Reid's fundamental question in his criticism of Berkeley.817.Cf.Principles, sect. 8.818.Cf.Principles, sect. 25, 26.819.In other words, the percipient activity of a living spirit is the necessary condition of the real existence of all ideas or phenomena immediately present to our senses.820.An“explanation”afterwards elaborately developed by Hartley, in hisObservations on Man(1749). Berkeley has probably Hobbes in view.821.The brain with the human body in which it is included constitutes a part of the material world, and must equally with the rest of the material world depend for its realisation upon percipient Spirit as the realising factor.822.Cf.Principles, sect. 23.823.“in stones and minerals”—in first and second editions.824.Cf.Principles, sect. 29-33; also sect. 90.—Thepermanenceof a thing, during intervals in which it may be unperceived and unimagined by human beings, is here assumed, as a natural conviction.825.In other words, men are apt to treat the omniscience of God as an inference from the dogmatic assumption that God exists, instead of seeing that our cosmic experience necessarily presupposes omnipotent and omniscient Intelligence at its root.826.Cf.Principles, sect. 90. A permanent material world is grounded on Divine Mind, because it cannot but depend on Mind, while its reality is only partially and at intervals sustained by finite minds.827.“necessarily inferred from”—rather necessarily presupposed in.828.The present reality of Something implies the eternal existence of living Mind, if Somethingmustexist eternally, and if real or concrete existence involves living Mind. Berkeley's conception of material nature presupposes a theistic basis.829.He refers of course to Malebranche and his Divine Vision.830.But Malebranche usesideain a higher meaning than Berkeley does—akin to the Platonic, and in contrast to the sensuous phenomena which Berkeley calls ideas.831.The passage within brackets first appeared in the third edition.832.Cf.Principles, sect. 25-33.833.Cf. Ibid., sect. 3-24.834.Icanrepresent to myself another mind perceiving and conceiving things; because I have an example of this my own conscious life. Icannotrepresent to myself sensible things existing totally unperceived and unimagined; because I cannot, without a contradiction, have an example of this in my own experience.835.“reason,”i.e. by reasoning.836.Berkeley'smaterial substanceis a natural or divinely ordered aggregate of sensible qualities or phenomena.837.Inasmuch as, according to Berkeley, it must be a living Spirit, and it would be an abuse of language to call this Matter.838.Cf.Principles, sect. 25, 26.839.It is here argued that asvolitionis the onlyoriginativecause implied in our experience, and which consequently alone puts true meaning into the term Cause, to apply that term to what is not volition is to make it meaningless, or at least to misapply it.840.While thus arguing against the need for independent matter, as an instrument needed by God, Berkeley fails to explain how dependent matter can be a medium of intercourse between persons. It must be more than a subjective dream, however well ordered, if it is available for this purpose. Unless the visible and audible ideas or phenomena presented to me are actually seen and heard by other men, how can they be instrumental in intercommunication?841.Cf.Principles, sect. 68-79.842.Cf.Principles, sect. 20.843.Cf.Principles, sect. 80, 81.844.i.e. all Spirits and their dependent ideas or phenomena.845.This, according to Hume (who takes for granted that Berkeley's reasonings can produce no conviction), is the natural effect of Berkeley's philosophy.—“Most of the writings of that very ingenious author (Berkeley) form the best lessons of scepticism which are to be found either among the ancient or modern philosophers, Bayle not excepted.... That all his arguments, though otherwise intended, are, in reality, merely sceptical, appear from this—that they admit of no answer, and produce no conviction. Their only effect is to cause that momentary amazement and irresolution and confusion, which is the result of scepticism.”(Hume'sEssays, vol. II. Note N, p. 554.)846.Omitted in last edition.847.“Tell me, Hylas,”—“So Hylas”—in first and second editions.848.Variously callednoumena,“things-in-themselves,”absolute substances, &c.—which Berkeley's philosophy banishes, on the ground of their unintelligibility, and thus annihilates all farther questions concerning them. Questions about existence are thus confined within the concrete or realising experiences of living spirits.849.Berkeley claims that his doctrine supersedes scepticism, and excludes the possibility of fallacy in sense, in excluding an ultimately representative perception of Matter. He also assumes the reasonableness of faith in the reality and constancy of natural law. When we see an orange, the visual sense guarantees only colour. The other phenomena, which we associate with this colour—the other“qualities”of the orange—are, when we onlyseethe orange, matter of faith. We believe them to be realisable.850.He accepts the common belief on which interpretation of sense symbols proceeds—that sensible phenomena are evolved in rational order, under laws that are independent of, and in that respect external to, the individual percipient.851.Mediately as well as immediately.852.We can hardly be said to have animmediatesense-perception of an individual“thing”—meaning by“thing”a congeries of sense-ideas or phenomena, presented to different senses. We immediately perceive some of them, and believe in the others, which those suggest. See the last three notes.853.He probably refers to Descartes, whoarguesfor the trustworthiness of our faculties from the veracity of God; thus apparently arguing in a circle, seeing that the existence of God is manifested to us only through our suspected faculties. But is not confidence in the trustworthiness of the Universal Power at the heart of the universe, the fundamentalpresuppositionof all human experience, and God thus the basis and end of philosophy and of experience?854.As Locke does. SeeEssay, Bk. IV. ch. 11.855.Cf.Principles of Human Knowledge, sect. 45-48.856.And to be thus external to individual minds.857.It is here that Berkeley differs, for example, from Hume and Comte and J.S. Mill; who accept sense-given phenomena, and assume the constancy of their orderly reappearances,as a matter of fact, while they confess total ignorance of thecauseof natural order. (Thus ignorant, why do they assume reason or order in nature?) The ground of sensible things, which Berkeley refers to Divine Power, Mill expresses by the term“permanent possibilityof sensation.”(See hisExamination of Hamilton, ch. 11.) Our belief in the continued existence of a sensible thingin our absencemerely means, with him, our conviction, derived from custom, that we should perceive it under inexplicable conditions which determine its appearance.858.Cf.Principles, sect. 25, 26.859.Cf. Ibid., sect. 2, 27, 135-142.860.Inasmuch as I am conscious ofmyself, I can gather, through the sense symbolism, the real existence of other minds, external to my own. For I cannot, of course, enter into the very consciousness of another person.861.“reason,”i.e. reasoning or necessary inference—founded here on our sense of personal dependence; not merely on our faith in sense symbolism and the interpretability of the sensible world. Our belief in the existence of finite minds, external to our own, is, with Berkeley, an application of this faith.862.“Matter,”i.e. Matter as abstract substance. Cf.Principles, sect. 135-138.863.Does this imply that with Berkeley,self, as distinguished from thephenomenaof which the material world consists, is not a necessary presuppostion of experience? He says in many places—I amconsciousof“my own being,”and that my mind is myself. Cf.Principles, sect, 2.864.Cf.Principles, sect. 8.865.Cf. Ibid., sect. 20866.This important passage, printed within brackets, is not found in the first and second editions of theDialogues. It is, by anticipation, Berkeley's answer to Hume's application of the objections to the reality of abstract or unperceived Matter, to the reality of the Ego or Self, of which we are aware through memory, as identical amid the changes of its successive states.867.See note 4 on preceding page.868.Cf.Principles, sect. 142.869.Cf. Ibid., sect. 2. Does he assume that he exists when he is not conscious of ideas—sensible or other? Or, does he deny that he is ever unconscious?870.That is of matter supposed to exist independently of any mind. Berkeley speaks here of aconsciousnessof matter. Does he mean consciousness of belief in abstract material Substance?871.Cf.Principles, sect. 54-57.872.Which he does not doubt.873.This sentence expresses the whole question between Berkeley and his antagonists.874.Cf.Principles, sect. 29-41.875.The words within brackets are omitted in the third edition.876.The index pointing to the originative causes in the universe is thus the ethical judgment, which fastens upon the free voluntary agency ofpersons, as absolutely responsible causes, not merely caused causes.877.That only ideas or phenomena are presented to our senses may be assented to by those who nevertheless maintain that intelligent sensuous experience implies more than the sensuous or empirical data.878.Cf.Principles, sect. 49.879.Cf.Principles, sect. 58.880.“without the mind,”i.e. without the mind of each percipient person.881.This is the gist of the whole question. According to the Materialists, sense-presented phenomena are due to unpresented, unperceived, abstract Matter; according to Berkeley, to living Spirit; according to Hume and Agnostics, their origin is unknowable, yet (incoherently) they claim that wecaninterpret them—in physical science.882.A similar objection is urged by Erdmann, in his criticism of Berkeley in theGrundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie.883.Cf.Principles, sect. 50;Siris, sect. 319.884.Cf.Principles, sect. 58.885.“order”—“series,”in first and second editions.886.“Matter,”i.e. when the reality of“matter”is supposed to signify what Berkeley argues cannot be; because really meaningless.887.“the connexion of ideas,”i.e. the physical coexistences and sequences, maintained in constant order by Power external to the individual, and which are disclosed in the natural sciences.888.Cf.Principles, sect. 38. Berkeley is not for making thingssubjective, but for recognising ideas or phenomena presented to the senses asobjective.889.They are not mere illusory appearances but are the very things themselves making their appearance, as far as our limited senses allow them to be realised for us.890.i.e. abstract Matter.891.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 49; andNew Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 9, 10, 15, &c.892.Cf.New Theory of Vision, sect. 84-86.893.“the connexion of ideas,”i.e. the order providentially maintained in nature.894.Cf.Principles, Introduction, sect. 23-25.895.Cf.Principles, sect. 8-10, 86, 87.896.This difficulty is thus pressed by Reid:—“The ideas in my mind cannot be the same with the ideas in any other mind; therefore, if the objects I perceive be only ideas, it is impossible that two or more such minds can perceive the same thing. Thus there is one unconfutable consequence of Berkeley's system, which he seems not to have attended to, and from which it will be found difficult, if at all possible, to guard it. The consequence I mean is this—that, although it leaves us sufficient evidence of a Supreme Mind, it seems to take away all the evidence we have of other intelligent beings like ourselves. What I call a father, or a brother, or a friend, is only a parcel of ideas in my own mind ; they cannot possibly have that relation to another mind which they have to mine, any more than the pain felt by me can be theindividual painfelt by another. I am thus left alone as the only creature of God in the universe”(Hamilton'sReid, pp. 284-285). Implied Solipsism or Panegoism is thus charged against Berkeley, unless his conception of the material world is further guarded.897.Reid and Hamilton argue in like manner against a fundamentally representative sense-perception.898.Cf.Principles, sect. 6.899.Cf. Ibid., sect. 87-90.900.Cf. Ibid., sect. 18.901.Cf.Principles, sect. 24.902.“unknown,”i.e. unrealised in percipient life.903.Cf.Principles, sect. 28-33.904.See also Collier'sClavis Universalis, p. 6:“Two or more persons who are present at a concert of music may indeed in some measure be said to hear thesamenotes; yet the sound which the one hears isnot the very samewith the sound which another hears,because the souls or persons are supposed to be different.”905.Berkeley seems to hold that inthingsthere is no identity other than perfect similarity—only inpersons. And even as to personal identity he is obscure. Cf.Siris, sect. 347, &c.906.But the question is, whether the very ideas or phenomena that are perceived by mecanbe also perceived by other persons; and if not, how I can discover that“other persons”exist, or that any finite person except myself is cognizant of the ideal cosmos—if the sort ofsamenessthat Berkeley advocates is all that can be predicated of concrete ideas; which are thus onlysimilar, or generically the same. Unless the ideas arenumericallythe same, can different persons make signs to one another through them?907.Omitted in author's last edition.908.This seems to imply that intercourse between finite persons is maintained through ideas or phenomena presented to the senses, under a tacit faith in divinely guaranteed correspondence between the phenomena of which I am conscious, and the phenomena of which my neighbour is conscious; so that they arepractically“the same.”If we are living in a fundamentally divine, and therefore absolutely trustworthy, universe, the phenomena presented to my senses, which I attribute to the agency of another person, are so attributed rightly. For if not, the so-called cosmos is adapted to mislead me.909.This explanation is often overlooked by Berkeley's critics.910.Cf.Principles, sect. 82-84.911.i.e. if you take the termideain its wholly subjective and popular meaning.912.i.e. if you take the termideain its objective meaning.913.“philosophic,”i.e.pseudo-philosophic, against which he argues.914.Had this their relative existence—this realisation of the material world through finite percipient and volitional life—any beginning? May not God have been eternally presenting phenomena to the senses of percipient beings in cosmical order, if not on this planet yet elsewhere, perhaps under other conditions? Has there been any beginning in the succession of finite persons?915.In the first and second editions only.916.Is“creation”by us distinguishable from continuous evolution, unbeginning and unending, in divinely constituted order; and is there a distinction between creation or evolution ofthingsand creation or evolution ofpersons?917.Cf.Siris, sect. 347-349.918.“Matter,”i.e. Matter in this pseudo-philosophical meaning of the word.919.Thus Origen in the early Church. That“Matter”is co-eternal with God would mean that God is eternally making things real in the percipient experience of persons.920.Cf.Principles, sect. 85-156, in which the religious and scientific advantages of the new conception of matter and the material cosmos are illustrated, when it is rightly understood and applied.921.“substance and accident”—“subjects and adjuncts,”—in the first and the second edition.922.Cf.Principles, sect. 28-42. InSiris, sect. 294-297, 300-318, 335, 359-365, we have glimpses of thought more allied to Platonism, if not to Hegelianism.923.“Matter,”i.e. matter unrealised in any mind, finite or Divine.924.These two propositions are a summary of Berkeley's conception of the material world. With him, theimmediateobjects of sense, realise inperception, are independent of thewillof the percipient, and are thus external to his proper personality. Berkeley's“material world”of enlightened Common Sense, resulting from two factors, Divine and human, is independent of each finite mind; but not independent of all living Mind.925.“voces male intellectæ.”Cf.Principles of Human Knowledge,“Introduction,”sect. 6, 23-25, on the abuse of language, especially by abstraction.926.“veterum philosophorum.”The history of ancient speculations about motion, from the paradoxes of Zeno downwards, is, in some sort, a history of ancient metaphysics. It involves Space, Time, and the material world, with the ultimate causal relation of Nature to Spirit.927.“hujus ævi philosophos.”As in Bacon on motion, and in the questions raised by Newton, Borelli, Leibniz, and others, discussed in the following sections.928.Sect. 3-42 are concerned with the principle of Causality, exemplified in the motion, or change of place and state, that is continually going on in the material world, and which was supposed by some to explain all the phenomena of the universe.929.“vis.”The assumption thatactive poweris an immediate datum of sense is the example here offered of the abase of abstract words. He proceeds to dissolve the assumption by shewing that it is meaningless.930.“principio”—the ultimate explanation or originating cause. Cf. sect. 36. Metaphors, or indeed empty words, are accepted for explanations, it is argued, whenbodilypower or force, in any form, e.g. gravitation, is taken as the real cause of motion. To call these“occult causes”is to say nothing that is intelligible. The perceived sensible effects and their customary sequences are all we know. Physicists are still deluded by words and metaphors.931.Cf. sect. 53, wheresense,imagination, andintelligenceare distinguished.932.Cf.Principles, Introd. 16, 20, 21; alsoAlciphron, Dial. VII. sect. 8, 17.933.[La Materia altro non è che un vaso di Circe incantato, il quale serve per ricettacolo della forza et de' momenti dell' impeto. La forzae l'impeti sono astratti tanto sottili, sono quintessenze tanto spiritose, che in altre ampolle non si possono racchiudere, fuor che nell' intima corpulenza de' solidi naturali, VideLezioni Accademiche.]—Author.Torricelli (1608-47), the eminent Italian physicist, and professor of mathematics at Florence, who invented the barometer.934.Borelli (1608-79), Italian professor of mathematics at Pisa, and then of medicine at Florence; see hisDe Vi Percussionis, cap. XXIV. prop. 88, and cap. XXVII.935.“per effectum,”i.e. by its sensible effects—real power or active force not being a datum of the senses, but found in the spiritual efficacy, of which we have an example in our personal agency.936.“vim mortuam.”The only power we can find is the living power of Mind. Reason is perpetually active in the universe, imperceptible through the senses, and revealed tothemonly in its sensible effects.“Power,”e.g.“gravitation,”in things,per se, is distinguished from perceived“motion”only through illusion due to misleading abstraction. There is nophysicalpower, intermediate between spiritual agency, on the one hand, and the sensible changes we see, on the other. Cf. sect. 11.937.“meditatione subigenda sunt.”Cf.Theory of Vision Vindicated, sect. 35, 70.938.“distingui.”It is here argued that so-called power within the things of sense is not distinguishable from the sensibly perceived sequences. To the meaningless supposition that it is, he attributes the frivolous verbal controversies among the learned mentioned in the following section. The province of natural philosophy, according to Berkeley, is to inquire what the rules are under which sensible effects are uniformly manifested. Cf.Siris, sect. 236, 247, 249.939.Principia Math.Def. III.940.De Vi Percussionis, cap. I.941.“utiles.”Such words as“force,”“power,”“gravity,”“attraction,”are held to be convenient in physical reasonings about thephenomenaof motion, but worthless as philosophical expressions of thecauseof motion, which transcends sense and mechanical science. Cf.Siris, sect. 234, 235.942.Cf. sect. 67.943.“candem.”So in recent discussions on the conservation of force.944.[Borellus.]—Author.SeeDe Vi Percussionis, cap. XXIII.945.[Leibnitius.]—Author.946.On Berkeley's reasoning all terms which involve the assumption that real causality is something presentable to the senses are a cover for meaninglessness. Only through self-conscious experience of personal activity does real meaning enter into the portion of language which deals with active causation. This is argued in detail in sect. 21-35.947.Our concrete experience is assumed to be confined to (a)bodies, i.e. the data of the senses, and (b)mindorspirit—sentient, intelligent, active—revealed by internal consciousness. Cf.Principles, sect. 1, 2, in which experience is resolved intoideasand theactive intelligencewhich they presuppose. Here the word idea disappears, but, in accordance with its signification,“bodies”is still regarded as aggregates of external phenomena, the passive subjects of changes of place and state: the idealisation of the material world is tacitly implied, but not obtruded.948.“nihilque,”&c. Cf.Principles of Human Knowledge, e.g. sect. 26, 65, 66. where the essential passivity of theideaspresented to the senses, i.e. the material world, is maintained as a cardinal principle—on the positive ground of our percipient experience of sensible things. To speak of the cause of motion assomething sensible, he argues (sect. 24), is merely to shew that we know nothing about it. Cf. sect. 28, 29, infra.949.The phenomena that can be presented to the senses are taken as the measure of what can be attributed to the material world; and as the senses presentonlyconditioned change of place in bodies, we must look for the active cause in the invisible world which internal consciousness presents to us.950.“genus rerum cogitantium.”Cf.Principles, sect. 2.951.“experientia didicimus.”Can the merely empirical data even of internal consciousness reveal this causal connexion between volition and bodily motions, without the venture of theistic faith?952.“a primo et universali Principio”i.e. God, or the Universal Spirit, in whom the universe of bodies and spirits finds explanation; in a way which Berkeley does not attempt to unfold articulately and exhaustively in philosophical system.953.Phys.θ. 4. 255 a 5-7.954.Princip. Math.Def. III.955.“resistentia.”Our muscularsensationof resistance is apt to be accepted empirically as itselfactive power in the concrete, entering very much, as has been said, into the often inaccurate idea of power which is formed. See Editor's Preface.956.“nec incommode.”Cf. sect. 17, and note.957.“hypothesis mathematica.”Cf. sect. 17, 35, 36-41, 66, 67; alsoSiris, sect. 250-251.958.“nihil.”This section sums up Berkeley's objections to creditingmatterwith real power; the senses being taken as the test of what is contained in matter. It may be compared with David Hume, Thomas Brown, and J.S. Mill on Causation. Berkeley differs from them in recognising active power in spirit, while with them he resolves causation among bodies into invariable sequence.959.Can the data presented to us reveal more than sequence, in the relation between our volitions and the corresponding movements of our bodies? Is not the difference found in the moral presupposition, whichsupernaturalisesman in his voluntary or morally responsible activity? This obliges us to seeourselvesas absolutely original causes of all bodily and mental states for which we can be morally approved or blamed.960.“novumque genus.”Cf. sect. 21. We have here Berkeley's antithesis of mind and matter—spirits and external phenomena presented to the senses—persons in contrast to passive ideas.961.De Anima, I. ii. 13, 22, 24.962.“Cartesius.”The antithesis of extended things and thinking things pervades Descartes; but not, as with Berkeley, on the foundation of the new conception of what is truly meant by matter or sensible things. See e.g.Principia, P. I. §§ 63, 64.963.“alii.”Does he refer to Locke, who suggests the possibility of matter thinking?964.See Aristotle,De Anima, I. ii. 5, 13; Diogenes Laertius, Lib. VI. i. 6.965.Nat. Ausc.VIII. 15; alsoDe Anima, III, x. 7.966.Hardly any passage in theTimæusexactly corresponds to this. The following is, perhaps, the most pertinent:—Κίνησιν γὰρ ἀπένειμεν αὐτῷ τὴν τοῦ σώματος οἰκείαν, τῶν ἑπτὰ τὴν περὶ νοῦν καὶ φρόνησιν μάλιστα οὖσαν (p. 34 a). Aristotle quotes theTimæusin the same connexion,De Anima, I. iii. ii.967.“philosophi Cartesiani.”Secundum Cartesium causa generalis omnium motuum et quietum est Deus.—Derodon,Physica, I. ix. 30.968.Principia Mathematica—Scholium Generale.969.“naturam naturantem esse Deum”—as we might say, God considered as imminent cause in the universe. See St. Thomas Aquinas,Opera, vol. XXII. Quest. 6, p. 27.970.“juxta certam et constantem rationem.”While all changes in Nature are determined by Will, it is not capricious but rational Will. The so-called arbitrariness of the Language of Nature is relative to us, and from our point of view. In itself, the universe of reality expresses Perfect Reason.971.“permaneret.”Cf. sect. 51.972.“spectat potius ad philosophiam primam.”The drift of theDe Motuis to distinguish the physical sequences of molecular motion, which the physical sciences articulate, from the Power with which metaphysics and theology are concerned, and which we approach through consciousness.973.“regulas.”Cf.Siris, sect. 231-235.974.Having, in the preceding sections, contrasted perceived motions and their immanent originating Power—matter and mind—physics and metaphysics—he proceeds in this and the seven following sections to explain more fully what ha means byprincipiumand also the two meanings (metaphysical and mechanical) ofsolutio. Byprincipium, in philosophy, he understands universally efficient supersensible Power. In natural philosophy the term is applied to the orderly sequences manifested to our senses, not to the active cause of the order.975.“ratiocinio ... redditæ universales.”Relations of the data of sense to universalising reason are here recognised.976.“natura motus.”Sect. 43-66 treat of the nature of theeffect—i.e. perceptible motion, as distinguished from its true causal origin (principium) in mind or spirit. The origin of motion belongs to metaphysics; its nature, as dependent on percipient experience, belongs to physics. Is motion independent of a plurality of bodies; or does it involve bodies in relation to other bodies, so that absolute motion is meaningless? Cf.Principles, sect. 111-116.977.“idea illa tenuissima et subtilissima.”The difficulty as to definition of motion is attributed to abstractions, and the inclination of the scholastic mind to prefer these to concrete experience.978.Motion is thus defined by Aristotle:—Διὸ ἡ κίνησις ἐντελέχεια τοῦ κινητοῦ, ᾗ κινητόν. Nat. Ausc. III. ii; see also i. and iii. Cf. Derodon,Physica, I. ix.979.Newton.980.Cf. sect. 3-42.981.Descartes,Principia, P. II. § 25; also Borellus,De Vi Percussionis, p. 1.982.“res faciles difficillimas.”Cf.Principles,“Introduction,”sect. 1.983.Καὶ διὰ τοῦτο δὴ χαλεπὸν αὐτὴν λαβεῖν τί ἐστίν.Nat. Ausc.III. ii.984.e.g. Zeno, in his noted argument against the possibility of motion, referred to as a signal example of fallacy.985.“de infinite, &c.”Cf.Principles, sect. 130-132, and theAnalystpassim, for Berkeley's treatment of infinitesimals.986.“confundere.”Cf. sect. 3-42 for illustrations of this confusion.987.The modern conception of the“conservation of force.”988.Aristotle states the question inNat. Ausc.VIII. cap. i, and solves it in cap. iv.989.“mutatio loci”is the effect, i.e. motion perceived by sense;“vitale principium”the real cause, i.e. vital rational agency.990.“moventis et moti,”i.e. as concauses.991.“motum localem.”Sect. 52-65 discuss the reality of absolute or empty space, in contrast with concrete space realised in perception of the local relations of bodies. The meaninglessness of absolute space and motion is argued. Cf.Principles, sect. 116, 117. See Locke'sEssay, Bk. II. ch. 13, 15, 17; alsoPapers which passed between Mr. Leibnitz and Dr. Clarke in 1715-16, pp. 55-59; 73-81; 97-103, &c. Leibniz calls absolute space“an ideal of some modern Englishman.”992.Newton'sPrincipia, Def. Sch. III. See also Derodon,Physica, P. I. cap. vi. § 1.993.Cf. Locke on a vacuum, and the“possibility of space existing without matter,”Essay, Bk. II. ch. 13.994.Note the account here given ofimaginationandintellect, as distinguished fromsense, which may be compared with αἴσθησις, φαντασία, and νοῦς in Aristotelian psychology.995.“attributorum divinorum particeps.”See Samuel Clarke, in hisDemonstration, and in thePapers between Clarke and Leibnitz.996.“nostrum,”sc. corpus. When we imagine space emptied of bodies, we are apt to forget that our own bodies are part of the material world.997.[Vide quæ contra spatium absolutum disseruntur in libroDe Principiis Cognitionis Humanæ, idiomate anglicano decem abhine annis edito.]—Author.He refers to sect. 116 of thePrinciples.998.He treats absolute space as nothing, and relative space as dependent on Perception and Will.999.Phys.α. 5. 188a. 22, 23.1000.See Locke,Essay, Bk. II. ch. 13, §§ 7-10.1001.Sect. 67-72 treat of the supposed ejection of motion from the striking body into the body struck. Is this only metaphorical? Is the motion received by the latter to be supposed identical with, or equivalent to, that given forth by the former?1002.Principia, Def. IV.1003.Lezioni Accademiche.1004.De Vi Percussionis, cap. IX.1005.Newton's third law of motion.1006.Berkeley sees in motion only a link in the chain which connects the sensible and intelligible worlds—a conception unfolded in hisSiris, more than twenty years later.1007.“provincia sua.”TheDe Motu, so far as it treats of motion perceptible to the senses, is assigned to physics; in contrast to theology or metaphysics, alone concerned with active causation.
Pope's poetic tribute to Berkeley belongs to this period—
“Even in a bishop I can spy desert;Secker is decent; Rundle has a heart:Manners with candour are to Benson given,To Berkeley—every virtue under heaven.”
Epilogue to the Satires.
Also his satirical tribute to the critics of Berkeley—
“Truth's sacred fort th' exploded laugh shall win;And Coxcombs vanquish Berkeley with a grin.”
Essay on Satire,Part II.
That Berkeley was buried in Oxford is mentioned in his son's letter to Johnson, in which he says :“His remains are interred in the Cathedral of Christ Church, and next week a monument to his memory will be erected with an inscription by Dr. Markham, a Student of this College.”As the son was present at, and superintended the arrangements for his father's funeral, it can be no stretch of credulity to believe that he knew where his father was buried. It may be added that Berkeley himself had provided in his Will“that my body be buried in the churchyard of the parish in which I die.”The Will, dated July 31, 1752, is givenin extensoin myLife and Lettersof Berkeley, p. 345. We have also the record of burial in the Register of Christ Church Cathedral, which shews that“on January ye 20th1753, ye Right Reverend John (sic) Berkley, LdBishop of Cloyne, was buryed”there. This disposes of the statement on p. 17 of Diprose'sAccount of the Parish of Saint Clement Danes(1868), that Berkeley was buried in that church.
I may add that a beautiful memorial of Berkeley has lately been placed in the Cathedral of Cloyne, by subscriptions in this country and largely in America.
Sir A. Grant, (Ethics of Aristotle, vol. II. p. 172) remarks, as to the doctrine that the Common Sensibles are apprehended concomitantly by the senses, that:“this is surely the true view; we see in the apprehension of number, figure, and the like, not an operation of sense, but the mind putting its own forms and categories, i.e. itself, on the external object. It would follow then that the senses cannot really be separated from the mind; the senses and the mind each contribute an element to every knowledge. Aristotle's doctrine of κοινὴ αἴσθησις would go far, if carried out, to modify his doctrine of the simple and innate character of the senses, e.g. sight (cf.Eth.II. 1, 4), and would prevent its collision with Berkeley'sTheory of Vision.”—See also Sir W. Hamilton,Reid's Works, pp. 828-830.
Dugald Stewart (Collected Works, vol. I. p. 341, note) quotes Aristotle'sEthics, II. 1, as evidence that Berkeley's doctrine,“with respect to the acquired perceptions of sight, was quite unknown to the best metaphysicians of antiquity.”
The rough draft of the Introduction, prepared two years before the publication of thePrinciples(see Appendix, vol. III), should be compared with the published version. He there tells that“there was a time when, being bantered and abused by words,”he“did not in the least doubt”that he was“able to abstract his ideas”; adding that“after a strict survey of my abilities, I not only discovered my own deficiency on this point, but also cannot conceive it possible that such a power should be even in the most perfect and exalted understanding.”What he thus pronounces“impossible,”is asensuousperception or imagination of an intellectual relation, as to which most thinkers would agree with him. But in so arguing, he seems apt to discard the intellectual relations themselves that are necessarily embodied in experience.
David Hume refers thus to Berkeley's doctrine about“abstract ideas”:—“A great philosopher has asserted that all general ideas are nothing but particular ones annexed to a certain term, which gives them a more extensive signification. I look upon this to be one of the greatest and most valuable discoveries that has been made of late years in the republic of letters.”(Treatise of H. N.Pt. I, sect. 7.)
Simultaneous perception of the“same”(similar?)sense-ideas,by different persons, as distinguished from purely individual consciousness of feelings and fancies, is here taken as a test of thevirtually external realityof the former.
Berkeley does not ask whether the change of the rod into a serpent, or of the water into wine, is the issue of divine agency and order, otherwise than as all natural evolution is divinely providential.
The following is the translator's Prefatory Note, on the objects of theDialogues,and in explanation of the three illustrative vignettes:—
“L'Auteur expose dans le premier Dialogue le sentiment du Vulgaire et celui des Philosophes, sur les qualités secondaires et premieres, la nature et l'existence des corps; et il prétend prouver en même tems l'insuffisance de l'un et de l'autre. La Vignette qu'on voit à la téte du Dialogue, fait allusion à cet objet. Elle représente un Philosophe dans son cabinet, lequel est distrait de son travail par un enfant qu'il appercoit se voyant lui-méme dans un miroir, en tendant les mains pour embrasser sa propre image. Le Philosophe rit de l'erreur où il croit que tombe l'enfant; tandis qu'on lui applique à lui-même ces mots tirés d'Horace:
Quid rides?....de teFabula narratur.
“Le second Dialogue est employé à exposer le sentiment de l'Auteur sur le même sujet, sçavoir, que les choses corporelles ont une existence réelle dans les esprits qui les apperçoivent; mais qu'elles ne sçauroient exister hors de tous les esprits à la fois, même de l'esprit infini de Dieu; et que par conséquent la Matière, prise suivant l'acception ordinaire du mot, non seulement n'existe point, mais seroit même absolument impossible. On a taché de représenter aux yeux ce sentiment dans la Vignette du Dialogue. Le mot grec νοῦς qui signifieâme, désigne l'àme: les rayons qui en partent marquent l'attention que l'âme donne à des idées ou objets; les tableaux qu'on a placés aux seuls endroits où les rayons aboutissent, et dont les sujets sont tirés de la description des beautés de la nature, qui se trouve dans le livre, représentent les idées ou objets que l'âme considère, pas le secours des facultes qu'elle a reçues de Dieu; et l'action de l'Étre suprème sur l'âme est figurée par un trait, qui, partant d'un triangle, symbole de la Divinité, et perçant les nuages dont le triangle est environné. s'étend jusqu'à l'âme pour la vivifier; enfin, on a fait en sorte de rendre le même sentiment par ces mots:
Quæ noscere cumque Deus det,Esse puta.
“L'objet du troisième Dialogue est de répondre aux difficultés auxquelles le sentiment qu'on a établi dans les Dialogues précédens, peut être sujet, de l'éclaircir en cette sorte de plus, d'en développer toutes les heureuses conséquences, enfin de faire voir, qu'étant bien entendu, il revient aux notions les plus communes. Et comme l'Auteur exprime à la fin du livre cette dernière pensée, en comparant ce qu'il vient de dire, à l'eau que les deux Interlocuteurs sont supposés voir jaillir d'un jet, et qu'il remarque que la même force de la gravité fait élever jusqu'à une certaine hauteur et retomber ensuite dans le bassin d'où elle étoit d'abord partie; on a pris cet emblême pour le sujet de la Vignette de ce Dialogue; on a représenté en conséquence dans cette dernière Vignette les deux Interlocuteurs, se promenant dans le lieu où l'Auteur les suppose, et s'entretenant là-dessus, et pour donner au Lecteur l'explication de l'emblême, on a mis au bas le vers suivant:
Urget aquas vis sursum, eadem flectitque deorsum.”